HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

Yogachara (, IAST: ') is an influential tradition of Buddhist philosophy and psychology emphasizing the study of
cognition Cognition is the "mental action or process of acquiring knowledge and understanding through thought, experience, and the senses". It encompasses all aspects of intellectual functions and processes such as: perception, attention, thought, ...
,
perception Perception () is the organization, identification, and interpretation of sensory information in order to represent and understand the presented information or environment. All perception involves signals that go through the nervous syste ...
, and
consciousness Consciousness, at its simplest, is awareness of a state or object, either internal to oneself or in one's external environment. However, its nature has led to millennia of analyses, explanations, and debate among philosophers, scientists, an ...
through the interior lens of meditation, as well as philosophical reasoning (hetuvidyā). Yogachara was one of the two most influential traditions of Mahayana Buddhism in India, along with
Madhyamaka Madhyamaka ("middle way" or "centrism"; ; ; Tibetic languages, Tibetan: དབུ་མ་པ་ ; ''dbu ma pa''), otherwise known as Śūnyavāda ("the Śūnyatā, emptiness doctrine") and Niḥsvabhāvavāda ("the no Svabhava, ''svabhāva'' d ...
. The compound ''Yogācāra'' literally means "practice of
yoga Yoga (UK: , US: ; 'yoga' ; ) is a group of physical, mental, and spiritual practices or disciplines that originated with its own philosophy in ancient India, aimed at controlling body and mind to attain various salvation goals, as pra ...
", or "one whose practice is yoga", hence the name of the school is literally "the school of the yogins". Yogācāra was also variously termed ''Vijñānavāda'' (the doctrine of consciousness), ''Vijñaptivāda'' (the doctrine of
idea In philosophy and in common usage, an idea (from the Greek word: ἰδέα (idea), meaning 'a form, or a pattern') is the results of thought. Also in philosophy, ideas can also be mental representational images of some object. Many philosophe ...
s or percepts) or ''Vijñaptimātratā-vāda'' (the doctrine of 'mere representation'), which is also the name given to its major theory of mind which seeks to deconstruct how we perceive the world. There are several interpretations of this main theory: various forms of
Idealism Idealism in philosophy, also known as philosophical realism or metaphysical idealism, is the set of metaphysics, metaphysical perspectives asserting that, most fundamentally, reality is equivalent to mind, Spirit (vital essence), spirit, or ...
, as well as a phenomenology or representationalism. Aside from this, Yogācāra also developed an elaborate analysis of consciousness ( vijñana) and mental phenomena ( dharmas), as well as an extensive system of Buddhist spiritual practice, i.e. yoga. The movement has been traced to the first centuries of the common era and seems to have developed as some yogis of the Sarvāstivāda and Sautrāntika traditions in north India adopted Mahayana Buddhism. The brothers Asaṅga and Vasubandhu (both c. 4-5th century CE), are considered the classic philosophers and systematizers of this school, along with the figure of
Maitreya Maitreya (Sanskrit) or Metteyya (Pali), is a bodhisattva who is regarded as the future Buddhahood, Buddha of this world in all schools of Buddhism, prophesied to become Maitreya Buddha or Metteyya Buddha.Williams, Paul. ''Mahayana Buddhism: Th ...
.Siderits, Mark, ''Buddhism as philosophy'', 2017, p. 146. Yogācāra was later imported to
Tibet Tibet (; ''Böd''; ), or Greater Tibet, is a region in the western part of East Asia, covering much of the Tibetan Plateau and spanning about . It is the homeland of the Tibetan people. Also resident on the plateau are other ethnic groups s ...
and
East Asia East Asia is a geocultural region of Asia. It includes China, Japan, Mongolia, North Korea, South Korea, and Taiwan, plus two special administrative regions of China, Hong Kong and Macau. The economies of Economy of China, China, Economy of Ja ...
by figures like Shantaraksita (8th century) and
Xuanzang Xuanzang (; ; 6 April 6025 February 664), born Chen Hui or Chen Yi (), also known by his Sanskrit Dharma name Mokṣadeva, was a 7th-century Chinese Bhikkhu, Buddhist monk, scholar, traveller, and translator. He is known for the epoch-making ...
(7th-century). Today, Yogācāra ideas and texts continue to be influential subjects of study for
Tibetan Buddhism Tibetan Buddhism is a form of Buddhism practiced in Tibet, Bhutan and Mongolia. It also has a sizable number of adherents in the areas surrounding the Himalayas, including the Indian regions of Ladakh, Gorkhaland Territorial Administration, D ...
and East Asian Buddhism.


Doctrine

Yogācāra philosophy is primarily meant to aid in the practice of
yoga Yoga (UK: , US: ; 'yoga' ; ) is a group of physical, mental, and spiritual practices or disciplines that originated with its own philosophy in ancient India, aimed at controlling body and mind to attain various salvation goals, as pra ...
and meditation and thus it also sets forth a systematic analysis of the
Mahayana Mahāyāna ( ; , , ; ) is a term for a broad group of Buddhist traditions, Buddhist texts#Mahāyāna texts, texts, Buddhist philosophy, philosophies, and practices developed in ancient India ( onwards). It is considered one of the three main ex ...
path of mental training (see five paths ''pañcamārga''). Yogācārins made use of ideas from previous traditions, such as Prajñāpāramitā and the Sarvāstivāda Abhidharma tradition, to develop a novel analysis of conscious experience and a corresponding schema for Mahāyāna spiritual practice. Yogācāra sutras such as the '' Saṅdhinirmocana Sūtra'' developed various core concepts such as ''vijñapti-mātra'', the ''ālaya-vijñāna'' (store consciousness), the turning of the basis (''āśraya-parāvṛtti),'' the three natures ('' trisvabhāva''), and emptiness. These form a complex system, and each can be taken as a point of departure for understanding Yogācāra.Muller, A. Charles (2005; 2007). ''Wonhyo's Reliance on Huiyuan in his Exposition of the Two Hindrances.'' (Published in Reflecting Mirrors: Perspectives on Huayan Buddhism. Imre Hamar, ed., Harrassowitz Verlag, 2007, p. 281-295.) Source

(accessed: April 7, 2010)


The doctrine of ''vijñapti-mātra''

One of the main features of Yogācāra philosophy is the concept of ''vijñapti-mātra''. It is often used interchangeably with the term ''citta-mātra'' in modern and ancient Yogacara sources.Gold, Jonathan C., "Vasubandhu", ''The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' (Summer 2018 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/vasubandhu/ The standard translation of both terms is "consciousness-only" or "mind-only." Several modern researchers object to this translation in favor of alternative like ''representation-only''. The meaning of this term is at the heart of the modern scholarly disagreement about whether
Yogacara Yogachara (, IAST: ') is an influential tradition of Buddhist philosophy and psychology emphasizing the study of cognition, perception, and consciousness through the interior lens of meditation, as well as philosophical reasoning (hetuvidyā). ...
Buddhism can be said to be a form of idealism (as supported by Garfield, Hopkins, and others) or whether it is definitely not idealist (Anacker, Lusthaus, Wayman).


Origins

According to Lambert Schmithausen, the earliest surviving appearance of this term is in chapter 8 of the '' Saṅdhinirmocana Sūtra,'' which has only survived in Tibetan and Chinese translations that differ in syntax and meaning. The passage is depicted as a response by the Buddha to a question which asks "whether the images or replicas (''*pratibimba'') which are the object (''*gocara'') of meditative concentration (*''samadhi''), are different/separate (''*bhinna'') from the contemplating mind (''*citta'') or not." The Buddha says they are not different, "Because these images are ''vijñapti-mātra."'' The text goes on to affirm that the same is true for objects of ordinary perception. The term is sometimes used as a synonym with ''citta-mātra'' (mere '' citta''), which is also used as a name for the school that suggests
Idealism Idealism in philosophy, also known as philosophical realism or metaphysical idealism, is the set of metaphysics, metaphysical perspectives asserting that, most fundamentally, reality is equivalent to mind, Spirit (vital essence), spirit, or ...
. Schmithausen writes that the first appearance of this term is in the ''Pratyupanna samadhi sutra'', which states "this (or: whatever belongs to this) triple world is nothing but mind (or thought: *''cittamatra''). Why? Because however I imagine things, that is how they appear." Regarding existing
Sanskrit Sanskrit (; stem form ; nominal singular , ,) is a classical language belonging to the Indo-Aryan languages, Indo-Aryan branch of the Indo-European languages. It arose in northwest South Asia after its predecessor languages had Trans-cultural ...
sources, the term appears in the first verse of Vasubandhu's ''Vimśatikā'' (''Twenty Verses''), which states:Siderits, Mark, ''Buddhism as philosophy'', 2017, p. 149.
This orldis ''vijñaptimātra'', since it manifests itself as an unreal object (''artha''), just like the case of those with cataracts seeing unreal hairs in the moon and the like (''vijñaptimātram evaitad asad arthāvabhāsanāt yathā taimirikasyāsat keśa candrādi darśanam'').
According to Mark Siderits, what Vasubandhu means here is that we are only ever aware of mental images or impressions which manifest themselves as external objects, but "there is actually no such thing outside the mind." The term also appears in Asaṅga's classic work, the '' Mahāyānasaṃgraha'' (no Sanskrit original, trans. from Tibetan)'':''
These representations (''vijñapti'') are mere representations (''vijñapti-mātra''), because there is no orrespondingthing/object (''artha'')...Just as in a dream there appear, even without a thing/object (''artha''), just in the mind alone, forms/images of all kinds of things/objects like visibles, sounds, smells, tastes, tangibles, houses, forests, land, and mountains, and yet there are no uchthings/objects at all in that lace ''MSg II.6''
Another classic statement of the doctrine appears in Dharmakīrti's ''Pramānaṿārttika'' (''Commentary on Epistemology'') which states: "cognition experiences itself, and nothing else whatsoever. Even the particular objects of perception, are by nature just consciousness itself."


Interpretations of ''vijñapti-mātra''


Idealism

According to Bruce Cameron Hall, the interpretation of this doctrine as a form of subjective or absolute idealism has been "the most common 'outside' interpretation of ''Vijñānavāda'', not only by modern writers, but by its ancient opponents, both Hindu and Buddhist."Cameron Hall, Bruce, ''The Meaning of Vijnapti in Vasubandhu's Concept of Mind,'' JIABS Vol 9, 1986, Number 1, p. 7. Scholars such as Jay Garfield, Saam Trivedi, Nobuyoshi Yamabe, Paul Williams, and Sean Butler argue that Yogācāra is similar to Idealism (and they compare it to the idealisms of Kant and Berkeley), though they note that it is its own unique form and that it might be confusing to categorize it as such. The German scholar and philologist Lambert Schmithausen affirms that Yogācāra sources teach a type of idealism which is supposed to be a middle way between Abhidharma realism and what it often considered a nihilistic position which only affirms emptiness as the ultimate. Schmithausen notes that philological study of Yogācāra texts shows that they clearly reject the independent existence of mind and the external world.Schmithausen, Lambert (2005). On the Problem of the External World in the Ch’eng wei shih lun. Tōkyō: The International Institute for Buddhist Studies. The International Institute for Buddhist Studies. He also notes that the current trend in rejecting the idealistic interpretation might be related to the unpopularity of idealism among Western academics. Florin Deleanu likewise affirms the idealist nature of Yogācāra texts, while also underscoring how Yogācāra retains a strong orientation to a soteriology which aims at contemplative realization of an ultimate reality that is an ‘inexpressible essence’ (''nirabhilāpyasvabhāva'') beyond any subject-object duality. Similarly, Jonathan Gold writes that the Yogācāra thinker Vasubandhu can be said to be an idealist (similar to Kant), in the sense that for him, everything in experience as well as its causal support is mental, and thus he gives causal priority to the mental. At the same time however, this is only in the conventional realm, since "mind" is just another concept and true reality for Vasubandhu is ineffable, "an inconceivable 'thusness' ('' tathatā'')." Indeed, the ''Vimśatikā'' states that the very idea of ''vijñapti-mātra'' must ''also'' be understood to be itself a self-less construction and thus ''vijñapti-mātra'' is not the ultimate truth ('' paramārtha-satya'') in Yogācāra. Thus according to Gold, while Vasubandhu's ''vijñapti-mātra'' can be said to be a “conventionalist idealism”, it is to be seen as unique and different from Western forms, especially Hegelian Absolute Idealism.


Mere representation

The interpretation of Yogācāra as a type of
idealism Idealism in philosophy, also known as philosophical realism or metaphysical idealism, is the set of metaphysics, metaphysical perspectives asserting that, most fundamentally, reality is equivalent to mind, Spirit (vital essence), spirit, or ...
was standard until recently, when it began to be challenged by scholars such as Kochumuttom, Anacker, Kalupahana, Dunne, Lusthaus, Powers, and Wayman.Garfield, Jay L. (2002). ''Empty words: Buddhist philosophy and cross-cultural interpretation'' ( nline-Ausg. ed.). New York: Oxford University Press. . Some scholars like David Kalupahana argue that it is a mistake to conflate the terms ''citta-mātra'' (which is sometimes seen as a different, more metaphysical position) with ''vijñapti-mātra'' (which need not be idealist). However, Deleanu points out that Vasubandhu clearly states in his ''Twenty Verses'' and ''Abhidharmakosha'' that ''vijñapti'' and '' citta'' are synonymous. Nevertheless, different alternative translations for ''vijñapti-mātra'' have been proposed, such as ''representation-only, ideation-only, impressions-only'' and ''perception-only''.Wayman, Alex, ''A Defense of Yogācāra Buddhism'', Philosophy East and West, Vol. 46, No. 4 (Oct., 1996), pp. 447-476. Alex Wayman notes that one's interpretation of Yogācāra will depend on how the qualifier ''mātra'' is to be understood in this context, and he objects to interpretations which claim that Yogācāra rejects the external world altogether, preferring translations such as "amounting to mind" or "mirroring mind" for ''citta-mātra''. For Wayman, what this doctrine means is that "the mind has only a report or representation of what the sense organ had sensed." The representationalist interpretation is also supported by Stefan Anacker. According to Thomas Kochumuttom, Yogācāra is a ''realistic pluralism'' which does not deny the existence of individual beings. Kochumuttom argues that Yogācāra is not idealism since it denies that absolute reality is a consciousness, that individual beings are transformations or illusory appearances of an absolute consciousness. Thus, for Kochumuttom, ''vijñapti-mātra'' means "mere representation of consciousness," a view which states "that the world ''as it appears'' to the unenlightened ones is mere representation of consciousness". Furthermore, according to Kochumuttom, in Yogācāra "the absolute state is defined simply as emptiness, namely the emptiness of subject-object distinction. Once thus defined as emptiness (''sunyata''), it receives a number of synonyms, none of which betray idealism."


Soteriological phenomenology

According to Dan Lusthaus, the ''vijñapti-mātra'' theory is closer in some ways to Western Phenomenological theories and Epistemological Idealism. However, it is not a form of metaphysical idealism because Yogācāra rejects the construction of any type of
metaphysical Metaphysics is the branch of philosophy that examines the basic structure of reality. It is traditionally seen as the study of mind-independent features of the world, but some theorists view it as an inquiry into the conceptual framework of h ...
or ontological theories. Moreover, Western idealism lacks any counterpart to karma, samsara or awakening, all of which are central for Yogācāra. Regarding ''vijñapti-mātra,'' Lusthaus translates it as "nothing but conscious construction" and states it is a kind of trick built into consciousness which "projects and constructs a cognitive object in such a way that it disowns its own creation - pretending the object is "out there" - in order to render that object capable of being appropriated." This reification of cognition aids in constructing the notion of a permanent and independent self, which is believed to appropriate and possess external 'things'. Yogācāra offers an analysis and meditative means to negate this reification, thereby also negating the notion of a solid self. According to Lusthaus, this analysis is not a rejection of external phenomena, and it does not grant foundational or transcendent status to consciousness. In this interpretation, instead of offering an ontological theory, Yogācāra focuses on understanding and eliminating the underlying tendencies (''anuśaya'') that lead to clinging concepts and theories, which are just cognitive projections (''pratibimba'', ''parikalpita''). Thus, for Lusthaus, the orientation of the Yogācāra school is largely consistent with the thinking of the Pāli nikāyas and seeks to realign Mahayana with early Buddhist theory.


Arguments for consciousness-only

According to the contemporary philosopher Jan Westerhoff, Yogācāra philosophers came up with various arguments in defense of the consciousness-only view. He outlines three main arguments: the explanatory equivalence argument, the causation-resemblance argument, and the constant co-cognition argument.


Explanatory equivalence argument

This argument is found in Vasubandhu's ''Vimśatikā'' (''Twenty Verses'') and is an
inference to the best explanation Abductive reasoning (also called abduction,For example: abductive inference, or retroduction) is a form of logical inference that seeks the simplest and most likely conclusion from a set of observations. It was formulated and advanced by Ameri ...
. It argues that consciousness-only can provide an account of the various features of experience which are explained by the existence of mind-independent material objects. This is coupled with a principle of ontological parsimony to argue in favor of idealism. Vasubandhu mentions three key features of experience which are supposed to be explained by matter and refutes them: # According to critics, the problem of spatio-temporal determination (or non-arbitrariness in regard to place and time) indicates that there must be some external basis for our experiences, since experiences of any particular object do not occur everywhere and at every time. Vasubandhu responds with the dream argument, which shows how a world created by mind can still ''seem'' to have spatio-temporal localization. # The problem of inter-subjective experience (multiple minds experiencing the same world). Vasubandhu counters that mass hallucinations (such as those said to occur to hungry ghosts) caused by the fact they share similar
karma Karma (, from , ; ) is an ancient Indian concept that refers to an action, work, or deed, and its effect or consequences. In Indian religions, the term more specifically refers to a principle of cause and effect, often descriptively called ...
(which is here understood as traces or seeds in the mind-stream), show that inter-subjective agreement is possible without positing real external objects. # Another criticism states that hallucinations have no pragmatic results, efficacy or causal function and thus can be determined to be unreal, but entities we generally accept as being "real" have actual causal results (such as the 'resistance' of external objects) that cannot be of the same class as hallucinations. Against this claim, Vasubandhu argues that waking life is the same as in a dream, where objects have pragmatic results within the very rules of the dream. He also uses the example of a wet dream to show that mental content can have causal efficacy even outside of a dream. According to Mark Siderits, after disposing of these objections, Vasubandhu believes he has shown that mere cognizance is just as good at explaining the relevant phenomena of experience as any theory of realism that posits external objects. Therefore, he then applies the Indian philosophical principle termed the "Principle of Lightness" (Sanskrit: ''lāghava,'' which is similar to Occam's Razor) to rule out realism since ''vijñapti-mātra'' is the simpler and "lighter" theory which "posits the least number of unobservable entities." Another objection that Vasubandhu answers is that of how one person can influence another's experiences, if everything arises from mental karmic seeds in one's mind stream. Vasubandhu argues that "impressions can also be caused in a mental stream by the occurrence of a distinct impression in another suitably linked mental stream."Siderits, Mark, ''Buddhism as philosophy'', 2017, p. 170. As Siderits notes, this account can explain how it is possible to influence or even totally disrupt (murder) another mind, even if there is no physical medium or object in existence, since a suitably strong enough intention in one mind stream can have effects on another mind stream. From the mind-only position, it is easier to posit a mind to mind causation than to have to explain mind to body causation, which the realist must do. However, Siderits then goes on to question whether Vasubandhu's position is indeed "lighter" since he must make use of multiple interactions between different minds to take into account an intentionally created artifact, like a pot. Since we can be aware of a pot even when we are not "linked" to the potter's intentions (even after the potter is dead), a more complex series of mental interactions must be posited. Nevertheless, not all interpretations of Yogācāra's view of the external world rely on multiple relations between individual minds. Some interpretations in
Chinese Buddhism Chinese Buddhism or Han Buddhism ( zh, s=汉传佛教, t=漢傳佛教, first=t, poj=Hàn-thoân Hu̍t-kàu, j=Hon3 Cyun4 Fat6 Gaau3, p=Hànchuán Fójiào) is a Chinese form of Mahayana Buddhism. The Chinese Buddhist canonJiang Wu, "The Chin ...
, such as in Huayan, defended the view of a single shared external world (bhājanaloka) which was still made of consciousness, while some later Indian thinkers like Ratnakīrti (11th century CE) defended a type of non-dual monism.


Causation-resemblance argument

This argument was famously defended in Dignāga's '' Ālambanaparīkṣā'' (''Examination of the Object of Consciousness'') and its main target is Indian atomism, which was the main theory of matter in the 5th century.Finnigan, Bronwyn (2017). "Buddhist Idealism." In Tyron Goldschmidt & Kenneth Pearce (eds.), ''Idealism: New Essays in Metaphysics''. Oxford University Press. pp. 178-199. The argument is based on the premise that a perception must resemble the perceived object ('' ālambana'') and have been caused by the object. According to this argument, since atoms are not extended, they do not resemble the object of perception (which appears as spatially extended). Furthermore, collections of atoms might resemble the object of perception, but they cannot have caused it. This is because collections of things are unreal in classic Buddhist thought (thus it is a mereological nihilism), since they are composites and composites made of parts do not have any causal efficacy (only individual atoms do). In disproving the possibility of external objects, Vasubandhu's ''Vimśatikā'' similarly attacks Indian theories of atomism and property particulars as incoherent on mereological grounds.Gold, Jonathan C., "Vasubandhu", ''The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' (Summer 2018 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2018/entries/vasubandhu/


Constant co-cognition argument

This argument was defended by Dharmakīrti in his ''Ascertainment of Epistemology'' ('' Pramāṇaviniścaya''), which calls it "the necessity of things only ever being experienced together with experience" (Sanskrit: ''sahopalambhaniyama'')''.'' According to Dharmakīrti:
Because omething blueis not apprehended without the additional qualification of consciousness, ndbecause lueis apprehended when this ualification of consciousnessis apprehended, consciousness tselfhas the appearance of blue. There is no external object by itself. (PV 3.335)''''
According to this argument, any object of consciousness, like blue, cannot be differentiated from the conscious awareness of blue since both are always experienced as one thing. Since we never experience blue without the experience of blue, they cannot be differentiated
empirically In philosophy, empiricism is an Epistemology, epistemological view which holds that true knowledge or justification comes only or primarily from Sense, sensory experience and empirical evidence. It is one of several competing views within ...
. Furthermore, we cannot differentiate them through an
inference Inferences are steps in logical reasoning, moving from premises to logical consequences; etymologically, the word '' infer'' means to "carry forward". Inference is theoretically traditionally divided into deduction and induction, a distinct ...
either, since this would need to be based on a pattern of past experiences which included the absence or presence of the two elements. Thus, this is a type of epistemological argument for idealism which attempts to show there is no good reason to accept the existence of mind-independent objects.''''


Soteriological importance of mind-only

Vasubandhu also explains why it is soteriologically important to get rid of the idea of really existing external objects. According to Siderits, this is because:
When we wrongly imagine there to be external objects we are led to think in terms of the duality of 'grasped and grasper', of what is 'out there' and what is ' in here' - in short, of external world and self. Coming to see that there is no external world is a means, Vasubandhu thinks, of overcoming a very subtle way of believing in an 'I'... once we see why physical objects can't exist we will lose all temptation to think there is a true ' me' within. There are really just impressions, but we superimpose on these the false constructions of object and subject. Seeing this will free us from the false conception of an 'I'.Siderits, Mark, ''Buddhism as philosophy'', 2017, p. 175.
Siderits notes how Kant had a similar notion, that is, without the idea of an objective mind independent world, one cannot derive the concept of a subjective "I". But Kant drew the opposite conclusion to Vasubandhu, since he held that we must believe in an enduring subject, and thus, also believe in external objects.


Analysis of Consciousness

Yogācāra gives a detailed explanation of the workings of the mind and the way it constructs the reality we experience. The central Yogācāra theory of mind is that of the eight consciousnesses.


Eight consciousnesses

A key innovation of the Yogācāra school was the doctrine of eight consciousnesses. These "eight bodies of consciousnesses" (''aṣṭa vijñānakāyāḥ'') are: the five
sense A sense is a biological system used by an organism for sensation, the process of gathering information about the surroundings through the detection of Stimulus (physiology), stimuli. Although, in some cultures, five human senses were traditio ...
-consciousnesses (of seeing, hearing, smelling, tasting and bodily sense), mentation (mano or citta), the defiled self-consciousness (''kliṣṭamanovijñāna''), and the storehouse or substratum consciousness ( Skt: ''ālayavijñāna'').Williams, Paul (2008). ''Mahayana Buddhism: The Doctrinal Foundations'', Routledge, p. 97. Traditional Buddhist descriptions of consciousness taught just the first six '' vijñānas'', each corresponding to a sense base ('' ayatana'') and having their own sense objects (sounds etc). Five are based on the five senses, while the sixth (''mano-vijñāna),'' was seen as the surveyor of the content of the five senses as well as of mental content like thoughts and ideas. Standard Buddhist doctrine held that these eighteen "elements" (dhatus), i.e. six external sense bases (smells, sounds etc.), six internal bases (sense organs like the eye, ear, etc.), and six consciousnesses "exhaust the full extent of everything in the universe, or more accurately, the sensorium." The six consciousnesses are also not substantial entities, but a series or stream of events (dharmas), which arise and vanish very rapidly moment by moment. This is the Abhidharma doctrine of "momentariness" (kṣaṇavada), which Yogācāra also accepts. Yogācāra expanded the six vijñāna schema into a new system which with two new categories. The seventh consciousness developed from the early Buddhist concept of '' manas,'' and was seen as the defiled mentation (''kliṣṭa-manas'') which is obsessed with notions of "self". According to Paul Williams, this consciousness "takes the substratum consciousness as its object and mistakenly considers the substratum consciousness to be a true Self."


''Ālaya-vijñāna''

The eighth consciousness, ''ālaya-vijñāna'' (storehouse or repository consciousness), was defined as the storehouse of all karmic seeds ( bīja), where they gradually matured until ripe, at which point they manifested as karmic consequences. Because of this, it is also called the "mind which has all the seeds" (''sarvabījakam cittam''), as well as the "basis consciousness" (''mūla-vijñāna'') and the "appropriating consciousness" (''ādānavijñāna''). According to the '' Saṅdhinirmocana Sūtra,'' this kind of consciousness ''underlies'' and ''supports'' the six types of manifest awareness, all of which occur simultaneously with the ''ālaya.''Waldron, William S. The Buddhist Unconscious: The Alaya-vijñana in the context of Indian Buddhist Thought. Routledge Critical Studies in Buddhism, 2003, pp 94-95. William S. Waldron sees this "simultaneity of all the modes of cognitive awareness" as the most significant departure of Yogācāra theory from traditional Buddhist models of ''vijñāna,'' which were "thought to occur solely in conjunction with their respective sense bases and epistemic objects". As noted by Schmithausen, the ''ālaya-vijñāna,'' being a kind of vijñāna, has an object as well (as all vijñāna has intentionality). That object is the sentient being's surrounding world, that is to say, the "receptable" or "container" (''bhājana'') world. This is stated in the 8th chapter of the ''Saṅdhinirmocana Sūtra,'' which states that the ''ādānavijñāna'' is characterized by "an unconscious (or not fully conscious?) steady perception (or "representation") of the Receptacle (''*asaṃvidita-sthira-bhājana-vijñapti'')." The ''ālaya-vijñāna'' is also what experiences rebirth into future lives and what descends into the womb to appropriate the fetal material. Therefore, the ''ālaya-vijñāna's'' holding on to the body's sense faculties and "profuse imaginings" ('' prapañca'') are the two appropriations which make up the "kindling" or "fuel" (lit. '' upādāna'') that samsaric existence depends upon. Yogācāra thought thus holds that being unaware of the processes going on in the ''ālaya-vijñāna'' is an important element of ignorance ('' avidya''). The ''ālaya'' is also individual, so that each person has their own ''ālaya-vijñāna,'' which is an ever changing process and therefore not a permanent self. According to Williams, this consciousness "seen as a defiled form of consciousness (or perhaps sub- or unconsciousness), is personal, individual, continually changing and yet serving to give a degree of personal identity and to explain why it is that certain karmic results pertain to this particular individual. The seeds are momentary, but they give rise to a perfumed series which eventually culminates in the result including, from seeds of a particular type, the whole ‘inter-subjective’ phenomenal world." Also, Asanga and Vasubandhu write that the ''ālaya-vijñāna'' ‘ceases’ at awakening, becoming transformed into a pure consciousness. According to the '' Mahāyānasaṃgraha'', the ''ālayavijñāna'' has both a common character and an uncommon character. The common character refers to those seeds which ripen into the ''bhājanaloka'', or container world, which is common to all. On the other hand, its uncommon character refers to those seeds which ripen as an individual's own sense faculties. The ''Mahāyānasaṃgraha'' states that the remedies (i.e. those which comprise the Buddhist path) counteract the uncommon character of the ''ālayavijñāna'', but not that which is common. That is, although they lack any individual karma of their own, purified persons are nonetheless supported by a consciousness of common seeds and that which is sustained by the discriminations of others. And while buddhas have access to that which is shared in common, i.e. the container world, they nonetheless experience it as pure. The storehouse consciousness also serves as the basis for container worlds that are uninhabited by sentient beings. That is, according to Buddhist cosmology, when a world is going to perish, beings no longer populate it. However, although there are no beings to perceive it, that container world is nonetheless "mind only," as it still exists in the storehouse consciousnesses of the beings who have departed from it. Similarly, in the case of an uninhabited world in which beings are yet to be reborn, such a world also exists in the storehouse consciousnesses of those beings who will be reborn there. According to Waldron, while there were various similar concepts in other Buddhist Abhidharma schools which sought to explain karmic continuity, the ''ālaya-vijñāna'' is the most comprehensive and systematic. Waldron notes that the ''ālaya-vijñāna'' concept was probably influenced by these theories, particularly the Sautrantika theory of seeds and Vasumitra's theory of a subtle form of mind ''(suksma-citta)''. Regarding the status of the seeds, according to the ''Chengweishilun'', Sthiramati regarded the seeds to be merely nominal (i.e. conventional and not actually real); while on the other hand,
Xuanzang Xuanzang (; ; 6 April 6025 February 664), born Chen Hui or Chen Yi (), also known by his Sanskrit Dharma name Mokṣadeva, was a 7th-century Chinese Bhikkhu, Buddhist monk, scholar, traveller, and translator. He is known for the epoch-making ...
took them to be real.


Transformations of consciousness

Yogācāra sources do not necessarily describe the eight consciousnesses as absolutely separate or substantial phenomena. For example, Kalupahana notes that the ''Triṃśika'' describes the various forms of consciousness as transformations and functions of a being's stream of consciousness. These transformations are threefold according to Kalupahana. The first is the ''ālaya'' and its seeds, which is the flow or stream of consciousness, without any of the usual projections on top of it. The second transformation is ''manana'', self-consciousness or "Self-view, self-confusion, self-esteem and self-love". It is "thinking" about the various perceptions occurring in the stream of consciousness". The ''ālaya'' is defiled by this self-interest. The third transformation is ''visaya-vijñapti'', the "''concept'' of the object". In this transformation the ''concept'' of objects is created. By creating these concepts human beings become "susceptible to grasping after the object" as if it were a real object (''sad artha'') even though it is just a conception (''vijñapti''). A similar perspective which emphasizes Yogācāra's continuity with early Buddhism is given by Walpola Rahula. According to Rahula, all the elements of this theory of consciousness with its three layers of ''vijñāna'' are already found in the
Pāli Canon The Pāḷi Canon is the standard collection of scriptures in the Theravada Buddhism, Buddhist tradition, as preserved in the Pāli language. It is the most complete extant Early Buddhist texts, early Buddhist canon. It derives mainly from t ...
, corresponding to the terms ''viññāna'' (sense cognition), ''manas'' (mental function, thinking, reasoning, conception) and ''citta'' (the deepest layer of the aggregate of consciousness which retains karmic impressions and the defilements).


The three natures

Yogācāra works often define three basic modes or "natures" ('' svabhāva'') of experience. Jonathan Gold explains that "the three natures are all one reality viewed from three distinct angles. They are the appearance, the process, and the emptiness of that same apparent entity." According to Paul Williams, "all things which can be known can be subsumed under these Three Natures." Since this schema is Yogācāra's systematic explanation of the Buddhist doctrine of emptiness ('' śūnyatā''), each of the three natures are also explained as having a lack of own-nature (''niḥsvabhāvatā'').King, Richard, Early Yogācāra and its Relationship with the Madhyamaka School, Philosophy East & West Volume 44, Number 4 October 1994 PP.659-683. The ''Trisvabhāva-nirdeśa'' (''Exposition of the Three Natures'') gives a brief definition of these three natures:
What appears is the dependent. How it appears is the fabricated. Because of being dependent on conditions. Because of being only fabrication. The eternal non-existence of the appearance as it is appears: That is known to be the perfected nature, because of being always the same. What appears there? The unreal fabrication. How does it appear? As a dual self. What is its nonexistence? That by which the nondual reality is there.
In detail, three natures (''trisvabhāva'') are:Williams (2008), p. 90. #''Parikalpita-svabhāva'' (the "fully conceptualized" or "imagined" nature). This is the "imaginary" or "constructed" nature, wherein things are incorrectly comprehended based on conceptual construction, through the activity of language and through attachment and erroneous discrimination which attributes intrinsic existence to things. According to the '' Mahāyānasaṃgraha'', it also refers to the appearance of things in terms of subject-object dualism (literally "grasper" and "grasped"). The conceptualized nature is the world of everyday unenlightened people, i.e. samsara. It is false and empty, and does not really exist (''Triṃśikā'' v. 20). According to Xuanzang's '' Cheng Weishi Lun'', this nature is an "absence of an existential nature by its very defining characteristic''"'' (''lakṣana-niḥsvabhāvatā''). Because these conceptualized natures and distinct characteristics (''lakṣana'') are wrongly imputed and not truly real, "they are like mirages and blossoms in the sky." #''Paratantra-svabhāva'' (literally, "other dependent"), which is the dependently originated nature of dharmas, or the causal flow of phenomena which is erroneously confused into the conceptualized nature. According to Williams, it is "''the basis'' for the erroneous partition into supposedly intrinsically existing subjects and objects which marks the conceptualized nature." Jonathan Gold writes that it is "the causal ''process'' of the thing's fabrication, the causal story that brings about the thing's apparent nature." This basis is considered to be an ultimately existing ('' paramārtha'') basis in classical Yogācāra (see '' Mahāyānasaṃgraha,'' 2:25).Williams (2008), pp. 90-91. However, as Xuanzang notes, this nature is also empty in that there is an "absence of an existential nature in conditions that arise and perish" (''utpatti-niḥsvabhāvatā''). That is, the events in this causal flow, while "seeming to have real existence of their own" are actually like magical illusions since "they are said to only be hypothetical and not really exist on their own." As Siderits writes "to the extent that we are thinking of it at all - even if only as the non-dual flow of impressions-only - we are still conceptualizing it." #''Pariniṣpanna-svabhāva'' (literally, "fully accomplished", "perfected", "consummated"): This is the true nature of things, the experience of Suchness or Thatness ('' Tathātā'') discovered in meditation unaffected by conceptualization, causality, or duality. It is defined as "''the complete absence'', in the dependent nature, of objects – that is, the objects of the conceptualized nature" (see '' Mahāyānasaṃgraha,'' 2:4). What this refers to is that empty non-dual experience which has been stripped of the duality of the constructed nature through yogic praxis. According to Williams, this is "''what has to be known'' for enlightenment" and Siderits defines it as "just pure seeing without any attempt at conceptualization or interpretation. Now this is also empty, but only of itself as an interpretation. That is, this mode of cognition is devoid of all concepts, and so is empty of being of the nature of the perfected. About it nothing can be said or thought, it is just pure immediacy." According to Xuanzang, this nature has the "absence of any existential nature of ultimate meaning" (''paramārtha-niḥsvabhāvatā'') since it is "completely free from any clinging to entirely imagined speculations about its identity or purpose. Because of this, it is conventionally said that it does not exist. However, it is also not entirely without a real existence."


Two interpretations of the three natures

Various Buddhist studies scholars such as Alan Spongberg, Mario D'amato, Daniel McNamara, and Matthew T. Kapstein have noted that there are two main interpretations of the three natures doctrine among the various texts of the Yogacara corpus. The two models have been named the "pivot" model and "progressive" model by these Western scholars.McNamara, Daniel (2011)
“On the Status of the Trisvabhāvanirdeśa in Contemporary Conceptions of Yogācāra Thought.”
/ref>Matthew Kapstein
Who Wrote the Trisvabhāvanirdeśa? Reflections on an Enigmatic Text and Its Place in the History of Buddhist Philosophy.
Journal of Indian Philosophy, 2017. ⟨halshs-02503277⟩
The "pivot" model, found in texts like the '' Triṃśikā'' and the '' Mahāyānasaṃgraha,'' presents the dependent nature as a kind of "ontological pivot" since it is the basis for conceptual construction (the imagined nature) and for the perfected nature (which is nothing but the absence of the imagined nature in the dependent nature). As such, the imagined nature is an incorrect way of experiencing the dependent, while the perfected nature is the correct way. The "progressive model" meanwhile can be found in the '' Trisvabhāvanirdeśa'' and in the '' Mahāyānasūtrālaṃkāra'' and its ''bhāṣya''. In this model, it is the perfected nature which is the primary element of the three natures schema. Here, the perfected nature is the pure basis of reality, while the other two natures are both impaired by ignorance.D’AMATO, M. “THREE NATURES, THREE STAGES: AN INTERPRETATION OF THE YOGĀCĀRA ‘TRISVABHĀVA’-THEORY.” ''Journal of Indian Philosophy'', vol. 33, no. 2, 2005, pp. 185–207. ''JSTOR'', http://www.jstor.org/stable/23497001. Accessed 16 Feb. 2024. As the ''Trisvabhāvanirdeśa'' states: "The imputed and the other-dependent are to be known as having defiled characteristics. The perfected is asserted to have the characteristic of purity." In this text, the dependent nature is seen as something which must be abandoned since it has the "appearance of duality" (dvayākāra). As such, in this "progressive" model, the dependent nature is the basis for the imagined nature, but not the basis for the perfected nature. The perfected nature on the other hand is a fundamentally pure true reality (which nevertheless is covered by adventitious defilements). As the ''Mahāyānasūtrālaṃkāra'' states:
Reality - which is always without duality, is the basis of error, and is entirely inexpressible - does not have the nature of discursivity. It is to be known, abandoned, and purified. It should properly be thought of as naturally immaculate, since it is purified from defilements, as are space, gold, and water.
Furthermore, according to the ''Trisvabhāvanirdeśa'' (TSN 17-20), the three natures are inseparable (abhinna) and as such non-dual. This is a key difference between this model and the pivot model, where the dependent nature is ultimately devoid of the imagined nature. Another difference between these sources is that in the ''Triṃśikā'', the main model of liberation is a radical transformation of the basis (āśrayaparāvṛtti). The ''Trisvabhāvanirdeśa'' meanwhile claims that liberation occurs through knowledge of the three natures as they are (in their non-duality). Some scholars, like McNamara, argue that these two models are incompatible, ontologically and soteriologically. Kapstein thinks that it is possible that the ''Trisvabhāvanirdeśa'' is attempting to reconcile them. These differences have also led some scholars (Kapstein and Thomas Wood) to question the attribution of the ''Trisvabhāvanirdeśa'' to Vasubandhu.


Divisions of consciousness and their relationship to the three natures

Different Yogācāra philosophers analyzed consciousness into various parts or divisions (''bhāga''). According to Nanda, consciousness was divided into a seeing part (''darśana-bhāga'') and a seen, or image part (''nimitta-bhāga''). Dignāga accepted a third part, the self-cognizing part (''svasaṃvitti-bhāga''), which refers to consciousness' reflexive knowing within any act of cognition. Dharmapāla added to this yet a fourth part, the cognition of self-cognition, which is the resulting awareness that one is self-aware. These philosophers differed on the question of the relationship of the various divisions of consciousness to the three natures (''trisvabhāva''). For Nanda, the seeing part of consciousness belonged to the dependent nature (''paratantra-svabhāva''), while the seen part belonged to the imagined (''parikalpita-svabhāva''). According to Dharmapāla, the seeing part, seen part, and the self-cognizing part all belong to the dependent nature. For Dharmapāla, it is only when false notions are applied to them (such as existence, nonexistence, identity, difference, etc.) that the seeing and seen parts can be called imagined, but they are otherwise real. While Sthiramati was influenced by Dignāga's three-bhāga theory, he held that the self-cognizing part alone belonged to the dependent nature (with the seeing and seen parts both belonging to the imagined). Thus, for Sthiramati, consciousness really only has one part, and in this he differed from Dharmapāla and Xuanzang. According to Zhihua Yao, the one-bhāga theory is associated with the classical Nirākarāvāda position according to which consciousness is not subject to any divisions.


Emptiness

The central meaning of emptiness (''śūnyatā'') in Yogācāra is a twofold " absence of duality." The first element of this is the unreality of any conceptual duality such as "physical" and "non-physical", "self" and "other". To define something conceptually is to divide the world into what it is and what it is not, but the world is a causal flux that does not accord with conceptual constructs. The second element of this is a perceptual duality between the sensorium and its objects, between what is "external" and "internal", between subject (''grāhaka,'' literally "grasper") and object (''grāhya,'' "grasped"). This is also an unreal superimposition, since there is really no such separation of inner and outer, but an interconnected causal stream of mentality which is falsely divided up. An important difference between the Yogācāra conception of emptiness and the
Madhyamaka Madhyamaka ("middle way" or "centrism"; ; ; Tibetic languages, Tibetan: དབུ་མ་པ་ ; ''dbu ma pa''), otherwise known as Śūnyavāda ("the Śūnyatā, emptiness doctrine") and Niḥsvabhāvavāda ("the no Svabhava, ''svabhāva'' d ...
conception is that in classical Yogācāra, emptiness ''does exist'' (as a real absence) and so does consciousness (which is that which is empty, the referent of emptiness), while Madhyamaka refuses to endorse such existential statements. The '' Madhyāntavibhāga'' for example, states "the imagination of the nonexistent 'abhūta-parikalpa''exists. In it duality does not exist. Emptiness, however, exists in it," which indicates that even though that which is dualistically imagined (subjects and objects), is unreal and empty, their basis does exist (i.e. the dependently arisen conscious manifestation).King, Richard, Early Yogācāra and its Relationship with the Madhyamaka School, Philosophy East & West Volume 44, Number 4 October 1994 pp. 659-683. The Yogācāra school also gave special significance to the Āgama sutra called ''Lesser Discourse on Emptiness'' (parallel to the Pali ''Cūḷasuññatasutta'', MN 121) and relies on this sutra in its explanations of emptiness. According to Gadjin Nagao, this sutra affirms that "emptiness includes both being and non-being. both negation and affirmation."


Disagreement with Madhyamaka

Indian sources indicate that Yogācāra thinkers sometimes debated with the defenders of the
Madhyamaka Madhyamaka ("middle way" or "centrism"; ; ; Tibetic languages, Tibetan: དབུ་མ་པ་ ; ''dbu ma pa''), otherwise known as Śūnyavāda ("the Śūnyatā, emptiness doctrine") and Niḥsvabhāvavāda ("the no Svabhava, ''svabhāva'' d ...
tradition.Garfield, Jay L.; Westerhoff, Jan (2015). ''Madhyamaka and Yogacara: Allies Or Rivals?'' p. 3. Oxford University Press. However, there is disagreement among contemporary Western and traditional Buddhist scholars about the degree to which they were opposed, if at all.:50f. The main difference between these schools was related to issues of existence and the nature of emptiness. The Chinese pilgrim Yijing (635–713) concisely summarized the differences thus: “For Yogācāra the real exists, but the conventional does not exist; and ogācāratakes the three natures as foundational. For Madhyamaka the real does not exist, but the conventional does exist; and actually the two truths are primary". Garfield and Westerhoff write that "Yogācāra is both ontologically and epistemologically foundationalist; Madhyamaka is antifoundationalist in both senses." Another way to state this key difference is that Madhyamaka defends a "global antirealism" while Yogācāra "restrict the scope of their antirealism to the external and the conventional". While Madhyamaka generally states that asserting the ultimate existence or non-existence of anything (including emptiness) was inappropriate, Yogācāra treatises (like the ''Madhyāntavibhāga'') often assert that the dependent nature (''paratantra-svabhāva'') really exists and that emptiness is an ''actual absence'' that also exists ultimately.Williams (2008), p. 93. In a similar fashion, Asaṅga states "that of which it is empty does not truly exist; that which is empty truly exists: emptiness makes sense in this way". He also describes emptiness as "the non-existence of the self, and the existence of the no-self." Classical Yogācāras like Vasubandhu and Sthiramati also affirm the reality of conscious appearance, i.e. that truly existent stream of dependent arisen and constantly changing
consciousness Consciousness, at its simplest, is awareness of a state or object, either internal to oneself or in one's external environment. However, its nature has led to millennia of analyses, explanations, and debate among philosophers, scientists, an ...
which projects false and illusory subjective minds and their cognitive objects. It is this real flow of conscious transformation (vijñānapariṇāma) which is said to be empty (of duality and conceptuality). Against the radically anti-foundationalist interpretation of
Madhyamaka Madhyamaka ("middle way" or "centrism"; ; ; Tibetic languages, Tibetan: དབུ་མ་པ་ ; ''dbu ma pa''), otherwise known as Śūnyavāda ("the Śūnyatā, emptiness doctrine") and Niḥsvabhāvavāda ("the no Svabhava, ''svabhāva'' d ...
, the classic Yogācāra position is that there is something (the dependent nature which is mere-consciousness) that " exists" (sat) independently of conceptual designation (prajñapti), and that it is this real thing (vāstu) which is said to be empty of duality and yet is a basis for all dualistic conceptions. Furthermore, Yogācāra thinkers like Asaṅga and Vasubandhu critiqued those who "adhere to non-existence" (''nāstikas, vaināśkas'', likely referring to certain Madhyamikas) because they saw them as straying into metaphysical nihilism (''abhāvānta'', see ''Vimśatikā'' v. 10). They held that there was really something which could be said to "exist", that is, ''vijñapti,'' and that was what is described as being "empty" in their system. For Yogācāra, all conventional existence must be based on something which is real (dravya). Sthiramati argues that we cannot say that everything exists conventionally ( saṁvṛtisat) or nominally (prajñaptisat) and that nothing truly exists in an ultimate fashion (which would entail a global conventionalism and
nominalism In metaphysics, nominalism is the view that universals and abstract objects do not actually exist other than being merely names or labels. There are two main versions of nominalism. One denies the existence of universals—that which can be inst ...
without any metaphysical ground). For Sthiramati, this view is false because "what would follow is non-existence even conventionally. That is because conventions are not possible without something to depend upon (or, “without taking up something”— upādāna)."Garfield, Jay L.; Westerhoff, Jan (2015). ''Madhyamaka and Yogacara: Allies Or Rivals?'' p. 46. Oxford University Press. Thus, for Sthiramati, consciousness (vijñana) "since it is dependently arisen, exists as dravya ( substance)." The ''Bodhisattvabhūmi'' likewise argues that it is only logical to speak of emptiness if there is ''something'' (i.e. '' dharmatā,'' an ultimate nature) that is empty. The ''Bodhisattvabhūmi's'' Chapter on Reality (''Tattvārthapaṭala'') states that emptiness is "wrongly grasped" by those who "do not accept that of which something is empty, nor do they accept that which is empty". This is because "emptiness holds good only as long as that of which something is aid to beempty does not exist, but on the other hand, that which is empty exists. If, however, all lements involved in this relationwere non-existent, in what respect, what would be empty, ndof what?" For the ''Bodhisattvabhūmi'', the "right" way to understand emptiness is "one regards that something is empty of that which does not exist in it and correctly comprehends that what remains there does actually exist here". That which "remains" and "actually exists" is the true reality, the thing itself (vastumātra), the foundation (āśraya) which remains (avaśiṣṭa) after all conceptual constructs have been removed. Yogācārins also criticized certain Madhyamaka accounts of conventional truth, that is, the view which says that conventional truth is merely erroneous cognitive processes (designations, expressions, and linguistic conventions) which project an inherent nature. The ''Yogācārabhūmi'''s Viniścayasaṃgrahanī states that either Madhyamakas see conventional reality as produced by linguistic expressions and also by causal forces, or they see it as produced merely by linguistic expressions and convention. If the former, then Madhyamikas must accept the reality of causal efficacy, which is a kind of existence (since things which are causally produced can be said to exist in some way). If the latter, then without any basis for linguistic expression and convention, it makes no sense to even use these terms (for Yogācāra these conventions must have some kind of referential basis). Yogācārins further held that if all phenomena are equally conventional and unreal in the same way this would lead to laxity in ethics and in following the path, in other words to moral relativism.Garfield, Jay L.; Westerhoff, Jan (2015). ''Madhyamaka and Yogacara: Allies Or Rivals?'' p. 116. Oxford University Press. The basic idea behind this critique is that if only convention exists (as Madhyamaka claims) and there are no truths that are independent of convention and linguistic expression, there would be no epistemic foundations for critiquing worldly (non-buddhist) conventions and affirming other conventions as closer to the truth (like the conventions used by Buddhists to establish their ethics and their teachings). Madhyamaka thinkers like Bhaviveka, Candrakirti and
Shantideva Shantideva (Sanskrit: Śāntideva; ; ; ; ) was an 8th-century CE Indian philosopher, Buddhist monk, poet, and scholar at the mahavihara of Nalanda. He was an adherent of the Mādhyamaka philosophy of Nāgārjuna. Abhayadatta Sri also li ...
also critiqued Yogācāra views in their works for what they saw as an improper reification (samāropa) of mind and for a nihilistic denial of conventional truth. The work of
Xuanzang Xuanzang (; ; 6 April 6025 February 664), born Chen Hui or Chen Yi (), also known by his Sanskrit Dharma name Mokṣadeva, was a 7th-century Chinese Bhikkhu, Buddhist monk, scholar, traveller, and translator. He is known for the epoch-making ...
(7th century) also contains evidence for this Indian debate.Lusthaus, Dan (undated). ''Xuanzang (Hsüan-tsang)''. Source: (accessed: December 12, 2007)


Mental images: true vs false

An important debate about the reality of mental appearances within Yogācāra led to its later subdivision into two systems of Alikākāravāda ( Tib. ''rnam rdzun pa'', False Aspectarians, also known as Nirākāravāda) and Satyākāravāda (''rnam bden pa'', True Aspectarians, also known as Sākāravāda). They are also termed "Aspectarians" (''ākāra'') and "Non-Aspectarians" (''anākāra''). The core issue is whether appearances or “aspects” (''rnam pa, ākāra'') of objects in the mind are treated as true (''bden pa, satya'') or false (''rdzun pa, alika''). While this division did not exist in the works of the early Yogācāra philosophers, tendencies similar to these views can be discerned in the works of Yogācāra thinkers like Dharmapāla (c. 530–561?) and Sthiramati (c. 510–570?).Kajiyama, Yuichi. “Controversy between the sakara- and nirakara-vadins of the Yogacara school-some materials.” Journal of Indian and Buddhist Studies 14 (1965): n. pag. https://www.semanticscholar.org/paper/Controversy-between-the-sakara-and-nirakara-vadins-Kajiyama/655a1f561c18725188c0916ca05ec334b5f9f7cd According to Zhihua Yao, Dharmapāla was a Sākāravādin, while Sthiramati was a Nirākāravādin. According to Yaroslav Komarovski the distinction is as follows:
Although Yogācāras in general do not accept the existence of an external material world, according to Satyākāravāda its appearances or “aspects” (''rnam pa, ākāra'') reflected in consciousness have a real existence, because they are of one nature with the really existent consciousness, their creator. According to Alikākāravāda, neither external phenomena nor their appearances and/in the minds that reflect them really exist. What exists in reality is only primordial mind (''ye shes, jñāna''), described as self-cognition (''rang rig, svasamvedana/ svasamvitti'') or individually self-cognizing primordial mind (''so so(r) rang gis rig pa’i ye shes'').
Davey K. Tomlinson describes the difference (with reference to later Yogacara scholars from Vikramashila) as follows:
On one hand is the Nirākāravāda, typified by Ratnākaraśānti (ca. 970–1045); on the other, the Sākāravāda, articulated by his colleague and critic Jñānaśrīmitra (ca. 980–1040). The Nirākāravādin argues that all appearances do not really exist. They are ersatz or false (alīka). Ephemeral forms appear to us but are the erroneous construction of ignorance, which fundamentally characterizes our existence as suffering beings in saṃsāra. In the ultimately real experience of an awakened buddha, no appearances show up at all. Pure experience, unstained by false appearance (which is nirākāra, “without appearance”), is possible. The Sākāravādin, on the other hand, defends the view that all conscious experience is necessarily the experience of a manifest appearance (consciousness is sākāra, or constitutively “has appearance”). Manifest appearances, properly understood, are really real. A buddha's experience has appearances, and there is nothing about this fact that makes a buddha's experience mistaken.


Karma

An explanation of the Buddhist doctrine of
karma Karma (, from , ; ) is an ancient Indian concept that refers to an action, work, or deed, and its effect or consequences. In Indian religions, the term more specifically refers to a principle of cause and effect, often descriptively called ...
(action) is central to Yogācāra, and the school sought to explain important questions such as how moral actions can have effects on individuals long after that action was done, that is, how karmic causality works across temporal distances. Previous Abhidharma schools like the Sautrantika had developed theories of karma based on the notion of "seeds" ('' bījā'') in the mind stream, which are unseen karmic habits (good and bad) which remain until they meet with the necessary conditions to manifest. Yogācāra adopts and expanded this theory. Yogācāra then posited the "storehouse consciousness" as the container of the seeds, as the storage place for karmic latencies and as a fertile matrix of predispositions that bring karma to a state of fruition. In the Yogācāra system, all experience without exception is said to result from karma or mental intention ( ''cetana''), either arising from one's own subliminal seeds or from other minds. For Yogācāra, the seemingly external or dualistic world is merely a "by-product" (''adhipati-phala'') of karma. The term '' vāsanā'' ("perfuming") is also used when explaining karma. Yogācārins were divided on the issue of whether vāsāna and bija were essentially the same, whether the seeds were the effect of the perfuming, or whether the perfuming simply affected the seeds. The type, quantity, quality and strength of the seeds determine where and how a sentient being will be reborn: one's race, sex, social status, proclivities, bodily appearance and so forth. The conditioning of the mind resulting from karma is called '' saṃskāra''. Vasubandhu's ''Treatise on Action'' (''Karmasiddhiprakaraṇa''), treats the subject of karma in detail from the Yogācāra perspective.


Meditation and awakening

As the name of the school suggests, meditation practice is central to the Yogācāra tradition. Yogācāra texts prescribe various yogic practices such as mindfulness and the four investigations, out of which a revolutionary and radically transformative understanding of the non-duality of self and other is said to arise. This process is referred to as ''āśraya-parāvṛtti'' ("overturning the cognitive basis", or "revolution of the basis"), which refers to "overturning the conceptual projections and imaginings which act as the base of our cognitive actions." This event is seen as the transformation of the basic mode of cognition into '' jñāna'' (knowledge, direct knowing), which is seen as a non-dual knowledge that is non-conceptual (''nirvikalpa''), i.e., "devoid of interpretive overlay". Roger R. Jackson describes this as a "'fundamental unconstructed awareness' (''mūla-nirvikalpa-jñāna'')". When this knowledge arises, the eight consciousnesses come to an end and are replaced by direct knowings. According to Lusthaus:
Overturning the Basis turns the five sense consciousnesses into immediate cognitions that accomplish what needs to be done (''kṛtyānuṣṭhāna-jñāna''). The sixth consciousness becomes immediate cognitive mastery (''pratyavekṣaṇa-jñāna''), in which the general and particular characteristics of things are discerned just as they are. This discernment is considered nonconceptual (''nirvikalpa-jñāna''). ''Manas'' becomes the immediate cognition of equality (''samatā-jñāna''), equalizing self and other. When the Warehouse Consciousness finally ceases it is replaced by the Great Mirror Cognition (''Mahādarśa-jñāna'') that sees and reflects things just as they are, impartially, without exclusion, prejudice, anticipation, attachment, or distortion. The grasper-grasped relation has ceased. ..."purified" cognitions all engage the world in immediate and effective ways by removing the self-bias, prejudice, and obstructions that had prevented one previously from perceiving beyond one's own narcissistic consciousness. When consciousness ends, true knowledge begins. Since enlightened cognition is nonconceptual its objects cannot be described.


Five Categories of Beings

One of the more controversial Yogācāra teachings was the "five categories of beings", which was an extension of the teachings on the seeds of the storehouse consciousness. This teaching states that sentient beings have certain innate seeds that determine their capability of achieving a particular state of enlightenment and no other. Thus, beings were placed into five categories: # Beings whose innate seeds gave them the capacity to practice the bodhisattva path and achieve full
Buddhahood In Buddhism, Buddha (, which in classic Indo-Aryan languages, Indic languages means "awakened one") is a title for those who are Enlightenment in Buddhism, spiritually awake or enlightened, and have thus attained the Buddhist paths to liberat ...
# Beings whose innate seeds gave them the capacity to achieve the state of a pratyekabuddha (private Buddha) # Beings whose innate seeds gave them the capacity to achieve the state of an arhat # Beings whose innate seeds had an indeterminate nature, and could potentially be any of the above # Beings whose innate seeds were incapable of achieving enlightenment ever because they lacked any wholesome seeds The fifth class of beings, the icchantika, were described in various Mahayana sutras as being incapable of achieving enlightenment, unless in some cases through the aid of a Buddha or Bodhisattva. Nevertheless, the notion was highly criticized by later Mahayanists who supported the universalist doctrine of ekayana. This tension is important in East Asian Buddhist history and later East Asian Yogācārins attempted to resolve the dispute by softening their stance on the five categories.


Practice

Maitreya meditating, 2nd century CE, Loriyan Tangai, Indian_Museum.html" ;"title="Loriyan Tangai, Indian Museum">Loriyan Tangai, Indian Museum, Kolkata ">Indian Museum">Loriyan Tangai, Indian Museum, Kolkata">Indian_Museum.html" ;"title="Loriyan Tangai, Indian Museum">Loriyan Tangai, Indian Museum, Yogācārabhūmi-Śāstra'' (YBh'', Shastra">Treatise on the Foundation for Yoga Practitioners).'' The YBh presents a structured exposition of the Mahāyāna Buddhist path of ''
yoga Yoga (UK: , US: ; 'yoga' ; ) is a group of physical, mental, and spiritual practices or disciplines that originated with its own philosophy in ancient India, aimed at controlling body and mind to attain various salvation goals, as pra ...
'' (here referring to spiritual practice in general) from a Yogācāra perspective and relies in both Āgama/Nikāya texts and Mahayana sutras, Mahāyāna sūtras while also being influenced by Vaibhāṣika Abhidharma. According to some scholars, this text can be traced to communities of ''yogācāras,'' which initially referred not to a philosophical school, but to groups of meditation specialists whose main focus was Buddhist yoga. Other Yogācāra texts which also discuss meditation and spiritual practice (and show some relationship with the YBh) include the '' Saṃdhinirmocanasūtra,'' the '' Madhyāntavibhāga'', '' Mahāyānasūtrālaṃkāra, Dharmadharmatāvibhāga'' and Asanga's '' Mahāyānasaṃgraha''. The YBh discusses various topics relevant to the bodhisattva practice, including: the eight different forms of dhyāna (meditative absorptions), the three ''samādhis'', different types of liberation ( ''vimokṣa''), meditative attainments (''samāpatti'') such as '' nirodhasamāpatti'', the five hindrances ('' nivaraṇa''), the various types of foci (''ālambana'') or 'images' (''nimitta'') used in meditation, the various types contemplative antidotes (''pratipakṣa'') against the afflictions (like contemplating death, unattractiveness, impermanence, and suffering), the practice of ''śamatha'' through "the nine aspects of resting the mind" (''navākārā cittasthitiḥ''), the practice of insight ('' vipaśyanā''), mindfulness of breathing (''ānāpānasmṛti''), how to understand the
four noble truths In Buddhism, the Four Noble Truths (; ; "The Four Arya (Buddhism), arya satya") are "the truths of the noble one (the Buddha)," a statement of how things really are (Three marks of existence, the three marks of existence) when they are seen co ...
, the thirty-seven factors of Awakening (''saptatriṃśad bodhipakṣyā dharmāḥ''), the four immeasurables (''apramāṇa''), and how to practice the six perfections (''pāramitā'').Timme Kragh 2013 pp. 51, 60–230


Bodhisattva path

Yogācāra sources like the ''Abhidharmasamuccaya'', the '' Chéng Wéishì Lùn'' and the commentaries to the ''Mahāyānasaṃgraha'' and the ''Mahāyānasūtrālamkāra'' also contain various descriptions of the main stages of the bodhisattva path.Brunnholzl, Karl (trans.), Asanga. (2019) ''A Compendium of the Mahayana: Asanga's Mahayanasamgraha and Its Indian and Tibetan Commentaries,'' Appendix 10. Shambhala Publications. These Yogācāra sources integrate the Mahayana teaching of the ten bodhisattva stages (bhūmis) with the earlier Abhidharma outline of the path called the "five paths" (''pañcamārga''), to produce a Mahayanist version of "five stages" (pañcāvasthā).Muller, Charles
Five stages of cultivating the Yogâcāra path 唯識修道五位
Digital Dictionary of Buddhism, 2006
In classic Yogācāra, this bodhisattva path is said to last for three incaculable eons ( asaṃkhyeya kalpas), i.e. millions upon millions of years. The five paths or stages are outlined in Yogācāra sources as follows:Watanabe, Chikafumi, ''A Study of Mahayanasamgraha III: The Relation of Practical Theories and Philosophical Theories'', pp. 40-65. University of Calgary, 2000. # Path of accumulation (''sambhāra-mārga,'' 資糧位), in which a bodhisattva gives rise to bodhicitta, and works on the two accumulations of merit (puṇya) and wisdom ( jñana). These are linked with the practice of the six perfections. In this first stage of the path, one attains merit by doing good deeds like giving (dana) and one also accumulates wisdom by listening to the Mahayana teachings many times, contemplating them and meditating on them. One also associates with good spiritual friends. According to the ''Mahāyānasaṃgraha'', at this stage the bodhisattva focuses on accumulating wholesome roots (kuśalamūla) and on permeating one's mind with learning (bahuśrutaprabhāvita). This leads to the accumulation of great faith and conviction in the Mahayana and in the principle of consciousness-only. # Path of engagement (''prayoga-mārga,'' 加行位), also termed "the stage of the practice of faith and conviction" (''adhimukticaryābhūmi''). Here, a bodhisattva practices morality, meditation, and wisdom in order to quell the manifest activities of the two types of obscurations: emotionally afflictive and cognitive. While their active elements are quelled, they remain as seeds in the foundation consciousness. Furthermore, one also cultivates the "factors conducive to penetration", which consists of the "four investigations" and the "four correct cognitions". These are ways of contemplating the truth of mind-only and lead to the "entrance into the principle of cognizance-only" (vijñaptimātrapraveśa) as well as to "the certainty as to the non-existence of the object" (arthābhāvaniścaya). At this stage one relies on the fourth dhyana and also attains various samadhis (meditative concentrations). The final stage of this path which is just before the path of seeing is called "the elimination of the ideation of cognizance-only" (vijñaptimātrasaṃjñāvibhāvana). As the ''Mahāyānasaṃgraha'' states, at this point, the realization of the absolute nature (pariniṣpannasvabhāvabuddhi) eliminates the very "perception of mind-only" (vijñaptimātratābuddhi). The resulting wisdom is described by Asanga as "the non-conceptual cognition (nirvikalpakajñāna) in which the object (ālambana) and the subject (ālambaka) are completely identical (samasama)." # Path of seeing (''darśana-mārga'', 見道位), at this stage (which lasts for only a few moments), a bodhisattva attains an untainted knowledge (Skt. anāsrava-jñāna, 無漏智) into emptiness, the non-duality of self and other, and consciousness-only. The ''Cheng wei shi lun'' describes this knowledge which realises Suchness (tathatā) as being "entirely undifferentiated (samasama) from Suchness since both are free from the characteristics (lakṣaṇa) of subject (grāhaka) and object (grāhya)." This stage is equated with the first bodhisattva stage, the stage of joy. At this point, one is a proper noble (arya) bodhisattva instead of just a beginner. # Path of cultivation (''bhāvanā-mārga,'' 修道位), at this stage, a bodhisattva continues to train themselves in two main cognitions in order to fully eliminate all the seeds of the two types of obscurations. They train in the non-conceptual gnosis (nirvikalpakajñāna) of ultimate reality, and the wordly or subsequent knowledge (pṛṣṭhtalabdhajñāna) which knows conventional reality as illusory, and is yet able to conceptually understand it and use it for guiding sentient beings according to their needs. Part of this path requires effort, as the bodhisattva is said to "repeatedly (abhīkṣṇam) cultivate the non-conceptual cognition" (''Cheng wei shi lun''). However, after a certain point one advances effortlessly. This path corresponds to the second to ninth stages of the bodhisattva path. The ''Mahāyānasaṃgraha'' states that at this stage the yogin "dwells in intense cultivation for hundreds of thousands of koṭis of niyutas n astronomical numberof aeons and consequently attains the transformation of the basis (āśrayaparavṛtti)". # Path of fulfillment (''niṣṭhā-mārga''), also known as the path of no more learning (''aśaikṣa-mārga'', 無學位) in other sources. This is equivalent to complete
Buddhahood In Buddhism, Buddha (, which in classic Indo-Aryan languages, Indic languages means "awakened one") is a title for those who are Enlightenment in Buddhism, spiritually awake or enlightened, and have thus attained the Buddhist paths to liberat ...
. It also entails attaining the three bodies ( trikāya) of the Buddha (a doctrine which was also invented by the Yogācāra school).


Bodhisattva practice

The ''Bodhisattvabhūmi'' discusses the Yogācāra school's specifically Mahāyāna forms of practice which are tailored to
bodhisattva In Buddhism, a bodhisattva is a person who has attained, or is striving towards, '' bodhi'' ('awakening', 'enlightenment') or Buddhahood. Often, the term specifically refers to a person who forgoes or delays personal nirvana or ''bodhi'' in ...
s. The aim of the bodhisattva's practice in the ''Bodhisattvabhūmi'' is the wisdom ('' prajñā'') which realizes of the inexpressible Ultimate Reality (''tathata'') or the 'thing-in-itself (''vastumatra''), which is essenceless and beyond the duality ('' advaya'') of existence (''bhāva'') and non-existence (''abhāva''). The ''Bodhisattvabhūmi'' outlines several practices of bodhisattvas, including the six perfections (''pāramitā''), the thirty-seven factors of Awakening, and the four immeasurables. Two key practices which are unique to bodhisattvas in this text are the four investigations and the four correct cognitions or "the four kinds of understanding in accordance with true reality".Brunnholzl, Karl (trans.), Asanga. (2019) ''A Compendium of the Mahayana: Asanga's Mahayanasamgraha and Its Indian and Tibetan Commentaries,'' Appendix 8. Shambhala Publications. These two sets of four practices and cognitions are also taught in the ''Abhidharmasamuccaya'' and its commentaries.


The four investigations and four correct cognitions

The four investigations (catasraḥ paryeṣaṇāḥ) and the corresponding four correct cognitions (catvāri yathābhūtaparijñānāni) are a set of original contemplations found in Yogācāra works. These were seen as very important contemplative methods by the authors of the ''Bodhisattvabhūmi''. They were considered to lead to awakening, and were linked with the thirty-seven factors leading to Awakening. The four investigations and the corresponding four correct cognitions (which are said to arise out of the investigations) are: # The investigation of the names f things(''nāmaparyeṣaṇā''), leads to correct cognition resulting from the investigation of names just for what they are, which is "just names" (''nāmamātra''), i.e. arbitrary linguistic signs. # The investigation of things (''vastuparyeṣaṇā''), leads to correct cognition resulting from the investigation of things. One sees things just for what they are, namely a mere presence or a thing-in-itself (''vastumātra''). One understands that this is apart from all labels and is inexpressible (''nirabhilāpya''). # The investigation of verbal designations suggesting and portraying an intrinsic nature (''svabhāva-prajñapti-paryeṣaṇā''), leads to correct cognition resulting from the investigation of such designations. One sees the designations just for what they are, namely as mere designations ('' prajñaptimātratā''). Thus, one sees the idea of intrinsic nature to be illusory like a hallucination or a dream. # The investigation of verbal designations expressing individuation and differences (''viśeṣaprajñaptiparyeṣaṇā''), leads to correct cognition resulting from the investigation of such designations. One sees the designations just for what they are, namely as mere designations. For example, a thing may be designated as existing or non-existing, but such designations do not apply to true reality or the thing-in-itself. The practice which leads to the realization of the true nature of things is based on the elimination of all conceptual proliferations (''prapañca'') and ideations (''
saṃjñā ''Saṃjñā'' (Sanskrit; Pali: ''sañña'') is a Buddhist term that is typically translated as "perception" or "cognition." It can be defined as grasping at distinguishing features or characteristics. ''Samjñā'' has multiple meanings dependi ...
'') that one superimposes on true reality''.Deleanu, Florin. ''"Meditative Practices in the Bodhisattvabhūmi: Quest for and Liberation through the Thing-In-Itself,"'' in Kragh 2013 pp. 896-897.'' The YBh states that the yogin must "repeatedly remove any ideation conducive to the proliferation directed at all phenomena and should consistently dwell on the thing-in-itself by a non-conceptualizing mental state which is focused on grasping only the object perceived without any characteristics".


Four prayogas

Various Yogācāra sources provide a four step process of realization leading to the path of seeing, these four are the four yogic practices (prayogas): * Yogic practice of observation (upalambha-prayoga) - Outer objects are observed to be nothing but mind. * Yogic practice of non-observation (anupalambha-prayoga) - Outer objects are not observed as such * Yogic practice of observation and non-observation (upalambhānupalambha-prayoga) - Outer objects being unobservable, a mind cognizing them is not observed either * Yogic practice of double non-observation (nopalambhopalambha-prayoga) - Not observing both, nonduality is observed This process is conceisely explained in the ''Trisvabhāvanirdeśa'' which says "through the observation of it being merely mind, a knowable object is not observed. Through not observing a knowable object, mind is not observed ither Through not observing both, the dharmadhātu is observed." Thus, the goal of meditation is a totally unified mind that goes beyond all concepts and language to directly know the undifferentiated "uniformity of phenomena" (dharmasamatāḥ) and the thing-in-itself, the supreme reality. The elimination of all concepts applies even to the very idea of mind only or "mere-cognizance" itself. As the '' Dharmadharmatāvibhāga'' states: "through eferentsbeing observed in this way, they are observed as mere cognizance. By virtue of observing them as mere cognizance, Referents are not observed, and through not observing referents, mere cognizance is not observed ither" This elimination of concepts and ideas is the basic framework applied by the bodhisattva to all meditative practices, including the different mindfulness meditations''.'' The three ''samādhis'' (meditative absorptions) are likewise adapted into this new framework. These three are the emptiness ('' śūnyatā''), wishlessness ('' apraṇihita''), and imagelessness (''ānimitta'') ''samādhis.''


Meditation

As the "school of yoga practitioners", meditative practice is discussed in various Yogācāra sources. The sixth chapter (the Maitreya Chapter) of the ''Saṃdhinirmocanasūtra'' focuses entirely on meditation. It extensively discusses the meditative aspects of ‘calm’ (śamatha) and ‘insight’ (vipaśyanā) from unique perspectives. Success in both of these is based on pure ethics and on pure views based on listening and reflecting (viśuddhaṃ śrutamayacintāmayadarśanam). Insight is paired with "objects consisting in images accompanied by reflection" (savikalpaṃ pratibimbaṃ) while tranquility is seen as based on objects consisting in images unaccompanied by reflection (nirvikalpaṃ pratibimbaṃ). Thus, insight meditation is based on the uninterrupted contemplation of mental images, while calming meditation is simply focusing on "the continuous flow of mind with uninterrupted attention". The ''Saṃdhinirmocana'' also states that the teachings themselves are an important object of meditative contemplation. This includes the Yogācāra teaching of consciousness-only, the teachings on the twofold emptiness (of self and phenomena), and the schematic analysis of the subject and its objects of consciousness. While insight meditation is initially based on conceptual reflection, these are gradually abandoned at later stages until the yogin lets go of all concepts, teachings, and mental images. Furthermore, at the higher stages of meditation, the calm and insight meditations must ultimately be blended or yoked together (yuganaddha) in a single state of one-pointedness of mind (cittaikāgratā). This unified state is described as that state in which the yogin: "realises that these images (pratibimba) which are the domain of concentration (samādhigocara) are nothing but representation (vijñaptimātra), and having realised this, he contemplates (manasikaroti) Suchness ( tathatā)."


History

Yogācāra, along with
Madhyamaka Madhyamaka ("middle way" or "centrism"; ; ; Tibetic languages, Tibetan: དབུ་མ་པ་ ; ''dbu ma pa''), otherwise known as Śūnyavāda ("the Śūnyatā, emptiness doctrine") and Niḥsvabhāvavāda ("the no Svabhava, ''svabhāva'' d ...
(Middle Way), is one of the two principal philosophical schools of Indian Mahāyāna Buddhism,Jones, Lindsay (Ed. in Chief)(2005). ''Encyclopedia of Religion''. (2nd Ed.) Volume 14; Masaaki, Hattori (Ed.)(1987 & 2005)"''Yogācāra''": p.9897. USA: Macmillan Reference. (v.14) though the related movement of Tathāgatagarbha-thought was also influential.


Origin and early Yogācāra

The Kushan Empire ruled much of north India during the early period of the Yogācāra school.">north_India.html" ;"title="Kushan Empire ruled much of north India">Kushan Empire ruled much of north India during the early period of the Yogācāra school. The term "yogācāra" (yoga practitioner) was originally used to refer to the Buddhist meditation adepts of the first centuries of the common era which were associated with the Sarvāstivāda and Sautrāntika traditions in north India (some of their key centers included Gandhara,
Kashmir Kashmir ( or ) is the Northwestern Indian subcontinent, northernmost geographical region of the Indian subcontinent. Until the mid-19th century, the term ''Kashmir'' denoted only the Kashmir Valley between the Great Himalayas and the Pir P ...
and Mathura). Modern scholars like Florin Deleanu have suggested that some yogis in this north Indian Buddhist milieu gradually adopted Mahāyāna ideas, eventually developing into a separate movement (a process which was complete by the 5th century).Deleanu, F. (Ed.). (2006). ''The Chapter on the Mundane Path (Laukikamārga): A Trilingual Edition(Sanskrit, Tibetan, Chinese), Annotated Translation and Introductory Study (2 vol),'' p. 162. Tokyo:International Institute for Buddhist Studies.Kragh, U.T. (editor), ''The Foundation for Yoga Practitioners'': ''The Buddhist Yogācārabhūmi Treatise and Its Adaptation in India, East Asia, and Tibet, Volume 1,'' pp. 30-31''.'' Harvard University, Department of South Asian studies, 2013. According to Deleanu, the Chinese '' Dhyana Sutras'' indicate just such a gradual adoption of Mahāyāna elements. One of the earliest texts of the Mahāyāna Yogācāra tradition proper is the ''Saṃdhinirmocana Sūtra'' (''Unraveling the Profound Intent'') which might be as early as the first or second century CE. It includes new theories such as the basis-consciousness ( ''ālaya-vijñāna''), the doctrine of ''vijñapti-mātra'' and the "three natures" (''trisvabhāva''). However, these theories were not completely new, as they have predecessors in older theories held by previous Buddhist schools, such as the Sautrāntika theory of seeds ('' bīja'') and the Sthavira theory of the bhavanga. Philosophically speaking, Richard King notes that Sautrāntikas defended a kind of representationalism, in which the mind only perceives an image (akara) or representation (vijñapti) of an external object (never the object itself). Mahayana Yogācāras adopted a similar model but removed the need for any external object which acts as a cause for the image. As the doctrinal trailblazer of the Yogācāra, the ''Saṃdhinirmocana'' also introduced the paradigm of the Three Turnings of the Wheel of Dharma, with its own teachings being placed into the final and definitive teaching (which supersedes those of the Prajñaparamita sutras). The early layers of the massive '' Yogācārabhūmi-śāstra'' (''Treatise on the Stages of the Yogācāras'') also contains very ancient Yogācāra material which is earlier than the ''Saṃdhinirmocana''. However, in its current form it is a "conglomeration of heterogenous materials" ( Schmithausen) which was finally compiled (perhaps by Asanga) after the ''Saṃdhinirmocana'' (hence, later layers quote the sutra directly). Modern scholars consider the ''Yogācārabhūmi'' to contain the work of several authors (mainly of a Mūlasarvāstivāda milieu), though it has traditionally been attributed in full to the bodhisattva Maitreya or to Asanga. It is influenced by Sarvāstivāda Abhidharma and Sautrāntika traditions, who also had similar texts called by the name ''"Yogācārabhūmi''", such as the ''Yogācārabhūmi of Saṅgharakṣa''.


Classical Yogācāra - Asaṅga and Vasubandhu

Yogācāra's systematic exposition owes much to the brothers Asaṅga (4th c. CE) and Vasubandhu (c. 4th - 5th CE). Little is known of these figures, but traditional accounts (in authors like Xuanzang) state that Asaṅga received Yogācāra teachings from the bodhisattva and future Buddha,
Maitreya Maitreya (Sanskrit) or Metteyya (Pali), is a bodhisattva who is regarded as the future Buddhahood, Buddha of this world in all schools of Buddhism, prophesied to become Maitreya Buddha or Metteyya Buddha.Williams, Paul. ''Mahayana Buddhism: Th ...
. However, there are various discrepancies between the Chinese and Tibetan traditions concerning these so called "five works of Maitreya". Modern scholars argue that the various works traditionally attributed to Maitreya are actually by other authors. According to Mario D'amato, the ''Mahāyānasūtrālamkāra'' and the ''Madhyāntavibhāga'' are part of a second phase of Yogācāra scholarship which took place after the completion of the ''Bodhisattvabhumi'', but before the composition of Asanga's ''Mahāyānasaṃgraha'' (which quotes the ''Mahāyānasūtrālamkāra'' as an authoritative text).D’AMATO, M. “THREE NATURES, THREE STAGES: AN INTERPRETATION OF THE YOGĀCĀRA ‘TRISVABHĀVA’-THEORY.” ''Journal of Indian Philosophy'', vol. 33, no. 2, 2005, pp. 185–207. ''JSTOR'', http://www.jstor.org/stable/23497001. Accessed 16 Feb. 2024. Regarding the '' Abhisamayalankara'' and the '' Ratnagotravibhaga'', modern scholars generally see these as the works of different authors. Asaṅga went on to write many of the key Yogācāra treatises such as the '' Mahāyānasaṃgraha'' and the '' Abhidharma-samuccaya''. Asaṅga also went on to convert his brother Vasubandhu to Yogācāra. Vasubandhu was a top scholar of Vaibhāṣika and Sautrāntika Abhidharma thought, and the '' Abhidharmakośakārikā'' is his main work which discusses the doctrines of these traditions. Vasubandhu also went on to write important Yogācāra works like the '' Twenty Verses'' and the ''Thirty Verses on Consciousness-Only''.


The middle period and the epistemological turn

The Yogācāra school held a prominent position in Indian Buddhism for centuries after the time of the two brothers. According to Lusthaus and Deleanu, after Asaṅga and Vasubandhu, two distinct "wings" of the school developed during the "Middle Period" of Yogācāra, the epistemological school and the scholastic school. Another important third movement developed a synthesis of Yogācāra with buddha-nature thought. Thus, the three main branches of the Yogācāra movement which developed during the so called middle period are:Delenau, Florin.
Mind Only and Beyond: History of Yogacara Meditation
', 2010, pp. 17-20. Lectures Series (Oxford Centre for Buddhist Studies).
# A logico-epistemic tradition (''pramāṇavāda'') focusing on issues of
epistemology Epistemology is the branch of philosophy that examines the nature, origin, and limits of knowledge. Also called "the theory of knowledge", it explores different types of knowledge, such as propositional knowledge about facts, practical knowle ...
(Sanskrit: pramāṇa) and
logic Logic is the study of correct reasoning. It includes both formal and informal logic. Formal logic is the study of deductively valid inferences or logical truths. It examines how conclusions follow from premises based on the structure o ...
(hetuvidyā), exemplified by such thinkers as Dignāga, Dharmakīrti, Dharmottara, Devendrabuddhi, Prajñakaragupta, Jinendrabuddhi, Śākyabuddhi # A scholastic and exegetical tradition which refined and elaborated Yogācāra Abhidharma and wrote various commentaries, exemplified by such thinkers as Gunamati, Asvabhāva, Sthiramati, Jinaputra, Dharmapāla, Śīlabhadra,
Xuanzang Xuanzang (; ; 6 April 6025 February 664), born Chen Hui or Chen Yi (), also known by his Sanskrit Dharma name Mokṣadeva, was a 7th-century Chinese Bhikkhu, Buddhist monk, scholar, traveller, and translator. He is known for the epoch-making ...
, and Vinītadeva (710-770). # The Yogācāra-tathāgatagarbha synthesis, found in the '' Laṅkāvatāra Sūtra'', and '' Ghanavyūha sūtra'', two treatises attributed to an author named Sāramati: the '' Ratnagotravibhāga,'' and '' Dharmadhātvaviśeṣaśāstra'' (''Dasheng fajie wuchabie lun'' 大乘法界無差別論), as well as in the works of Paramārtha (499-569 CE), including his translations: ''Buddhagotraśāstra'' (''Fó xìng lùn,'' 佛性論)'','' and ''Anuttarâśrayasūtra''. These branches of Yogācāra thought were not mutually exclusive however, for example, Vinītadeva wrote ''pramāṇa'' works as well as commentaries on the works of Vasubandhu. Aside from these, there were also Yogācāra authors writing commentaries on the Prajñaparamita sutras, including the unknown author of the ''Abhisamayālaṅkāra'' (AA)'','' Arya Vimuktisena (6th century) who commented on the AA, and Daṃṣṭrāsena (author of the ''Bṛhaṭṭīkā''). The doctrines of the exegetical tradition sometimes came under attack by other Buddhists, especially the notion of ''ālaya-vijñāna'', which was seen as close to the Hindu ideas of '' ātman'' and '' prakṛti.'' It was perhaps due to this that the logical tradition shifted over time to using the term ''citta-santāna'' instead'','' since it was easier to defend a "stream" ''(santāna)'' of thoughts as a doctrine that did not contradict not-self. By the end of the eighth century, the scholastic tradition had mostly become eclipsed by the pramāṇa tradition as well as by a new hybrid school that "combined basic Yogācāra doctrines with '' Tathāgatagarbha'' thought." The influential Pramāṇavāda tradition led by Dignāga and Dharmakīrti defined the main epistemological method for Indian Buddhism. Modern scholars see this school as having ushered in an "epistemological turn" for all
Indian philosophy Indian philosophy consists of philosophical traditions of the Indian subcontinent. The philosophies are often called darśana meaning, "to see" or "looking at." Ānvīkṣikī means “critical inquiry” or “investigation." Unlike darśan ...
. The pramāṇa tradition continued to thrive in Magadha (especially at Nalanda) as well as in
Kashmir Kashmir ( or ) is the Northwestern Indian subcontinent, northernmost geographical region of the Indian subcontinent. Until the mid-19th century, the term ''Kashmir'' denoted only the Kashmir Valley between the Great Himalayas and the Pir P ...
well into the 11th century. One of the most important late figures of this tradition was
Śaṅkaranandana Śaṅkaranandana (fl. c. 9th or 10th century), (Tibetan: ''Bde byed dga’ ba)'' was a Mahayana Buddhist philosopher, and a brahmin lay devotee (upāsaka) active in Kashmir in the Buddhist logico-epistemology, epistemological (''pramana'') traditi ...
(fl. c. 9th or 10th century), "the second Dharmakīrti"."Śaṅkaranandana" in Silk, Jonathan A (editor in chief). ''Brill's Encyclopedia of Buddhism Volume II: Lives.''


Yogācāra-tathāgatagarbha synthesis

According to Lusthaus, the synthetic Yogācāra-tathāgatagarbha school accepted the definition of '' tathāgatagarbha'' (the buddha-womb, buddha-source, or "buddha-within") as "permanent, pleasurable, ''self'', and pure" (''nitya, sukha, ātman, śuddha'') which is found in various '' tathāgatagarbha sutras.'' This hybrid school eventually went on to link the ''tathāgatagarbha'' with the ''ālaya-vijñāna'' doctrine. Some key sources of this tendency are the '' Laṅkāvatāra Sūtra'', '' Ratnagotravibhāga'' (''Uttaratantra''), and in China the '' Awakening of Faith.'' The synthesis of Yogācāra and Tathāgatagarbha thought became extremely influential in both East Asia and Tibet. During the sixth and seventh centuries, various forms of competing Yogācāra systems were popular in Chinese Buddhism. The translator Bodhiruci (6th century CE) for example, took a more "classical" approach while Ratnamati was attracted to Tathāgatagarbha thought and sought to translate texts like the ''Dasabhumika commentary'' accordingly. Their disagreement on this issue led to the end of their collaboration as co-translators. The translator Paramārtha is another example of a hybrid thinker. He promoted the theory of a "stainless consciousness" (''amala-vijñāna,'' a pure wisdom within all beings, i.e. the tathāgatagarbha), which is revealed once the ''ālaya-vijñāna'' is purified. According to Lusthaus, Xuanzang's travels to India and his translation work was an attempt to return to a more "orthodox" and "authentic" Indian Yogācāra, and thus put to rest the debates and confusions in the Chinese Yogācāra of his time. The ''Cheng Weishi Lun'' returns to the use of the theory of seeds instead of the ''tathāgatagarbha'' to explain how some beings can reach
Buddhahood In Buddhism, Buddha (, which in classic Indo-Aryan languages, Indic languages means "awakened one") is a title for those who are Enlightenment in Buddhism, spiritually awake or enlightened, and have thus attained the Buddhist paths to liberat ...
.Lusthaus, Dan, ''Buddhist Phenomenology: A Philosophical Investigation of Yogacara Buddhism and the Ch'eng Wei-shih Lun,'' Routledge, 2014, pp. 8-10. However, by the eighth century, the Yogācāra-tathāgatagarbha synthesis became the dominant interpretation of Yogācāra in East Asian Buddhism. Later Chinese thinkers like Fazang would thus criticize Xuanzang for failing to teach the ''tathāgatagarbha''. Karl Brunnhölzl notes that this syncretic tendency also existed in Indian Yogācāra scholasticism, but that it only became widespread during the later tantric era (when
Vajrayana ''Vajrayāna'' (; 'vajra vehicle'), also known as Mantrayāna ('mantra vehicle'), Guhyamantrayāna ('secret mantra vehicle'), Tantrayāna ('tantra vehicle'), Tantric Buddhism, and Esoteric Buddhism, is a Mahāyāna Buddhism, Mahāyāna Buddhis ...
became prominent) with the work of thinkers like Jñānaśrīmitra, Ratnākaraśānti, and Maitripa. Kashmir also became an important center for this tradition, as can be seen in the works of Kashmiri Yogacarins Sajjana and Mahājana.Kano, Kazuo. "Sajjana and Mahājana: Yogācāra Exegeses in the Eleventh Century Kashmir." ''Indogaku Bukkyogaku Kenkyu'' (''Journal of Indian and Buddhist Studies'') 69, no. 2 (2021): 118–124


Yogācāra and Madhyamaka

Yogācāra and Madhyamaka philosophers demonstrated two opposing tendencies throughout the history of Buddhist philosophy in India, an antagonistic stance which saw both systems as rival and incompatible views and another inclusive tendency which worked towards harmonizing their views.Komarovski, Yaroslav'', Visions of Unity: The Golden Paṇḍita Shakya Chokden's New Interpretation of Yogācāra and Madhyamaka''. Albany, New York: State University of New York Press, 2011, p. 74. Some authors like the Madhyamikas Bhaviveka, Candrakīrti, and Śāntideva, and the Yogācāras Asanga, Dharmapala, Sthiramati criticized the philosophical theories of the other tradition. While Indian Yogācāras criticized certain interpretations of Madhyamaka (which they term “those who misunderstand emptiness”), they never criticize the founders of Madhyamaka themselves ( Nāgārjuna and Āryadeva), and saw their work as implicitly in agreement with Yogācāra. This
inclusivism Inclusivism is one of several approaches in religious studies, anthropology, or civics to understand the relationship between different religions, societies, cultures, political factions etc. It asserts that there is beauty in the variety of diff ...
saw Nāgārjuna's teachings as needing further expansion and explication (since it was part of the "second turning" of the wheel of Dharma). Thus, Yogācāra thinkers affirmed the importance Nāgārjuna's work and some even wrote commentaries on Nāgārjuna's '' Mūlamadhyamakakārika'' as a way to draw out the implicit meaning of Madhyamaka and show it was compatible with Yogācāra. These include Asanga's ''Treatise on Comforming to the Middle Way'' (''Shun zhonglun'' 順中論) and Sthiramati's ''Mahayana Middle Way Commentary'' (''Dasheng zhongguanshi lun'' 大乘中觀釋論 T.30.1567)''.'' Similarly, Vasubandhu and Dharmapāla both wrote commentaries on Āryadeva's ''Catuḥśātaka'' (''Four Hundred Verses''). The harmonizing tendency can be seen in the work of philosophers like Kambala (5-6th century, author of the ''Ālokamālā''), Jñānagarbha (8th century), his student Śāntarakṣita (8th century) and Ratnākaraśānti (c. 1000). Śāntarakṣita (8th century), whose view was later called "Yogācāra-Svatantrika-Madhyamaka" by the Tibetan tradition, saw the Mādhyamika position as ultimately true and at the same time saw the Yogācāra view as a useful way to relate to conventional truth (which leads one to the ultimate).Shantarakshita & Ju Mipham (2005) pp.117-122 Ratnākaraśānti on the other hand saw Nagarjuna as agreeing with the intent of Yogācāra texts, while criticizing the interpretations of later Madhyamikas like Bhaviveka. Later Tibetan Buddhist thinkers like Shakya Chokden would also work to show the compatibility of the alikākāravāda sub-school with
Madhyamaka Madhyamaka ("middle way" or "centrism"; ; ; Tibetic languages, Tibetan: དབུ་མ་པ་ ; ''dbu ma pa''), otherwise known as Śūnyavāda ("the Śūnyatā, emptiness doctrine") and Niḥsvabhāvavāda ("the no Svabhava, ''svabhāva'' d ...
, arguing that it is in fact a form of
Madhyamaka Madhyamaka ("middle way" or "centrism"; ; ; Tibetic languages, Tibetan: དབུ་མ་པ་ ; ''dbu ma pa''), otherwise known as Śūnyavāda ("the Śūnyatā, emptiness doctrine") and Niḥsvabhāvavāda ("the no Svabhava, ''svabhāva'' d ...
. Likewise, the Seventh Karmapa Chödrak Gyamtso has a similar view which holds that the "profound important points and intents" of the two systems are one. Ju Mipham is also another Tibetan philosopher whose project is aimed as showing the harmony between Yogacara and Madhyamaka, arguing that there is only a very subtle difference between them, being a subtle clinging by Yogacaras to the existence of an "inexpressible, naturally luminous cognition" (''rig pa rang bzhin gyis ’od gsal ba'').


Yogācāra in East Asia

Translations of Indian Yogācāra texts were first introduced to China in the early 5th century CE. Among these was Guṇabhadra's translation of the '' Laṅkāvatāra Sūtra'' in four fascicles, which would also become important in the early history of Chan Buddhism. Influential 5th century figures include the translators Bodhiruci, Ratnamati, and Paramārtha.Paul, Diana. ''Philosophy of Mind in Sixth-Century China: Paramartha's Evolution of Consciousness.'' 1984. pp. 32-33 Their followers founded the Dilun (''Daśabhūmikā Commentary'') and Shelun (''Mahāyānasaṃgraha'') schools, both of which included Yogācāra and tathāgatagarbha elements. Modern scholars also hold that the '' Awakening of Faith'', a very influential work in East Asian Buddhism, was written by a member of the Dilun tradition.
Xuanzang Xuanzang (; ; 6 April 6025 February 664), born Chen Hui or Chen Yi (), also known by his Sanskrit Dharma name Mokṣadeva, was a 7th-century Chinese Bhikkhu, Buddhist monk, scholar, traveller, and translator. He is known for the epoch-making ...
(fl. c. 602 – 664) is famous for having made a dangerous journey to India in order to study Buddhism, obtain more indic Yogācāra sources.Liu, JeeLoo. ''An Introduction to Chinese Philosophy: From Ancient Philosophy to Chinese Buddhism.'' 2006. p. 220 Xuanzang spent over ten years in India traveling and studying under various Buddhist masters and drew on a variety of Indian sources in his studies. Upon his return to China, Xuanzang brought with him 657 Buddhist texts, including the ''Yogācārabhūmi'' and began the work of translating them. Xuanzang composed the '' Cheng Weishi Lun'' (''Discourse on the Establishment of Consciousness Only'') which drew on many Indian sources and commentaries and became a central work of East Asian Yogācāra.Liu, JeeLoo. ''An Introduction to Chinese Philosophy: From Ancient Philosophy to Chinese Buddhism.'' 2006. p. 221 Xuanzang's student Kuiji continued this tradition, writing several important commentaries. However, another student of Xuanzang, the Korean monk Wŏnch’ŭk, defended some of the doctrines of the Shelun school of Paramārtha, for which he was criticized by the followers of Kuiji. Wŏnch’ŭk's teachings were influential on the Yogācāra (''Beopsang'') of
Silla Silla (; Old Korean: wikt:徐羅伐#Old Korean, 徐羅伐, Yale romanization of Korean, Yale: Syerapel, Revised Romanization of Korean, RR: ''Seorabeol''; International Phonetic Alphabet, IPA: ) was a Korean kingdom that existed between ...
Korea. Both of these competing Yogācāra sub-sects were then imported to Japan where they became the two sub-sects (the northern and southern temple lineages) of the Hossō school.Green, Ronald S. (2020). Early Japanese Hosso in Relation to Silla Yogacara in Disputes between Nara'€™s Northern and Southern Temple Traditions. ''Journal of Korean Religions'', 11(1), 97–121. doi:10.1353/jkr.2020.0003 Xuanzang's school later came under criticism from later Chinese masters like Fazang and it became less influential as the fortunes of other native Chinese schools rose. Nevertheless, Yogācāra studies continued to be important at different times throughout Chinese history, including during the modern revival of Yogācāra in the 20th century.


Yogācāra in Tibet

Yogācāra is studied in all schools of Tibetan Buddhism, though it receives different emphasis in each of these. Yogācāra thought is an integral part of the history of
Tibetan Buddhism Tibetan Buddhism is a form of Buddhism practiced in Tibet, Bhutan and Mongolia. It also has a sizable number of adherents in the areas surrounding the Himalayas, including the Indian regions of Ladakh, Gorkhaland Territorial Administration, D ...
. It was first transmitted to Tibet by figures like Śāntarakṣita, Kamalaśīla and Atiśa. The Tibetan
Nyingma Nyingma (, ), also referred to as ''Ngangyur'' (, ), is the oldest of the four major schools of Tibetan Buddhism. The Nyingma school was founded by PadmasambhavaClaude Arpi, ''A Glimpse of the History of Tibet'', Dharamsala: Tibet Museum, 2013. ...
school and its
Dzogchen Dzogchen ( 'Great Completion' or 'Great Perfection'), also known as ''atiyoga'' ( utmost yoga), is a tradition of teachings in Indo-Tibetan Buddhism and Bön aimed at discovering and continuing in the ultimate ground of existence. The goal ...
teachings draw on both Madhyamaka and Yogācāra-Tathāgatagarbha thought. Similarly, Kagyu school figures like the Third Karmapa also rely on the Madhyamaka and Yogācāra-Tathāgatagarbha systems in their presentation of the ultimate view (termed Mahamudra in Kagyu). The Jonang school also developed its own synthetic philosophy which they termed ''shentong'' ("other-emptiness" ), which also included elements from Yogācāra, Madhyamaka and Tathāgatagarbha. In contrast, the Gelug and Sakya schools generally see Yogācāra as a lesser view than the Madhyamaka philosophy of Candrakirti, which is seen as the definitive view in these traditions. Today, Yogācāra topics remain important in Tibetan Buddhism and Yogācāra texts are widely studied. There are various debates and discussions among the Tibetan Buddhist schools regarding key Yogācāra ideas, like '' svasaṃvedana'' (reflexive awareness) and the foundational consciousness. Furthermore, the debates between the other-emptiness and self-emptiness views are also similar in some ways to the historical debates between Yogācāra-Tathāgatagarbha and Madhyamaka, though the specific viewpoints have evolved further and changed in complex ways. Modern thinkers continue to discuss Yogācāra issues, and attempt to synthesize it with Madhyamaka. For example, Ju Mipham, the 19th-century Rimé commentator, wrote a commentary on Śāntarakṣita's synthesis arguing that the ultimate intent of Madhyamaka and Yogācāra is the same.


Influence

Virtually all contemporary schools of Mahāyāna Buddhism are influenced by Yogācāra to some extent. This includes modern East Asian Buddhist traditions (like
Zen Zen (; from Chinese: ''Chán''; in Korean: ''Sŏn'', and Vietnamese: ''Thiền'') is a Mahayana Buddhist tradition that developed in China during the Tang dynasty by blending Indian Mahayana Buddhism, particularly Yogacara and Madhyamaka phil ...
and
Pure Land Pure Land is a Mahayana, Mahayana Buddhist concept referring to a transcendent realm emanated by a buddhahood, buddha or bodhisattva which has been purified by their activity and Other power, sustaining power. Pure lands are said to be places ...
) and
Tibetan Buddhism Tibetan Buddhism is a form of Buddhism practiced in Tibet, Bhutan and Mongolia. It also has a sizable number of adherents in the areas surrounding the Himalayas, including the Indian regions of Ladakh, Gorkhaland Territorial Administration, D ...
. Zen was heavily influenced by Yogācāra sources, especially the ''Laṅkāvatāra Sūtra.'' In Tibetan Buddhism, Yogācāra sources are still widely studied and several are part of the monastic education curriculum in various traditions.Kapstein, Matthew T. ''Tibetan Buddhism: A Very Short Introduction''. New York: Oxford University Press, 2014, p. 64. Some influential Yogācāra texts in Tibetan Buddhism include: Asanga's ''Abhidharma-samuccaya'', and the " Five Treatises of Maitreya" including the ''Mahayanasutralankara'', and the ''Ratnagotravibhāga''. Hindu philosophers such as Vācaspati Miśra, Utpaladeva, Abhinavagupta, and Śrīharṣa were also influenced by Yogacara ideas and responded to their theories in their own works.


Textual corpus


Sūtras

The '' Saṃdhinirmocana Sūtra'' (''Sūtra of the Explanation of the Profound Secrets''; 2nd century CE), is a key early Yogācāra sutra which is considered to be the foundational sutra for the Yogācāra tradition.Keown, Damien (2004). ''A Dictionary of Buddhism,'' p. 302. Oxford University Press. . There are two Indian commentaries to this, one by Asanga and one by Jñanagarbha. The '' Avataṃsaka Sūtra'' (which includes the '' Daśabhūmikasūtra'') also contains numerous teachings on mind-only and is very influential for East Asian Buddhism. Vasubandhu's ''Commentary on the Daśabhūmikasūtra'' is an important commentary to this.Makeham, John. ''Transforming Consciousness: Yogacara Thought in Modern China'', p. 6. Oxford University Press, 2014 Another text, the ''Mahāyānābhidharmasūtra'' is often quoted in Yogācāra works and is assumed to also be an early Yogācāra sutra''.''Kritzer (2005), p. xii. The '' Laṅkāvatāra Sūtra'' also later assumed considerable importance in East Asia, and portions of this text were considered by
Étienne Lamotte Étienne Paul Marie Lamotte (; 21 November 1903 – 5 May 1983) was a Belgian priest and Professor of Greek at the Catholic University of Louvain, but was better known as an Indologist and the greatest authority on Buddhism in the West in his ...
as being contemporaneous with the ''Saṃdhinirmocana''. This text equates the Yogācāra theory of ''ālayavijñāna'' with the ''tathāgatagarbha'' (buddha-nature) and thus seems to be part of the tradition which sought to merge Yogācāra with ''tathāgatagarbha'' thought. Another sutra which contains similar themes to the ''Laṅkāvatāra'' is the '' Ghanavyūha Sūtra''. All these five sutras are listed by Kuiji as key sutras for the Yogācāra school in his ''Commentary on the'' ''Cheng weishi lun'' (成唯識 論述記; Taishō no. 1830). Another lesser known sutra which was important in East Asian Yogācāra is the ''Buddha Land Sutra'' ('' Buddhabhūmi Sūtra''; Taishō vol. 16, no. 680) which along with its commentaries, teaches that the pure land is not a physical place, but a symbol for wisdom. This sutra was important enough in India to have at least two Indian Yogācāra commentaries written on it, Śīlabhadra's '' Buddhabhūmi''-''vyākhyāna'' and Bandhuprabha's ''Buddhabhūmyupadeśa''.Keenan, John P. ''A Study of the Buddhabhūmyupadeś́a: The Doctrinal Development of the Notion of Wisdom in Yogācāra Thought''. Institute of Buddhist Studies and Bukkyō Dendō Kyōkai America, 2014. There are also various Indian, Chinese and Tibetan commentaries to these various
Mahayana sutras The Mahayana sutras are Buddhist texts that are accepted as wikt:canon, canonical and authentic Buddhist texts, ''buddhavacana'' in Mahayana, Mahayana Buddhist sanghas. These include three types of sutras: Those spoken by the Buddha; those spoke ...
. Furthermore, the Prajñaparamita sutras are also important sources in Yogācāra, even though most do not cover specifically "Yogācāra" doctrines. This is shown by the fact that various Yogācāra commentaries were written on Prajñaparamita sutras, including commentaries by Asanga (''Vajracchedikākāvyākhyā''), Vasubandhu, Dignāga, Daṃṣṭrasena (''Bṛhaṭṭīkā''), Ratnākaraśānti (various), and the '' Abhisamayālaṅkāra''.


Treatises

Yogācāra authors wrote numerous scholastic and philosophical treatises (''
śāstra ''Śāstra'' ( ) is a Sanskrit word that means "precept, rules, manual, compendium, book or treatise" in a general sense.Monier Williams, Monier Williams' Sanskrit-English Dictionary, Oxford University Press, Article on 'zAstra'' The word is ge ...
'') and commentaries (''ṭīkā, bhāṣya'', ''vyākhyāna,'' etc). The following is a list in historical order and only includes specifically Yogācāra-Vijñānavāda figures and works:Williams (2008), pp. 87-88.Brunnholzl, Karl. ''Luminous Heart: The Third Karmapa on Consciousness, Wisdom, and Buddha Nature'' pp. 10-11. Snow Lion Publications, The Nitartha Institute (2009). * '' Yogācārabhūmi-śāstra,'' the earliest Yogācāra treatise, a massive encyclopedic work on Yogācāra theory and praxis which is a composite work reflecting various stages of historical development (compiled 3rd to 5th century CE).Kritzer (2005), p. xvii, xix. * '' Mahāyānasūtrālamkāra'' and its ''bhāṣya,'' traditionally attributed to the bodhisattva Maitreya or Asanga, modern scholars like D'amato place this text (together with the commentary) after the ''Bodhisattvabhumi'', but before Asanga.D’AMATO, M. “THREE NATURES, THREE STAGES: AN INTERPRETATION OF THE YOGĀCĀRA ‘TRISVABHĀVA’-THEORY.” ''Journal of Indian Philosophy'', vol. 33, no. 2, 2005, pp. 185–207. ''JSTOR'', http://www.jstor.org/stable/23497001. Accessed 16 Feb. 2024. * '' Madhyāntavibhāga'' (''Distinguishing the Middle and the Extremes''), another work of the "second phase" of post-''Yogācārabhūmi'' Yogācāra thought, traditionally attributed to the bodhisattva Maitreya who is said to have revealed it to Asanga.D’AMATO, M. “THREE NATURES, THREE STAGES: AN INTERPRETATION OF THE YOGĀCĀRA ‘TRISVABHĀVA’-THEORY.” ''Journal of Indian Philosophy'', vol. 33, no. 2, 2005, pp. 185–207. ''JSTOR'', http://www.jstor.org/stable/23497001. Accessed 16 Feb. 2024. * '' Dharmadharmatāvibhāga (Distinguishing Dharmas and Dharmata),'' another work of the so called " Maitreya corpus" * Nāgamitra's (3rd-4th century?) ''Kāyatrayāvatāramukha'' (a treatise on the trikaya and the three natures) * The works of Asaṅga (4th-5th century CE): the '' Mahāyānasaṃgraha'' and the '' Abhidharma-samuccaya''.Lugli, Ligeia
Asaṅga, oxfordbibliographies.com
LAST MODIFIED: 25 NOVEMBER 2014, DOI: 10.1093/OBO/9780195393521-0205.
* Vasubandhu's (4th-5th century CE) '' Viṃśaṭikā-kārikā'' (Treatise in Twenty Stanzas), '' Triṃśikā-kārikā'' (Treatise in Thirty Stanzas), ''Vyākhyāyukti'' ("Proper Mode of Exposition"), ''Karmasiddhiprakarana'' ("A Treatise on
Karma Karma (, from , ; ) is an ancient Indian concept that refers to an action, work, or deed, and its effect or consequences. In Indian religions, the term more specifically refers to a principle of cause and effect, often descriptively called ...
"), and ''Pañcaskandhaprakaraṇa'' (Explanation of the Five Aggregates).'' '' * ''Ālokamālāprakaraṇanāma'' (''An Explanation named 'Garland of Light) by Kambala (c. fifth to sixth century) which attempts to harmonize Madhyamaka and Yogācāra, mostly by assimilating Madhyamaka under Yogācāra. * The ''Saṃdhinirmocanasūtravyākhyāna'' is a commentary to the ''Saṃdhinirmocanasūtra'' attributed to Asanga, but this has been questioned by modern scholars.Lugli, Ligeia
Asaṅga, oxfordbibliographies.com
LAST MODIFIED: 25 NOVEMBER 2014, DOI: 10.1093/OBO/9780195393521-0205.
* '' Abhisamayālaṅkāra'' (''Ornament of Realization''), a commentary on the Prajñaparamita sutras. It is attributed to Maitreya-Asanga by Tibetan tradition, but it is unknown in Chinese sources. Modern scholars see this as a post-Asanga text. Makransky attributes it to Ārya Vimuktisena, the first commentator on this text.Brunnholzl, Karl'', When the Clouds Part: The Uttaratantra and Its Meditative Tradition as a Bridge between Sutra and Tantra,'' Shambhala Publications, 2015, p. 81. * Dignāga's '' Ālambanaparīkṣā'' and its ''vrtti'' (commentary) defend the view of consciousness-only using epistemological arguments * The Indian Paramārtha (499–569) translated many works to Chinese, and also wrote some original treatises and commentaries, possibly including the ''Buddhagotraśāstra'' (''Fo Xing Lun'') * Sthiramati (6th century), wrote numerous commentaries like ''Pañcaskandhakavibhāṣā'' and ''Triṃśikāvijñaptibhāṣya'' * '' Mahayana Awakening of Faith'' (author unknown) * Dharmapala of Nalanda (6th century), wrote commentaries to the ''Ālambanaparīkṣā'' and Āryadeva's ''Catuḥśataka'' * Asvabhāva, wrote ''Mahāyānasūtrālaṃkāra-ṭīkā'', ''Mahāyānasaṃgrahopanibandhana'' and a commentary on ''Ālokamālā'' * Dharmakīrti's (6th or 7th century) ''Pramānaṿārttika'' (''Commentary on Epistemology''), is mostly a work on pramana, but it also argues for consciousness-only * Śīlabhadra (529–645) - ''Buddhabhūmivyākhyāna'' * Xuanzang's (602-664) '' Cheng Wei Shi Lun'' is a large Chinese commentary on the '' Triṃśikā'' which draws on numerous Indian sources * Kuiji (632–682) - Various commentaries on texts like ''Cheng weishi lun, Heart-sutra, Madhyāntavibhāga'' etc. * Wŏnch'ŭk (613–696) - Commentaries on the ''Samdhinirmocanasutra'', ''Heart-sutra'', and '' Benevolent King Sutra'' * Wŏnhyo (617–686) - wrote commentaries on various works such as the ''Madhyāntavibhāga'' * Guṇaprabha - ''Bodhisattvabhūmiśīlaparivarta-bhāṣya'' * Jinaputra, wrote a commentary to the ''Abhidharmasamucchaya'' * Candragomī (sixth/seventh century) - ''Śiṣyalekha,'' ''Bodhisattvasaṃvaraviṃsaka'' * Vinītadeva (c. 645–715) - wrote commentaries on ''Viṃśatikā'', ''Triṃśika'' and ''Ālambanaparīkśā'' * Jñānacandra (eighth century) - Yogacaryābhāvanātātparyārthanirdeśa, a meditation manual * Sāgaramegha (eighth century) - ''Yogācārabhūmaubodhisattvabhūmivyākhyā,'' a large Yogācārabhūmi commentary * Sumatiśīla (late eighth century) wrote a commentary on Vasubandhu's ''Karmasiddhiprakaraṇa'' * Prajñakaragupta (8th-9th century) - ''Pramāṇavārttikālaṃkāra'' and ''Sahāvalambanirṇayasiddhi'', a proof of idealism *
Śaṅkaranandana Śaṅkaranandana (fl. c. 9th or 10th century), (Tibetan: ''Bde byed dga’ ba)'' was a Mahayana Buddhist philosopher, and a brahmin lay devotee (upāsaka) active in Kashmir in the Buddhist logico-epistemology, epistemological (''pramana'') traditi ...
(fl. c. 9th or 10th century) - ''Prajñālaṅkāra'' (''Ornament of Wisdom''), an exposition of ''vijñaptimātratā'' "Śaṅkaranandana" in Silk, Jonathan A (editor in chief). ''Brill's Encyclopedia of Buddhism Volume II: Lives.'' * Dharmakīrti of Sumatra - ''Durbodhālokā'' (''Light on the Hard-to-Illuminate''), a sub-commentary to the '' Abhisamayālaṃkāra-śāstra-vṛtti'' of Haribhadra.Sinclair, Ia
. ''Dharmakirti of Kedah: His, life, work and troubled times.''
Temasek Working Paper No. 2: 2021. Temasek History Research Centre ISEAS – Yusof Ishak Institute
* Jñānaśrīmitra (fl. 975-1025 C.E.) - ''Sākarasiddhi, Sākarasaṃgraha'', and ''Sarvajñāsiddhi'' * Ratnakīrti (11th century CE) - ''Ratnakīrtinibandhāvalī'' and ''Sarvajñāsiddhi'' * Ratnākāraśānti (10-11th century) - ''Prajñāpāramitopadeśa, Madhyamakālaṃkāropadeśa, Vijñaptimātratāsiddhi'', ''Triyānavyavasthāna'', ''Madhyamakālaṃkāravṛtti-Madhyamapratipadāsiddhi'' * Jñānaśrībhadra - commentaries on ''Laṅkāvatārasūtra,'' ''Mahāyānasūtrālaṃkāra,'' and ''Pramāṇavārttika'' * Sajjana (11th century) - ''Putralekha'', ''Mahāyānottaratantraśāstropadeśa'' and ''Sūtrālaṃkārapiṇḍārtha'' * Jōkei (1155–1213) - ''Gumei hosshin shū'' (''Anthology of Awakenings from Delusion'') * Ryōhen (1194–1252) - ''Kanjin kakumushō'' (''Précis on Contemplating the Mind and Awakening from the Dream'')


Criticisms

Thinkers from the ancient Indian realist schools, such as the Mimamsa, Vishishtadvaita, Dvaita, Nyaya, Yoga, Samkhya, Sauntrantika, Jain, Vaisesika, and others heavily criticized Yogacara, and composed refutations of the Yogacara position. Sankara, founder of the Advaita school, which holds a form of idealism, also was harshly critical of Yogacara. Sinha, Jadunath ''Indian Realism'' p. 149. Routledge, 2024.


See also

*
Madhyamaka Madhyamaka ("middle way" or "centrism"; ; ; Tibetic languages, Tibetan: དབུ་མ་པ་ ; ''dbu ma pa''), otherwise known as Śūnyavāda ("the Śūnyatā, emptiness doctrine") and Niḥsvabhāvavāda ("the no Svabhava, ''svabhāva'' d ...
*
Mahayana Mahāyāna ( ; , , ; ) is a term for a broad group of Buddhist traditions, Buddhist texts#Mahāyāna texts, texts, Buddhist philosophy, philosophies, and practices developed in ancient India ( onwards). It is considered one of the three main ex ...
*
Idealism Idealism in philosophy, also known as philosophical realism or metaphysical idealism, is the set of metaphysics, metaphysical perspectives asserting that, most fundamentally, reality is equivalent to mind, Spirit (vital essence), spirit, or ...
* Vedanta * Kashmir Shaivism * School of the Heart-Mind * Mimamsa * Chandrakirti


Notes


References


Sources

* Bayer, Achim (2012)
''Addenda and Corrigenda to The Theory of Karman in the Abhidharmasamuccaya, 2012''
Hamburg: Zentrum für Buddhismuskunde. * * Keenan, John P. (1993). ''Yogācarā''. pp. 203–212 published in Yoshinori, Takeuchi; with Van Bragt, Jan; Heisig, James W.; O'Leary, Joseph S.; Swanson, Paul L.(1993). ''Buddhist Spirituality: Indian, Southeast Asian, Tibetan, and Early Chinese.'' New York City: The Crossroad Publishing Company. * * * Norbu, Namkhai (2001), ''The Precious Vase: Instructions on the Base of Santi Maha Sangha''. Shang Shung Edizioni. Second revised edition. (Translated from the Tibetan, edited and annotated by Adriano Clemente with the help of the author. Translated from Italian into English by Andy Lukianowicz.) * * Shantarakshita & Ju Mipham (2005). ''The Adornment of the Middle Way'' Padmakara Translation of Ju Mipham's commentary on Shantarakshita's root versus on his synthesis. * Sponberg, Alan (1979)
Dynamic Liberation in Yogacara Buddhism
Journal of the International Association of Buddhist Studies 2(1), pp. 44–64. * Stcherbatsky, Theodore (1936).
Mathyanta-Vibhanga, "Discourse on Discrimination between Middle and Extremes"
ascribed to Bodhisattva Maiteya and commented by Vasubhandu and Sthiramathi, translated from the sanscrit, Academy of Sciences USSR Press, Moscow/Leningrad. * Timme Kragh, Ulrich (editor) 2013, ''The Foundation for Yoga Practitioners'': ''The Buddhist Yogācārabhūmi Treatise and Its Adaptation in India, East Asia, and Tibet, Volume 1'' Harvard University, Department of South Asian studies. * Zim, Robert (1995). ''Basic ideas of Yogacara Buddhism.'' San Francisco State University. Source

(accessed: October 18, 2007).


External links



Surendranath Dasgupta, 1940

Richard King, ''Philosophy East & West'', vol. 44 no. 4, October 1994, pp. 659–683
"The mind-only teaching of Ching-ying Hui-Yuan"
(subtitle) "An early interpretation of Yogacara thought in China", Ming-Wood Liu, ''Philosophy East & West'', vol. 35 no. 4, October 1985, pp. 351–375
Yogacara Buddhism Research Association
articles, bibliographies, and links to other relevant sites. {{Consciousness Vajrayana Idealism Buddhist movements Buddhist philosophy Nonduality Buddhism in the Nara period Buddhist meditation