Filters in
topology
In mathematics, topology (from the Greek words , and ) is concerned with the properties of a geometric object that are preserved under continuous deformations, such as stretching, twisting, crumpling, and bending; that is, without closing ...
, a subfield of
mathematics, can be used to study
topological space
In mathematics, a topological space is, roughly speaking, a geometrical space in which closeness is defined but cannot necessarily be measured by a numeric distance. More specifically, a topological space is a set whose elements are called po ...
s and define all basic topological notions such a convergence,
continuity,
compactness, and more.
Filters
Filter, filtering or filters may refer to:
Science and technology
Computing
* Filter (higher-order function), in functional programming
* Filter (software), a computer program to process a data stream
* Filter (video), a software component tha ...
, which are special
families
Family (from la, familia) is a group of people related either by consanguinity (by recognized birth) or affinity (by marriage or other relationship). The purpose of the family is to maintain the well-being of its members and of society. Ideal ...
of
subsets of some given set, also provide a common framework for defining various types of
limits of functions such as limits from the left/right, to infinity, to a point or a set, and many others. Special types of filters called have many useful technical properties and they may often be used in place of arbitrary filters.
Filters have generalizations called (also known as ) and , all of which appear naturally and repeatedly throughout topology. Examples include
neighborhood filters/
bases/subbases and
uniformities. Every filter is a prefilter and both are filter subbases. Every prefilter and filter subbase is contained in a unique smallest filter, which they are said to . This establishes a relationship between filters and prefilters that may often be exploited to allow one to use whichever of these two notions is more technically convenient. There is a certain
preorder on families of sets, denoted by
that helps to determine exactly when and how one notion (filter, prefilter, etc.) can or cannot be used in place of another. This preorder's importance is amplified by the fact that it also defines the notion of filter convergence, where by definition, a filter (or prefilter)
to a point if and only if
where
is that point's
neighborhood filter In topology and related areas of mathematics, the neighbourhood system, complete system of neighbourhoods, or neighbourhood filter \mathcal(x) for a point x in a topological space is the collection of all neighbourhoods of x.
Definitions
Neighbou ...
. Consequently, subordination also plays an important role in many concepts that are related to convergence, such as
cluster point
In mathematics, a limit point, accumulation point, or cluster point of a set S in a topological space X is a point x that can be "approximated" by points of S in the sense that every neighbourhood of x with respect to the topology on X also contai ...
s and limits of functions. In addition, the
relation which denotes
and is expressed by saying that
also establishes a relationship in which
is to
as a subsequence is to a sequence (that is, the relation
which is called , is for filters the analog of "is a subsequence of").
Filters were introduced by
Henri Cartan in 1937 and subsequently used by
Bourbaki in their book as an alternative to the similar notion of a
net
Net or net may refer to:
Mathematics and physics
* Net (mathematics), a filter-like topological generalization of a sequence
* Net, a linear system of divisors of dimension 2
* Net (polyhedron), an arrangement of polygons that can be folded up ...
developed in 1922 by
E. H. Moore
Eliakim Hastings Moore (; January 26, 1862 – December 30, 1932), usually cited as E. H. Moore or E. Hastings Moore, was an American mathematician.
Life
Moore, the son of a Methodist minister and grandson of US Congressman Eliakim H. Moore, di ...
and
H. L. Smith.
Filters can also be used to characterize the notions of
sequence
In mathematics, a sequence is an enumerated collection of objects in which repetitions are allowed and order matters. Like a set, it contains members (also called ''elements'', or ''terms''). The number of elements (possibly infinite) is calle ...
and
net
Net or net may refer to:
Mathematics and physics
* Net (mathematics), a filter-like topological generalization of a sequence
* Net, a linear system of divisors of dimension 2
* Net (polyhedron), an arrangement of polygons that can be folded up ...
convergence. But unlike
[Sequences and nets in a space are maps from ]directed set
In mathematics, a directed set (or a directed preorder or a filtered set) is a nonempty set A together with a reflexive and transitive binary relation \,\leq\, (that is, a preorder), with the additional property that every pair of elements ha ...
s like the natural number
In mathematics, the natural numbers are those numbers used for counting (as in "there are ''six'' coins on the table") and ordering (as in "this is the ''third'' largest city in the country").
Numbers used for counting are called ''cardinal ...
, which in general maybe entirely unrelated to the set and so they, and consequently also their notions of convergence, are not intrinsic to sequence and net convergence, filter convergence is defined in terms of subsets of the topological space
and so it provides a notion of convergence that is completely intrinsic to the topological space; indeed, the
category of topological spaces can be
equivalently defined entirely in terms of filters. Every net induces a canonical filter and dually, every filter induces a canonical net, where this induced net (resp. induced filter) converges to a point if and only if the same is true of the original filter (resp. net). This characterization also holds for many other definitions such as cluster points. These relationships make it possible to switch between filters and nets, and they often also allow one to choose whichever of these two notions (filter or net) is more convenient for the problem at hand.
However, assuming that "
subnet
A subnetwork or subnet is a logical subdivision of an IP network. Updated by RFC 6918. The practice of dividing a network into two or more networks is called subnetting.
Computers that belong to the same subnet are addressed with an identical ...
" is defined using either of its most popular definitions (which are those
given by Willard and
by Kelley), then in general, this relationship does extend to subordinate filters and subnets because as
detailed below, there exist subordinate filters whose filter/subordinate–filter relationship cannot be described in terms of the corresponding net/subnet relationship; this issue can however be resolved by using a less commonly encountered definition of "subnet", which is that of an
AA–subnet.
Thus filters/prefilters and this single preorder
provide a framework that seamlessly ties together fundamental topological concepts such as
topological spaces
In mathematics, a topological space is, roughly speaking, a geometrical space in which closeness is defined but cannot necessarily be measured by a numeric distance. More specifically, a topological space is a set whose elements are called point ...
(
via neighborhood filters),
neighborhood base In topology and related areas of mathematics, the neighbourhood system, complete system of neighbourhoods, or neighbourhood filter \mathcal(x) for a point x in a topological space is the collection of all neighbourhoods of x.
Definitions
Neighbour ...
s,
convergence
Convergence may refer to:
Arts and media Literature
*''Convergence'' (book series), edited by Ruth Nanda Anshen
*Convergence (comics), "Convergence" (comics), two separate story lines published by DC Comics:
**A four-part crossover storyline that ...
,
various limits of functions, continuity,
compactness, sequences (via
sequential filters), the filter equivalent of "subsequence" (subordination),
uniform space
In the mathematical field of topology, a uniform space is a set with a uniform structure. Uniform spaces are topological spaces with additional structure that is used to define uniform properties such as completeness, uniform continuity and unifo ...
s, and more; concepts that otherwise seem relatively disparate and whose relationships are less clear.
Motivation
Archetypical example of a filter
The
archetypical
The concept of an archetype (; ) appears in areas relating to behavior, historical psychology, and literary analysis.
An archetype can be any of the following:
# a statement, pattern of behavior, prototype, "first" form, or a main model that ot ...
example of a filter is the
at a point
in a topological space
which is the
family of sets
In set theory and related branches of mathematics, a collection F of subsets of a given set S is called a family of subsets of S, or a family of sets over S. More generally, a collection of any sets whatsoever is called a family of sets, set fami ...
consisting of all neighborhoods of
By definition, a
neighborhood of some given point is any subset
whose
topological interior contains this point; that is, such that
Importantly, neighborhoods are required to be open sets; those are called .
The fundamental properties shared by neighborhood filters, which are listed below, ultimately became the definition of a "filter."
A is a set
of subsets of
that satisfies all of the following conditions:
- : – just as since is always a neighborhood of (and of anything else that it contains);
- : – just as no neighborhood of is empty;
- : If – just as the intersection of any two neighborhoods of is again a neighborhood of ;
- : If then – just as any subset of that contains a neighborhood of will necessarily a neighborhood of (this follows from and the definition of "a neighborhood of ").
Generalizing sequence convergence by using sets − determining sequence convergence without the sequence
A is by definition a
map
A map is a symbolic depiction emphasizing relationships between elements of some space, such as objects, regions, or themes.
Many maps are static, fixed to paper or some other durable medium, while others are dynamic or interactive. Although ...
from the
natural numbers into the space
The original notion of convergence in a
topological space
In mathematics, a topological space is, roughly speaking, a geometrical space in which closeness is defined but cannot necessarily be measured by a numeric distance. More specifically, a topological space is a set whose elements are called po ...
was that of a
sequence converging to some given point in a space, such as a
metric space
In mathematics, a metric space is a set together with a notion of '' distance'' between its elements, usually called points. The distance is measured by a function called a metric or distance function. Metric spaces are the most general set ...
.
With
metrizable space
In topology and related areas of mathematics, a metrizable space is a topological space that is homeomorphic to a metric space. That is, a topological space (X, \mathcal) is said to be metrizable if there is a metric d : X \times X \to , \infty) s ...
s (or more generally
first–countable spaces or
Fréchet–Urysohn space
In the field of topology, a Fréchet–Urysohn space is a topological space X with the property that for every subset S \subseteq X the closure of S in X is identical to the ''sequential'' closure of S in X.
Fréchet–Urysohn spaces are a speci ...
s), sequences usually suffices to characterize, or "describe", most topological properties, such as the closures of subsets or continuity of functions.
But there are many spaces where sequences can be used to describe even basic topological properties like closure or continuity.
This failure of sequences was the motivation for defining notions such as nets and filters, which fail to characterize topological properties.
Nets directly generalize the notion of a sequence since nets are, by definition, maps
from an arbitrary
directed set
In mathematics, a directed set (or a directed preorder or a filtered set) is a nonempty set A together with a reflexive and transitive binary relation \,\leq\, (that is, a preorder), with the additional property that every pair of elements ha ...
into the space
A sequence is just a net whose domain is
with the natural ordering. Nets have
their own notion of convergence, which is a direct generalization of sequence convergence.
Filters generalize sequence convergence in a different way by considering the values of a sequence.
To see how this is done, consider a sequence
which is by definition just a function
whose value at
is denoted by
rather than by the usual parentheses notation
that is commonly used for arbitrary functions.
Knowing only the
image (sometimes called "the range")
of the sequence is not enough to characterize its convergence; multiple sets are needed.
It turns out that the needed sets are the following,
[Technically, any infinite subfamily of this set of tails is enough to characterize this sequence's convergence. But in general, unless indicated otherwise, the set of tails is taken unless there is some reason to do otherwise.] which are called the of the sequence
:
These sets completely determine this sequence's convergence (or non–convergence) because given any point, this
sequence converges to it if and only if for every neighborhood
(of this point), there is some integer
such that
contains all of the points
This can be reworded as:
every neighborhood
must contain some set of the form
as a subset.
It is the above characterization that can be used with the above family of tails to determine convergence (or non–convergence) of the sequence
Specifically, with these in hand, the
is no longer needed to determine convergence of this sequence (no matter what topology is placed on
).
By generalizing this observation, the notion of "convergence" can be extended from functions/sequences to families of sets.
The above set of tails of a sequence is in general not a filter but it does "" a filter via taking its (which consists of all supersets of all tails). The same is true of other important families of sets such as any
neighborhood basis In topology and related areas of mathematics, the neighbourhood system, complete system of neighbourhoods, or neighbourhood filter \mathcal(x) for a point x in a topological space is the collection of all neighbourhoods of x.
Definitions
Neighbour ...
at a given point, which in general is also not a filter but does generate a filter via its upward closure (in particular, it generates the neighborhood filter at that point). The properties that these families share led to the notion of a , also called a , which by definition is any family having the minimal properties necessary and sufficient for it to generate a filter via taking its
upward closure.
Nets vs. filters − advantages and disadvantages
Filters and nets each have their own advantages and drawbacks and there's no reason to use one notion exclusively over the other.
[Indeed, net convergence is defined using neighborhood filters while (pre)filters are directed sets with respect to so it is difficult to keep these notions completely separate.]
Depending on what is being proved, a proof may be made significantly easier by using one of these notions instead of the other. Both filters and nets can be used to completely
characterize any given topology.
Nets are direct generalizations of sequences and can often be used similarly to sequences, so the learning curve for nets is typically much less steep than that for filters.
However, filters, and
especially ultrafilters, have many more uses outside of topology, such as in
set theory
Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory, as a branch of mathematics, is mostly conce ...
,
mathematical logic
Mathematical logic is the study of formal logic within mathematics. Major subareas include model theory, proof theory, set theory, and recursion theory. Research in mathematical logic commonly addresses the mathematical properties of formal ...
,
model theory (
ultraproduct
The ultraproduct is a mathematical construction that appears mainly in abstract algebra and mathematical logic, in particular in model theory and set theory. An ultraproduct is a quotient of the direct product of a family of structures. All factor ...
s, for example),
abstract algebra
In mathematics, more specifically algebra, abstract algebra or modern algebra is the study of algebraic structures. Algebraic structures include group (mathematics), groups, ring (mathematics), rings, field (mathematics), fields, module (mathe ...
,
order theory
Order theory is a branch of mathematics that investigates the intuitive notion of order using binary relations. It provides a formal framework for describing statements such as "this is less than that" or "this precedes that". This article int ...
,
generalized convergence spaces,
Cauchy space In general topology and analysis, a Cauchy space is a generalization of metric spaces and uniform spaces for which the notion of Cauchy convergence still makes sense. Cauchy spaces were introduced by H. H. Keller in 1968, as an axiomatic tool deriv ...
s, and in the definition and use of
hyperreal number
In mathematics, the system of hyperreal numbers is a way of treating infinite and infinitesimal (infinitely small but non-zero) quantities. The hyperreals, or nonstandard reals, *R, are an extension of the real numbers R that contains numbers ...
s.
Like sequences, nets are and so they have the .
For example, like sequences, nets can be "plugged into" other functions, where "plugging in" is just
function composition.
Theorems related to functions and function composition may then be applied to nets.
One example is the universal property of
inverse limit
In mathematics, the inverse limit (also called the projective limit) is a construction that allows one to "glue together" several related objects, the precise gluing process being specified by morphisms between the objects. Thus, inverse limits can ...
s, which is defined in terms of composition of functions rather than sets and it is more readily applied to functions like nets than to sets like filters (a prominent example of an inverse limit is the
Cartesian product).
Filters may be awkward to use in certain situations, such as when switching between a filter on a space
and a filter on a dense subspace
In contrast to nets, filters (and prefilters) are families of and so they have the .
For example, if
is surjective then the
under
of an arbitrary filter or prefilter
is both easily defined and guaranteed to be a prefilter on
's domain, whereas it is less clear how to
pullback
In mathematics, a pullback is either of two different, but related processes: precomposition and fiber-product. Its dual is a pushforward.
Precomposition
Precomposition with a function probably provides the most elementary notion of pullback: i ...
(unambiguously/without
choice
A choice is the range of different things from which a being can choose. The arrival at a choice may incorporate motivators and models. For example, a traveler might choose a route for a journey based on the preference of arriving at a give ...
) an arbitrary sequence (or net)
so as to obtain a sequence or net in the domain (unless
is also injective and consequently a bijection, which is a stringent requirement). Similarly, the intersection of any collection of filters is once again a filter whereas it is not clear what this could mean for sequences or nets.
Because filters are composed of subsets of the very topological space
that is under consideration, topological set operations (such as
closure or
interior) may be applied to the sets that constitute the filter.
Taking the closure of all the sets in a filter is sometimes useful in
functional analysis
Functional analysis is a branch of mathematical analysis, the core of which is formed by the study of vector spaces endowed with some kind of limit-related structure (e.g. inner product, norm, topology, etc.) and the linear functions defined o ...
for instance.
Theorems and results about images or preimages of sets under a function may also be applied to the sets that constitute a filter; an example of such a result might be one of
continuity's characterizations in terms of preimages of open/closed sets or in terms of the interior/closure operators.
Special types of filters called have many useful properties that can significantly help in proving results.
One downside of nets is their dependence on the directed sets that constitute their domains, which in general may be entirely unrelated to the space
In fact, the class of nets in a given set
is too large to even be a set (it is a
proper class); this is because nets in
can have domains of
cardinality.
In contrast, the collection of all filters (and of all prefilters) on
is a set whose cardinality is no larger than that of
Similar to a
topology
In mathematics, topology (from the Greek words , and ) is concerned with the properties of a geometric object that are preserved under continuous deformations, such as stretching, twisting, crumpling, and bending; that is, without closing ...
on
a filter on
is "intrinsic to
" in the sense that both structures consist of subsets of
and neither definition requires any set that cannot be constructed from
(such as
or other directed sets, which sequences and nets require).
Preliminaries, notation, and basic notions
In this article, upper case Roman letters like
denote sets (but not families unless indicated otherwise) and
will denote the
power set
In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is post ...
of
A subset of a power set is called (or simply, ) where it is if it is a subset of
Families of sets will be denoted by upper case calligraphy letters such as
Whenever these assumptions are needed, then it should be assumed that
is non–empty and that
etc. are families of sets over
The terms "prefilter" and "filter base" are synonyms and will be used interchangeably.
Warning about competing definitions and notation
There are unfortunately several terms in the theory of filters that are defined differently by different authors.
These include some of the most important terms such as "filter."
While different definitions of the same term usually have significant overlap, due to the very technical nature of filters (and point–set topology), these differences in definitions nevertheless often have important consequences.
When reading mathematical literature, it is recommended that readers check how the terminology related to filters is defined by the author.
For this reason, this article will clearly state all definitions as they are used.
Unfortunately, not all notation related to filters is well established and some notation varies greatly across the literature (for example, the notation for the set of all prefilters on a set) so in such cases this article uses whatever notation is most self describing or easily remembered.
The theory of filters and prefilters is well developed and has a plethora of definitions and notations, many of which are now unceremoniously listed to prevent this article from becoming prolix and to allow for the easy look up of notation and definitions.
Their important properties are described later.
Sets operations
The or in
of a
family of sets
In set theory and related branches of mathematics, a collection F of subsets of a given set S is called a family of subsets of S, or a family of sets over S. More generally, a collection of any sets whatsoever is called a family of sets, set fami ...
is
and similarly the of
is
Throughout,
is a map.
Topology notation
Denote the set of all topologies on a set
Suppose
is any subset, and
is any point.
If
then
Nets and their tails
A is a set
together with a
preorder, which will be denoted by
(unless explicitly indicated otherwise), that makes
into an () ; this means that for all
there exists some
such that
For any indices
the notation
is defined to mean
while
is defined to mean that
holds but it is true that
(if
is
antisymmetric then this is equivalent to
).
A is a map from a non–empty directed set into
The notation
will be used to denote a net with domain
Warning about using strict comparison
If
is a net and
then it is possible for the set
which is called , to be empty (for example, this happens if
is an
upper bound
In mathematics, particularly in order theory, an upper bound or majorant of a subset of some preordered set is an element of that is greater than or equal to every element of .
Dually, a lower bound or minorant of is defined to be an eleme ...
of the
directed set
In mathematics, a directed set (or a directed preorder or a filtered set) is a nonempty set A together with a reflexive and transitive binary relation \,\leq\, (that is, a preorder), with the additional property that every pair of elements ha ...
).
In this case, the family
would contain the empty set, which would prevent it from being a prefilter (defined later).
This is the (important) reason for defining
as
rather than
or even
and it is for this reason that in general, when dealing with the prefilter of tails of a net, the strict inequality
may not be used interchangeably with the inequality
Filters and prefilters
The following is a list of properties that a family
of sets may possess and they form the defining properties of filters, prefilters, and filter subbases. Whenever it is necessary, it should be assumed that
Many of the properties of
defined above and below, such as "proper" and "directed downward," do not depend on
so mentioning the set
is optional when using such terms. Definitions involving being "upward closed in
" such as that of "filter on
" do depend on
so the set
should be mentioned if it is not clear from context.
\text X containing
called the , and
is said to this filter. This filter is equal to the intersection of all filters on
that are supersets of
The –system generated by
denoted by
will be a prefilter and a subset of
Moreover, the filter generated by
is equal to the upward closure of
meaning
However,
if
is a prefilter (although
is always an upward closed filter base for
).
* A
–smallest (meaning smallest relative to
) filter containing a filter subbase
will exist only under certain circumstances. It exists, for example, if the filter subbase
happens to also be a prefilter. It also exists if the filter (or equivalently, the –system) generated by
is
principal, in which case
is the unique smallest prefilter containing
Otherwise, in general, a
–smallest filter containing
might not exist. For this reason, some authors may refer to the –system generated by
as However, if a
–smallest prefilter does exist (say it is denoted by
) then contrary to usual expectations, it is necessarily equal to "
the prefilter generated by " (that is,
is possible). And if the filter subbase
happens to also be a prefilter but not a -system then unfortunately, "
the prefilter generated by this prefilter" (meaning
) will not be
(that is,
is possible even when
is a prefilter), which is why this article will prefer the accurate and unambiguous terminology of "the
–system generated by
".
of a filter and that is a of if is a filter and where for filters,
* Importantly, the expression "is a filter of" is for filters the analog of "is a sequence of". So despite having the prefix "sub" in common, "is a filter of" is actually the of "is a sequence of." However, can also be written which is described by saying " is subordinate to " With this terminology, "is ordinate to" becomes for filters (and also for prefilters) the analog of "is a sequence of," which makes this one situation where using the term "subordinate" and symbol may be helpful.
There are no prefilters on
(nor are there any nets valued in
), which is why this article, like most authors, will automatically assume without comment that
whenever this assumption is needed.
Basic examples
Named examples
- The singleton set is called the or It is the unique filter on because it is a subset of every filter on ; however, it need not be a subset of every prefilter on
- The dual ideal is also called (despite not actually being a filter). It is the only dual ideal on that is not a filter on
- If is a topological space and then the
neighborhood filter In topology and related areas of mathematics, the neighbourhood system, complete system of neighbourhoods, or neighbourhood filter \mathcal(x) for a point x in a topological space is the collection of all neighbourhoods of x.
Definitions
Neighbou ...
at is a filter on By definition, a family is called a (resp. a ) at if and only if is a prefilter (resp. is a filter subbase) and the filter on that generates is equal to the neighborhood filter The subfamily of open neighborhoods is a filter base for Both prefilters also form a bases for topologies on with the topology generated being coarser than This example immediately generalizes from neighborhoods of points to neighborhoods of non–empty subsets
- is an
if for some sequence
- is an or a on if is a filter on generated by some elementary prefilter. The filter of tails generated by a sequence that is not eventually constant is necessarily an ultrafilter. Every principal filter on a countable set is sequential as is every cofinite filter on a countably infinite set. The intersection of finitely many sequential filters is again sequential.
- The set of all cofinite subsets of (meaning those sets whose complement in is finite) is proper if and only if is infinite (or equivalently, is infinite), in which case is a filter on known as the or the on If is finite then is equal to the dual ideal which is not a filter. If is infinite then the family of complements of singleton sets is a filter subbase that generates the Fréchet filter on As with any family of sets over that contains the kernel of the Fréchet filter on is the empty set:
- The intersection of all elements in any non–empty family is itself a filter on called the or of which is why it may be denoted by Said differently, Because every filter on has as a subset, this intersection is never empty. By definition, the infimum is the finest/largest (relative to ) filter contained as a subset of each member of
* If are filters then their infimum in is the filter If are prefilters then is a prefilter that is coarser (with respect to ) than both (that is, ); indeed, it is one of the finest such prefilters, meaning that if is a prefilter such that then necessarily More generally, if are non−empty families and if then and is a
greatest element
In mathematics, especially in order theory, the greatest element of a subset S of a partially ordered set (poset) is an element of S that is greater than every other element of S. The term least element is defined dually, that is, it is an elem ...
(with respect to ) of
- Let and let
The or of denoted by is the smallest (relative to ) dual ideal on containing every element of as a subset; that is, it is the smallest (relative to ) dual ideal on containing as a subset.
This dual ideal is where is the –system generated by
As with any non–empty family of sets, is contained in filter on if and only if it is a filter subbase, or equivalently, if and only if is a filter on in which case this family is the smallest (relative to ) filter on containing every element of as a subset and necessarily
- Let and let
The or of denoted by if it exists, is by definition the smallest (relative to ) filter on containing every element of as a subset.
If it exists then necessarily (as defined above) and will also be equal to the intersection of all filters on containing
This supremum of exists if and only if the dual ideal is a filter on
The least upper bound of a family of filters may fail to be a filter. Indeed, if contains at least 2 distinct elements then there exist filters for which there does exist a filter that contains both
If is not a filter subbase then the supremum of does not exist and the same is true of its supremum in but their supremum in the set of all dual ideals on will exist (it being the degenerate filter ).
* If are prefilters (resp. filters on ) then is a prefilter (resp. a filter) if and only if it is non–degenerate (or said differently, if and only if mesh), in which case it is coarsest prefilters (resp. coarsest filter) on (with respect to ) that is finer (with respect to ) than both this means that if is any prefilter (resp. any filter) such that then necessarily in which case it is denoted by
Other examples
- Let and let which makes a prefilter and a filter subbase that is not closed under finite intersections. Because is a prefilter, the smallest prefilter containing is The –system generated by is In particular, the smallest prefilter containing the filter subbase is equal to the set of all finite intersections of sets in The filter on generated by is All three of the –system generates, and are examples of fixed, principal, ultra prefilters that are principal at the point is also an ultrafilter on
- Let be a topological space, and define where is necessarily finer than If is non–empty (resp. non–degenerate, a filter subbase, a prefilter, closed under finite unions) then the same is true of If is a filter on then is a prefilter but not necessarily a filter on although is a filter on equivalent to
- The set of all dense open subsets of a (non–empty) topological space is a proper –system and so also a prefilter. If the space is a
Baire space
In mathematics, a topological space X is said to be a Baire space if countable unions of closed sets with empty interior also have empty interior.
According to the Baire category theorem, compact Hausdorff spaces and complete metric spaces are e ...
, then the set of all countable intersections of dense open subsets is a –system and a prefilter that is finer than If (with ) then the set of all such that has finite Lebesgue measure is a proper –system and free prefilter that is also a proper subset
In mathematics, set ''A'' is a subset of a set ''B'' if all elements of ''A'' are also elements of ''B''; ''B'' is then a superset of ''A''. It is possible for ''A'' and ''B'' to be equal; if they are unequal, then ''A'' is a proper subset of ...
of The prefilters and are equivalent and so generate the same filter on
The prefilter is properly contained in, and not equivalent to, the prefilter consisting of all dense subsets of Since is a Baire space
In mathematics, a topological space X is said to be a Baire space if countable unions of closed sets with empty interior also have empty interior.
According to the Baire category theorem, compact Hausdorff spaces and complete metric spaces are e ...
, every countable intersection of sets in is dense in (and also comeagre
In the mathematical field of general topology, a meagre set (also called a meager set or a set of first category) is a subset of a topological space that is small or negligible in a precise sense detailed below. A set that is not meagre is calle ...
and non–meager) so the set of all countable intersections of elements of is a prefilter and –system; it is also finer than, and not equivalent to,
Ultrafilters
There are many other characterizations of "ultrafilter" and "ultra prefilter," which are listed in the article on
ultrafilter
In the mathematical field of order theory, an ultrafilter on a given partially ordered set (or "poset") P is a certain subset of P, namely a maximal filter on P; that is, a proper filter on P that cannot be enlarged to a bigger proper filter o ...
s. Important properties of ultrafilters are also described in that article.
B there exists some set
such that
* This characterization of "
is ultra" does not depend on the set
so mentioning the set
is optional when using the term "ultra."
For set (not necessarily even a subset of ) there exists some set such that
if it is a prefilter that is also ultra. Equivalently, it is a filter subbase that is ultra. A prefilter is ultra if and only if it satisfies any of the following equivalent conditions:
- is in with respect to which means that
-
* Although this statement is identical to that given below for ultrafilters, here is merely assumed to be a prefilter; it need not be a filter.
- is ultra (and thus an ultrafilter).
- is equivalent (with respect to ) to some ultrafilter.
* A filter subbase that is ultra is necessarily a prefilter. A filter subbase is ultra if and only if it is a maximal filter subbase with respect to (as above).
if it is a filter on that is ultra. Equivalently, an ultrafilter on is a filter that satisfies any of the following equivalent conditions:
- is generated by an ultra prefilter.
- For any
- This condition can be restated as: is partitioned by and its dual
- For any if then (a filter with this property is called a ).
* This property extends to any finite union of two or more sets.
- is a filter on ; meaning that if is a filter on such that then necessarily (this equality may be replaced by ).
* If is upward closed then So this characterization of ultrafilters as maximal filters can be restated as:
* Because subordination is for filters the analog of "is a subnet/subsequence of" (specifically, "subnet" should mean " AA–subnet," which is defined below), this characterization of an ultrafilter as being a "maximally subordinate filter" suggests that an ultrafilter can be interpreted as being analogous to some sort of "maximally deep net" (which could, for instance, mean that "when viewed only from " in some sense, it is indistinguishable from its subnets, as is the case with any net valued in a singleton set for example),
[For instance, one sense in which a net could be interpreted as being "maximally deep" is if all important properties related to (such as convergence for example) of any subnet is completely determined by in all topologies on In this case and its subnet become effectively indistinguishable (at least topologically) if one's information about them is limited to only that which can be described in solely in terms of and directly related sets (such as its subsets).] which is an idea that is actually made rigorous by ultranets. The ultrafilter lemma
In the mathematical field of set theory, an ultrafilter is a ''maximal proper filter'': it is a filter U on a given non-empty set X which is a certain type of non-empty family of subsets of X, that is not equal to the power set \wp(X) of X (suc ...
is then the statement that every filter ("net") has some subordinate filter ("subnet") that is "maximally subordinate" ("maximally deep").
The ultrafilter lemma
The following important theorem is due to
Alfred Tarski
Alfred Tarski (, born Alfred Teitelbaum;School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews ''School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews''. January 14, 1901 – October 26, 1983) was a Polish-American logician a ...
(1930).
A consequence of the ultrafilter lemma is that every filter is equal to the intersection of all ultrafilters containing it.
Assuming the axioms of
Zermelo–Fraenkel (ZF), the ultrafilter lemma follows from the
Axiom of choice
In mathematics, the axiom of choice, or AC, is an axiom of set theory equivalent to the statement that ''a Cartesian product of a collection of non-empty sets is non-empty''. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection ...
(in particular from
Zorn's lemma) but is strictly weaker than it. The ultrafilter lemma implies the Axiom of choice for finite sets. If dealing with
Hausdorff spaces, then most basic results (as encountered in introductory courses) in Topology (such as
Tychonoff's theorem
In mathematics, Tychonoff's theorem states that the product of any collection of compact topological spaces is compact with respect to the product topology. The theorem is named after Andrey Nikolayevich Tikhonov (whose surname sometimes is trans ...
for compact Hausdorff spaces and the
Alexander subbase theorem) and in
functional analysis
Functional analysis is a branch of mathematical analysis, the core of which is formed by the study of vector spaces endowed with some kind of limit-related structure (e.g. inner product, norm, topology, etc.) and the linear functions defined o ...
(such as the
Hahn–Banach theorem
The Hahn–Banach theorem is a central tool in functional analysis.
It allows the extension of bounded linear functionals defined on a subspace of some vector space to the whole space, and it also shows that there are "enough" continuous linear f ...
) can be proven using only the ultrafilter lemma; the full strength of the axiom of choice might not be needed.
Kernels
The kernel is useful in classifying properties of prefilters and other families of sets.
B
If
then
and this set is also equal to the kernel of the –system that is generated by
In particular, if
is a filter subbase then the kernels of all of the following sets are equal:
:(1)
(2) the –system generated by
and (3) the filter generated by
If
is a map then
Equivalent families have equal kernels.
Two principal families are equivalent if and only if their kernels are equal.
=Classifying families by their kernels
=
If
is a principal filter on
then
and
and
is also the smallest prefilter that generates
Family of examples: For any non–empty
the family
is free but it is a filter subbase if and only if no finite union of the form
covers
in which case the filter that it generates will also be free. In particular,
is a filter subbase if
is countable (for example,
the primes), a
meager set
In the mathematical field of general topology, a meagre set (also called a meager set or a set of first category) is a subset of a topological space that is small or negligible in a precise sense detailed below. A set that is not meagre is calle ...
in
a set of finite measure, or a bounded subset of
If
is a singleton set then
is a subbase for the Fréchet filter on
=Characterizing fixed ultra prefilters
=
If a family of sets
is fixed (that is,
) then
is ultra if and only if some element of
is a singleton set, in which case
will necessarily be a prefilter. Every principal prefilter is fixed, so a principal prefilter
is ultra if and only if
is a singleton set.
Every filter on
that is principal at a single point is an ultrafilter, and if in addition
is finite, then there are no ultrafilters on
other than these.
The next theorem shows that every ultrafilter falls into one of two categories: either it is free or else it is a principal filter generated by a single point.
Finer/coarser, subordination, and meshing
The preorder
that is defined below is of fundamental importance for the use of prefilters (and filters) in topology. For instance, this preorder is used to define the prefilter equivalent of "subsequence", where "
" can be interpreted as "
is a subsequence of
" (so "subordinate to" is the prefilter equivalent of "subsequence of"). It is also used to define prefilter convergence in a topological space.
The definition of
meshes with
which is closely related to the preorder
is used in topology to define
cluster point
In mathematics, a limit point, accumulation point, or cluster point of a set S in a topological space X is a point x that can be "approximated" by points of S in the sense that every neighbourhood of x with respect to the topology on X also contai ...
s.
Two families of sets
and are , indicated by writing
if
If
do not mesh then they are . If
then
are said to if
mesh, or equivalently, if the of
which is the family
does not contain the empty set, where the trace is also called the of
''Example'': If
is a
subsequence
In mathematics, a subsequence of a given sequence is a sequence that can be derived from the given sequence by deleting some or no elements without changing the order of the remaining elements. For example, the sequence \langle A,B,D \rangle is a ...
of
then
is subordinate to
in symbols:
and also
Stated in plain English, the prefilter of tails of a subsequence is always subordinate to that of the original sequence.
To see this, let
be arbitrary (or equivalently, let
be arbitrary) and it remains to show that this set contains some
For the set
to contain
it is sufficient to have
Since
are strictly increasing integers, there exists
such that
and so
holds, as desired.
Consequently,
The left hand side will be a subset of the right hand side if (for instance) every point of
is unique (that is, when
is injective) and
is the even-indexed subsequence
because under these conditions, every tail
(for every
) of the subsequence will belong to the right hand side filter but not to the left hand side filter.
For another example, if
is any family then
always holds and furthermore,
A non-empty family that is coarser than a filter subbase must itself be a filter subbase.
Every filter subbase is coarser than both the –system that it generates and the filter that it generates.
If
are families such that
the family
is ultra, and
then
is necessarily ultra. It follows that any family that is equivalent to an ultra family will necessarily ultra. In particular, if
is a prefilter then either both
and the filter
it generates are ultra or neither one is ultra.
The relation
is
reflexive and
transitive, which makes it into a
preorder on
The relation
is
antisymmetric but if
has more than one point then it is
symmetric
Symmetry (from grc, συμμετρία "agreement in dimensions, due proportion, arrangement") in everyday language refers to a sense of harmonious and beautiful proportion and balance. In mathematics, "symmetry" has a more precise definiti ...
.
Equivalent families of sets
The preorder
induces its canonical
equivalence relation on
where for all
is to
if any of the following equivalent conditions hold:
- The upward closures of are equal.
Two upward closed (in
) subsets of
are equivalent if and only if they are equal.
If
then necessarily
and
is equivalent to
Every
equivalence class other than
contains a unique representative (that is, element of the equivalence class) that is upward closed in
Properties preserved between equivalent families
Let
be arbitrary and let
be any family of sets. If
are equivalent (which implies that
) then for each of the statements/properties listed below, either it is true of
or else it is false of
:
- Not empty
- Proper (that is, is not an element)
* Moreover, any two degenerate families are necessarily equivalent.
- Filter subbase
- Prefilter
* In which case generate the same filter on (that is, their upward closures in are equal).
- Free
- Principal
- Ultra
- Is equal to the trivial filter
* In words, this means that the only subset of that is equivalent to the trivial filter the trivial filter. In general, this conclusion of equality does not extend to non−trivial filters (one exception is when both families are filters).
- Meshes with
- Is finer than
- Is coarser than
- Is equivalent to
Missing from the above list is the word "filter" because this property is preserved by equivalence.
However, if
are filters on
then they are equivalent if and only if they are equal; this characterization does extend to prefilters.
Equivalence of prefilters and filter subbases
If
is a prefilter on
then the following families are always equivalent to each other:
- ;
- the –system generated by ;
- the filter on generated by ;
and moreover, these three families all generate the same filter on
(that is, the upward closures in
of these families are equal).
In particular, every prefilter is equivalent to the filter that it generates.
By transitivity, two prefilters are equivalent if and only if they generate the same filter.
Every prefilter is equivalent to exactly one filter on
which is the filter that it generates (that is, the prefilter's upward closure).
Said differently, every equivalence class of prefilters contains exactly one representative that is a filter.
In this way, filters can be considered as just being distinguished elements of these equivalence classes of prefilters.
A filter subbase that is also a prefilter can be equivalent to the prefilter (or filter) that it generates.
In contrast, every prefilter is equivalent to the filter that it generates.
This is why prefilters can, by and large, be used interchangeably with the filters that they generate while filter subbases cannot.
Set theoretic properties and constructions relevant to topology
Trace and meshing
If
is a prefilter (resp. filter) on
then the trace of
which is the family
is a prefilter (resp. a filter) if and only if
mesh (that is,
), in which case the trace of
is said to be .
The trace is always finer than the original family; that is,
If
is ultra and if
mesh then the trace
is ultra.
If
is an ultrafilter on
then the trace of
is a filter on
if and only if
For example, suppose that
is a filter on
is such that
Then
mesh and
generates a filter on
that is strictly finer than
When prefilters mesh
Given non–empty families
the family
satisfies
and
If
is proper (resp. a prefilter, a filter subbase) then this is also true of both
In order to make any meaningful deductions about
from
needs to be proper (that is,
which is the motivation for the definition of "mesh".
In this case,
is a prefilter (resp. filter subbase) if and only if this is true of both
Said differently, if
are prefilters then they mesh if and only if
is a prefilter.
Generalizing gives a well known characterization of "mesh" entirely in terms of subordination (that is,
):
Two prefilters (resp. filter subbases)
mesh if and only if there exists a prefilter (resp. filter subbase)
such that
and
If the least upper bound of two filters
exists in
then this least upper bound is equal to
Images and preimages under functions
Throughout,
will be maps between non–empty sets.
Images of prefilters
Let
Many of the properties that
may have are preserved under images of maps; notable exceptions include being upward closed, being closed under finite intersections, and being a filter, which are not necessarily preserved.
Explicitly, if one of the following properties is true of
then it will necessarily also be true of
(although possibly not on the codomain
unless
is surjective):
ultra, ultrafilter, filter, prefilter, filter subbase, dual ideal, upward closed, proper/non–degenerate, ideal, closed under finite unions, downward closed, directed upward.
Moreover, if
is a prefilter then so are both
The image under a map
of an ultra set
is again ultra and if
is an ultra prefilter then so is
If
is a filter then
is a filter on the range
but it is a filter on the codomain
if and only if
is surjective.
Otherwise it is just a prefilter on
and its upward closure must be taken in
to obtain a filter.
The upward closure of
is
where if
is upward closed in
(that is, a filter) then this simplifies to:
If
then taking
to be the inclusion map
shows that any prefilter (resp. ultra prefilter, filter subbase) on
is also a prefilter (resp. ultra prefilter, filter subbase) on
Preimages of prefilters
Let
Under the assumption that
is
surjective:
is a prefilter (resp. filter subbase, –system, closed under finite unions, proper) if and only if this is true of
However, if
is an ultrafilter on
then even if
is surjective (which would make
a prefilter), it is nevertheless still possible for the prefilter
to be neither ultra nor a filter on
If
is not surjective then denote the trace of
by
where in this case particular case the trace satisfies:
and consequently also:
This last equality and the fact that the trace
is a family of sets over
means that to draw conclusions about
the trace
can be used in place of
and the
can be used in place of
For example:
is a prefilter (resp. filter subbase, –system, proper) if and only if this is true of
In this way, the case where
is not (necessarily) surjective can be reduced down to the case of a surjective function (which is a case that was described at the start of this subsection).
Even if
is an ultrafilter on
if
is not surjective then it is nevertheless possible that
which would make
degenerate as well. The next characterization shows that degeneracy is the only obstacle. If
is a prefilter then the following are equivalent:
- is a prefilter;
- is a prefilter;
- ;
- meshes with
and moreover, if
is a prefilter then so is
If
and if
denotes the inclusion map then the trace of
is equal to
This observation allows the results in this subsection to be applied to investigating the trace on a set.
Subordination is preserved by images and preimages
The relation
is preserved under both images and preimages of families of sets.
This means that for families
Moreover, the following relations always hold for family of sets
:
where equality will hold if
is surjective.
Furthermore,
If
then
and
where equality will hold if
is injective.
Products of prefilters
Suppose
is a family of one or more non–empty sets, whose product will be denoted by
and for every index
let
denote the canonical projection.
Let
be non−empty families, also indexed by
such that
for each
The of the families
is defined identically to how the basic open subsets of the
product topology
In topology and related areas of mathematics, a product space is the Cartesian product of a family of topological spaces equipped with a natural topology called the product topology. This topology differs from another, perhaps more natural-s ...
are defined (had all of these
been topologies). That is, both the notations
denote the family of all subsets
such that
for all but finitely many
and where
for any one of these finitely many exceptions (that is, for any
such that
necessarily
).
When every
is a filter subbase then the family
is a filter subbase for the filter on
generated by
If
is a filter subbase then the filter on
that it generates is called the .
If every
is a prefilter on
then
will be a prefilter on
and moreover, this prefilter is equal to the coarsest prefilter
such that
for every
However,
may fail to be a filter on
even if every
is a filter on
Convergence, limits, and cluster points
Throughout,
is a
topological space
In mathematics, a topological space is, roughly speaking, a geometrical space in which closeness is defined but cannot necessarily be measured by a numeric distance. More specifically, a topological space is a set whose elements are called po ...
.
Prefilters vs. filters
With respect to maps and subsets, the property of being a prefilter is in general more well behaved and better preserved than the property of being a filter. For instance, the image of a prefilter under some map is again a prefilter; but the image of a filter under a non–surjective map is a filter on the codomain, although it will be a prefilter. The situation is the same with preimages under non–injective maps (even if the map is surjective). If
is a proper subset then any filter on
will not be a filter on
although it will be a prefilter.
One advantage that filters have is that they are distinguished representatives of their equivalence class (relative to
), meaning that any equivalence class of prefilters contains a unique filter. This property may be useful when dealing with equivalence classes of prefilters (for instance, they are useful in the construction of completions of
uniform space
In the mathematical field of topology, a uniform space is a set with a uniform structure. Uniform spaces are topological spaces with additional structure that is used to define uniform properties such as completeness, uniform continuity and unifo ...
s via Cauchy filters). The many properties that characterize ultrafilters are also often useful. They are used to, for example, construct the
Stone–Čech compactification In the mathematical discipline of general topology, Stone–Čech compactification (or Čech–Stone compactification) is a technique for constructing a universal map from a topological space ''X'' to a compact Hausdorff space ''βX''. The Ston ...
. The use of ultrafilters generally requires that the ultrafilter lemma be assumed. But in the many fields where the
axiom of choice
In mathematics, the axiom of choice, or AC, is an axiom of set theory equivalent to the statement that ''a Cartesian product of a collection of non-empty sets is non-empty''. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection ...
(or the
Hahn–Banach theorem
The Hahn–Banach theorem is a central tool in functional analysis.
It allows the extension of bounded linear functionals defined on a subspace of some vector space to the whole space, and it also shows that there are "enough" continuous linear f ...
) is assumed, the ultrafilter lemma necessarily holds and does not require an addition assumption.
A note on intuition
Suppose that
is a non–principal filter on an infinite set
has one "upward" property (that of being closed upward) and one "downward" property (that of being directed downward).
Starting with any
there always exists some
that is a subset of
; this may be continued ad infinitum to get a sequence
of sets in
with each
being a subset of
The same is true going "upward", for if
then there is no set in
that contains
as a proper subset.
Thus when it comes to limiting behavior (which is a topic central to the field of topology), going "upward" leads to a
dead end
Dead End or dead end may refer to:
* Dead end (street), a street connected only at one end with other streets, called by many other official names, including ''cul-de-sac''.
Film and television
* ''The Dead End'' (1914 film), directed by Davi ...
, while going "downward" is typically fruitful. So to gain understanding and intuition about how filters (and prefilter) relate to concepts in topology, the "downward" property is usually the one to concentrate on. This is also why so many topological properties can be described by using only prefilters, rather than requiring filters (which only differ from prefilters in that they are also upward closed).
The "upward" property of filters is less important for topological intuition but it is sometimes useful to have for technical reasons. For example, with respect to
every filter subbase is contained in a unique smallest filter but there may not exist a unique smallest prefilter containing it.
Limits and convergence
The following well known definition will be generalized to prefilters.
A point
is called a , , or of a subset
if every neighborhood of
contains a point of
different from
or equivalently, if
The set of all limit points of
is called the
derived set of
The closure of a set
is equal to the union of
together with the set of all limit points of
A family
is said to to a point or subset
of
written
if
in which case
is said to be a (or if
is a point, also ) of
Denote the set of all these limit points by
As usual,
is defined to mean that
and
is the limit point of
that is, if also
(If the notation "
" did not also require that the limit point
be unique then the
equals sign
The equals sign (British English, Unicode) or equal sign (American English), also known as the equality sign, is the mathematical symbol , which is used to indicate equality in some well-defined sense. In an equation, it is placed between tw ...
would no longer be guaranteed to be
transitive).
In words,
converges to a point if and only if
is than the neighborhood filter at that point. Explicitly,
means that every neighborhood
contains some
as a subset (that is,
); thus the following then holds:
In the above definitions, it suffices to check that
is finer than some (or equivalently, finer than every)
neighborhood base In topology and related areas of mathematics, the neighbourhood system, complete system of neighbourhoods, or neighbourhood filter \mathcal(x) for a point x in a topological space is the collection of all neighbourhoods of x.
Definitions
Neighbour ...
in
of the point or set (for example, such as
or
).
For example, if
then
is a limit point of the principle ultra prefilter
the ultrafilter that it generates, the neighborhood filter
and of any neighborhood basis at
The one and only limit point in
of the free prefilter
is
If
converges to a point or subset then the same is true of any family finer than
(such as
's restriction to any given subset of
for example).
Consequently, the limit points of a family
are the same as the limit points of its upward closure:
In particular, the limit points of a prefilter are the same as the limit points of the filter that it generates.
If a filter subbase converges to a point or subset then so does the filter that it generates, although the converse is not guaranteed. For example, the filter subbase
does not converge to
in
although the (principle ultra) filter that it generates does.
If
then because
if
then
Because
is an open set, a family
converges to
if and only if
so in particular, no filter or other non-degenerate family can converge to the empty set, which is why when dealing with convergent prefilters (or filter subbases), it is typically assumed (often without mention) that
Given
the following are equivalent for a prefilter
- converges to
- converges to the set
- converges to
- There exists a family equivalent to that converges to
If
is a prefilter and
then
converges to a point (or subset) of
if and only if this is true of the trace
If
is a filter subbase that converges to
then this is also true of the filter that it generates (and also of any prefilter equivalent to this filter, such as the -system generated by
).
Because subordination is transitive, if
and moreover, for every
both
and the maximal/ultrafilter
converge to
Thus every topological space
induces a canonical
convergence
Convergence may refer to:
Arts and media Literature
*''Convergence'' (book series), edited by Ruth Nanda Anshen
*Convergence (comics), "Convergence" (comics), two separate story lines published by DC Comics:
**A four-part crossover storyline that ...
defined by
At the other extreme, the neighborhood filter
is the smallest (that is, coarsest) filter on
that converges to
that is, any filter converging to
must contain
as a subset. Said differently, the family of filters that converge to
consists exactly of those filter on
that contain
as a subset.
Consequently, the finer the topology on
then the prefilters exist that have any limit points in
Cluster points
Say that
is a or an of a family
if
meshes with the neighborhood filter at
; that is, if
The set of all cluster points of
is denoted by
Explicitly, this means that
and every neighborhood
of
When
is a prefilter then the definition of "
mesh" can be characterized entirely in terms of the preorder
More generally, given
say that
if
meshes with the neighborhood filter of
; that is, if
In the above definitions, it suffices to check that
meshes with some (or equivalently, meshes with every)
neighborhood base In topology and related areas of mathematics, the neighbourhood system, complete system of neighbourhoods, or neighbourhood filter \mathcal(x) for a point x in a topological space is the collection of all neighbourhoods of x.
Definitions
Neighbour ...
in
of
Two equivalent families of sets have the exact same limit points and also the same cluster points. No matter the topology, for every
both
and the principal ultrafilter
cluster at
For any
if
clusters at some
then
clusters at
No family clusters at
and if
If
clusters to a point or subset then the same is true of any family coarser than
Consequently, the cluster points of a family
are the same as the cluster points of its upward closure:
In particular, the cluster points of a prefilter are the same as the cluster points of the filter that it generates.
Given
the following are equivalent for a prefilter
:
- clusters at
- clusters at the set
- The family generated by clusters at
- There exists a family equivalent to that clusters at
- for every neighborhood of
* If is a filter on then for every neighborhood
- There exists a prefilter subordinate to (that is, ) such that
* This is the filter equivalent of " is a cluster point of a sequence if and only if there exists a subsequence converging to
* In particular, if is a cluster point of a prefilter then is a prefilter subordinate to that converges to
The set
of all cluster points of a prefilter
satisfies
Consequently, the set
of all cluster points of prefilter
is a closed subset of
This also justifies the notation
for the set of cluster points.
In particular, if
is non-empty (so that
is a prefilter) then
since both sides are equal to
Properties and relationships
Just like sequences and nets, it is possible for a prefilter on a topological space of infinite cardinality to not have cluster points or limit points.
If
is a limit point of
then
is necessarily a limit point of any family
than
(that is, if
then
).
In contrast, if
is a cluster point of
then
is necessarily a cluster point of any family
than
(that is, if
mesh and
then
mesh).
Equivalent families and subordination
Any two equivalent families
can be used in the definitions of "limit of" and "cluster at" because their equivalency guarantees that
if and only if
and also that
if and only if
In essence, the preorder
is incapable of distinguishing between equivalent families.
Given two prefilters, whether or not they mesh can be characterized entirely in terms of subordination.
Thus the two most fundamental concepts related to (pre)filters to
Topology
In mathematics, topology (from the Greek words , and ) is concerned with the properties of a geometric object that are preserved under continuous deformations, such as stretching, twisting, crumpling, and bending; that is, without closing ...
(that is, limit and cluster points) can both be defined in terms of the subordination relation. This is why the preorder
is of such great importance in applying (pre)filters to Topology.
Limit and cluster point relationships and sufficient conditions
Every limit point of a non-degenerate family
is also a cluster point; in symbols:
This is because if
is a limit point of
then
mesh, which makes
a cluster point of
But in general, a cluster point need not be a limit point. For instance, every point in any given non-empty subset
is a cluster point of the principle prefilter
(no matter what topology is on
) but if
is Hausdorff and
has more than one point then this prefilter has no limit points; the same is true of the filter
that this prefilter generates.
However, every cluster point of an prefilter is a limit point. Consequently, if
is an prefilter then
that is to say, a point
will be a cluster point of an ultra prefilter
if and only if it is a limit point of
Although a cluster point of a filter need not be a limit point, there will always exist a finer filter that does converge to it; in particular, if
clusters at
then
is a filter subbase whose generated filter converges to
If
is a filter subbase such that
then
In particular, any limit point of a filter subbase subordinate to
is necessarily also a cluster point of
If
is a cluster point of a prefilter
then
is a prefilter subordinate to
that converges to
If
and if
is a prefilter on
then every cluster point of
belongs to
and any point in
is a limit point of a filter on
Primitive sets
A subset
is called if it is the set of limit points of some ultrafilter (or equivalently, some ultra prefilter). That is, if there exists an ultrafilter
such that
is equal to
which recall denotes the set of limit points of
Since limit points are the same as cluster points for ultra prefilters, a subset is primitive if and only if it is equal to the set
of cluster points of some ultra prefilter
For example, every closed singleton subset is primitive. The image of a primitive subset of
under a continuous map
is contained in a primitive subset of
Assume that
are two primitive subset of
If
is an open subset of
that intersects
then
for any ultrafilter
such that
In addition, if
are distinct then there exists some
and some ultrafilters
such that
and
Other results
If
is a
complete lattice then:
* The
limit inferior
In mathematics, the limit inferior and limit superior of a sequence can be thought of as limiting (that is, eventual and extreme) bounds on the sequence. They can be thought of in a similar fashion for a function (see limit of a function). For ...
of
is the
infimum
In mathematics, the infimum (abbreviated inf; plural infima) of a subset S of a partially ordered set P is a greatest element in P that is less than or equal to each element of S, if such an element exists. Consequently, the term ''greatest lo ...
of the set of all cluster points of
* The
limit superior
In mathematics, the limit inferior and limit superior of a sequence can be thought of as limiting (that is, eventual and extreme) bounds on the sequence. They can be thought of in a similar fashion for a function (see limit of a function). For a ...
of
is the
supremum of the set of all cluster points of
*
is a convergent prefilter
if and only if
In logic and related fields such as mathematics and philosophy, "if and only if" (shortened as "iff") is a biconditional logical connective between statements, where either both statements are true or both are false.
The connective is b ...
its limit inferior and limit superior agree; in this case, the value on which they agree is the limit of the prefilter.
Limits of functions defined as limits of prefilters
Suppose
is a map from a set into a topological space
and
If
is a limit point (respectively, a cluster point) of
then
is called a or (respectively, a )
Explicitly,
is a limit of
with respect to
if and only if
which can be written as
(by
definition of this notation) and stated as
If the limit
is unique then the arrow
may be replaced with an equals sign
The neighborhood filter
can be replaced with any family equivalent to it and the same is true of
The definition of a
convergent net
In mathematics, more specifically in general topology and related branches, a net or Moore–Smith sequence is a generalization of the notion of a sequence. In essence, a sequence is a function whose domain is the natural numbers. The codoma ...
is a special case of the above definition of a limit of a function.
Specifically, if
is a net then
where the left hand side states that
is a
limit while the right hand side states that
is a limit
with respect to
(as just defined above).
The table below shows how various types of limits encountered in analysis and topology can be defined in terms of the convergence of images (under
) of particular prefilters on the domain
This shows that prefilters provide a general framework into which many of the various definitions of limits fit.
The limits in the left–most column are defined in their usual way with their obvious definitions.
Throughout, let
be a map between topological spaces,
If
is Hausdorff then all arrows in the table may be replaced with equal signs and may be replaced with
,
is a sequence in
, -
,
, ⇔
, style='text-align:left;',
,
, -
,
, ⇔
, style='text-align:left;',
,
, -
,
, ⇔
, style='text-align:left;',
,
for a double-ended sequence
, -
,
, ⇔
, style='text-align:left;',
, style="padding-left:2em; padding-right:2em;",
a
seminorm In mathematics, particularly in functional analysis, a seminorm is a vector space norm that need not be positive definite. Seminorms are intimately connected with convex sets: every seminorm is the Minkowski functional of some absorbing disk ...
ed space;
By defining different prefilters, many other notions of limits can be defined; for example,
Divergence to infinity
Divergence of a real-valued function to infinity can be defined/characterized by using the prefilters
where
along
if and only if
and similarly,
along
if and only if
The family
can be replaced by any family equivalent to it, such as
for instance (in real analysis, this would correspond to replacing the strict inequality in the definition with and the same is true of
and
So for example, if
then
if and only if
holds. Similarly,
if and only if
or equivalently, if and only if
More generally, if
is valued in
(or some other seminormed vector space) and if
then
if and only if
holds, where
Filters and nets
This section will describe the relationships between prefilters and nets in great detail because of how important these details are applying filters to topology − particularly in switching from utilizing nets to utilizing filters and vice verse.
Nets to prefilters
In the definitions below, the first statement is the standard definition of a limit point of a net (respectively, a cluster point of a net) and it is gradually reworded until the corresponding filter concept is reached.
If
is a map and
is a net in
then
Prefilters to nets
A is a pair
consisting of a non–empty set
and an element
For any family
let
Define a canonical
preorder on pointed sets by declaring
There is a canonical map
defined by
If
then the tail of the assignment
starting at
is
Although
is not, in general, a partially ordered set, it is a
directed set
In mathematics, a directed set (or a directed preorder or a filtered set) is a nonempty set A together with a reflexive and transitive binary relation \,\leq\, (that is, a preorder), with the additional property that every pair of elements ha ...
if (and only if)
is a prefilter.
So the most immediate choice for the definition of "the net in
induced by a prefilter
" is the assignment
from
into
:\;&& (\operatorname(\mathcal), \leq) &&\,\to \;& X \\
&& (B, b) &&\,\mapsto\;& b \\
\end
that is,
If
is a prefilter on
is a net in
and the prefilter associated with
is
; that is:
[The set equality holds more generally: if the family of sets then the family of tails of the map (defined by ) is equal to ]
This would not necessarily be true had
been defined on a proper subset of
If
is a net in
then it is in general true that
is equal to
because, for example, the domain of
may be of a completely different cardinality than that of
(since unlike the domain of
the domain of an arbitrary net in
could have cardinality).
\to x.
is a cluster point of if and only if is a cluster point of
\right) and that if
is a net in
then (1)
and (2)
is a cluster point of
if and only if
is a cluster point of
By using
it follows that
It also follows that
is a cluster point of
if and only if
is a cluster point of
if and only if
is a cluster point of
Partially ordered net
The domain of the canonical net
is in general not partially ordered. However, in 1955 Bruns and Schmidt discovered
[Bruns G., Schmidt J.,Zur Aquivalenz von Moore-Smith-Folgen und Filtern, Math. Nachr. 13 (1955), 169-186.] a construction (detailed here:
Filter (set theory)#Partially ordered net) that allows for the canonical net to have a domain that is both partially ordered and directed; this was independently rediscovered by
Albert Wilansky in 1970.
Because the tails of this partially ordered net are identical to the tails of
(since both are equal to the prefilter
), there is typically nothing lost by assuming that the domain of the net associated with a prefilter is both directed partially ordered. If can further be assumed that the partially ordered domain is also a
dense order.
Subordinate filters and subnets
The notion of "
is subordinate to
" (written
) is for filters and prefilters what "
is a
subsequence
In mathematics, a subsequence of a given sequence is a sequence that can be derived from the given sequence by deleting some or no elements without changing the order of the remaining elements. For example, the sequence \langle A,B,D \rangle is a ...
of
" is for sequences.
For example, if
denotes the set of tails of
and if
denotes the set of tails of the subsequence
(where
) then
(which by definition means
) is true but
is in general false.
If
is a net in a topological space
and if
is the
neighborhood filter In topology and related areas of mathematics, the neighbourhood system, complete system of neighbourhoods, or neighbourhood filter \mathcal(x) for a point x in a topological space is the collection of all neighbourhoods of x.
Definitions
Neighbou ...
at a point
then
If
is an surjective open map,
and
is a prefilter on
that converges to
then there exist a prefilter
on
such that
and
is equivalent to
(that is,
).
Subordination analogs of results involving subsequences
The following results are the prefilter analogs of statements involving subsequences. The condition "
" which is also written
is the analog of "
is a subsequence of
" So "finer than" and "subordinate to" is the prefilter analog of "subsequence of." Some people prefer saying "subordinate to" instead of "finer than" because it is more reminiscent of "subsequence of."
Non–equivalence of subnets and subordinate filters
A subset
of a
preordered space
is or in
if for every
there exists some
such that
If
contains a tail of
then
is said to be or ; explicitly, this means that there exists some
such that
(that is,
for all
satisfying
). A subset is eventual if and only if its complement is not frequent (which is termed ).
A map
between two preordered sets is if whenever
satisfy
then
Subnets in the sense of Willard and
subnets in the sense of Kelley are the most commonly used definitions of "
subnet
A subnetwork or subnet is a logical subdivision of an IP network. Updated by RFC 6918. The practice of dividing a network into two or more networks is called subnetting.
Computers that belong to the same subnet are addressed with an identical ...
."
The first definition of a subnet was introduced by
John L. Kelley in 1955.
Stephen Willard introduced his own variant of Kelley's definition of subnet in 1970.
AA–subnets were introduced independently by Smiley (1957), Aarnes and Andenaes (1972), and Murdeshwar (1983); AA–subnets were studied in great detail by Aarnes and Andenaes but they are not often used.
Kelley did not require the map
to be order preserving while the definition of an AA–subnet does away entirely with any map between the two nets' domains and instead focuses entirely on
− the nets' common codomain.
Every Willard–subnet is a Kelley–subnet and both are AA–subnets.
In particular, if
is a Willard–subnet or a Kelley–subnet of
then
:Example: If
and
is a constant sequence and if
and
then
is an AA-subnet of
but it is neither a Willard-subnet nor a Kelley-subnet of
AA–subnets have a defining characterization that immediately shows that they are fully interchangeable with sub(ordinate)filters.
Explicitly, what is meant is that the following statement is true for AA–subnets:
If
are prefilters then
if and only if
is an AA–subnet of
If "AA–subnet" is replaced by "Willard–subnet" or "Kelley–subnet" then the above statement becomes . In particular, as
this counter-example demonstrates, the problem is that the following statement is in general false:
statement: If
are prefilters such that
is a Kelley–subnet of
Since every Willard–subnet is a Kelley–subnet, this statement remains false if the word "Kelley–subnet" is replaced with "Willard–subnet".
If "subnet" is defined to mean Willard–subnet or Kelley–subnet then nets and filters are not completely interchangeable because there exists a filter–sub(ordinate)filter relationships that cannot be expressed in terms of a net–subnet relationship between the two induced nets. In particular, the problem is that Kelley–subnets and Willard–subnets are fully interchangeable with subordinate filters. If the notion of "subnet" is not used or if "subnet" is defined to mean AA–subnet, then this ceases to be a problem and so it becomes correct to say that nets and filters are interchangeable. Despite the fact that AA–subnets do not have the problem that Willard and Kelley subnets have, they are not widely used or known about.
Topologies and prefilters
Throughout,
is a
topological space
In mathematics, a topological space is, roughly speaking, a geometrical space in which closeness is defined but cannot necessarily be measured by a numeric distance. More specifically, a topological space is a set whose elements are called po ...
.
Examples of relationships between filters and topologies
Bases and prefilters
Let
be a family of sets that covers
and define
for every
The definition of a
base for some topology can be immediately reworded as:
is a base for some topology on
if and only if
is a filter base for every
If
is a topology on
and
then the definitions of
is a
basis
Basis may refer to:
Finance and accounting
* Adjusted basis, the net cost of an asset after adjusting for various tax-related items
*Basis point, 0.01%, often used in the context of interest rates
* Basis trading, a trading strategy consisting ...
(resp.
subbase
In topology, a subbase (or subbasis, prebase, prebasis) for a topological space X with topology T is a subcollection B of T that generates T, in the sense that T is the smallest topology containing B. A slightly different definition is used by so ...
) for
can be reworded as:
is a base (resp. subbase) for
if and only if for every
is a filter base (resp. filter subbase) that generates the neighborhood filter of
at
Neighborhood filters
The archetypical example of a filter is the set of all neighborhoods of a point in a topological space.
Any
neighborhood basis In topology and related areas of mathematics, the neighbourhood system, complete system of neighbourhoods, or neighbourhood filter \mathcal(x) for a point x in a topological space is the collection of all neighbourhoods of x.
Definitions
Neighbour ...
of a point in (or of a subset of) a topological space is a prefilter. In fact, the definition of a
neighborhood base In topology and related areas of mathematics, the neighbourhood system, complete system of neighbourhoods, or neighbourhood filter \mathcal(x) for a point x in a topological space is the collection of all neighbourhoods of x.
Definitions
Neighbour ...
can be equivalently restated as: "a neighborhood base is any prefilter that is equivalent the neighborhood filter."
Neighborhood bases at points are examples of prefilters that are fixed but may or may not be principal.
If
has its usual topology and if
then any neighborhood filter base
of
is fixed by
(in fact, it is even true that
) but
is principal since
In contrast, a topological space has the
discrete topology
In topology, a discrete space is a particularly simple example of a topological space or similar structure, one in which the points form a , meaning they are ''isolated'' from each other in a certain sense. The discrete topology is the finest top ...
if and only if the neighborhood filter of every point is a principal filter generated by exactly one point.
This shows that a non–principal filter on an infinite set is not necessarily free.
The neighborhood filter of every point
in topological space
is fixed since its kernel contains
(and possibly other points if, for instance,
is not a
T1 space). This is also true of any neighborhood basis at
For any point
in a
T1 space (for example, a
Hausdorff space
In topology and related branches of mathematics, a Hausdorff space ( , ), separated space or T2 space is a topological space where, for any two distinct points, there exist neighbourhoods of each which are disjoint from each other. Of the m ...
), the kernel of the neighborhood filter of
is equal to the singleton set
However, it is possible for a neighborhood filter at a point to be principal but discrete (that is, not principal at a point).
A neighborhood basis
of a point
in a topological space is principal if and only if the kernel of
is an open set. If in addition the space is
T1 then
so that this basis
is principal if and only if
is an open set.
Generating topologies from filters and prefilters
Suppose
is not empty (and
). If
is a filter on
then
is a topology on
but the converse is in general false. This shows that in a sense, filters are topologies. Topologies of the form
where
is an filter on
are an even more specialized subclass of such topologies; they have the property that proper subset
is open or closed, but (unlike the
discrete topology
In topology, a discrete space is a particularly simple example of a topological space or similar structure, one in which the points form a , meaning they are ''isolated'' from each other in a certain sense. The discrete topology is the finest top ...
) never both. These spaces are, in particular, examples of
door spaces.
If
is a prefilter (resp. filter subbase, –system, proper) on
then the same is true of both
and the set
of all possible unions of one or more elements of
If
is closed under finite intersections then the set
is a topology on
with both
being
bases for it. If the –system
covers
then both
are also bases for
If
is a topology on
then
is a prefilter (or equivalently, a –system) if and only if it has the finite intersection property (that is, it is a filter subbase), in which case a subset
will be a basis for
if and only if
is equivalent to
in which case
will be a prefilter.
Topologies on directed sets and net convergence
Let
be a non–empty
directed set
In mathematics, a directed set (or a directed preorder or a filtered set) is a nonempty set A together with a reflexive and transitive binary relation \,\leq\, (that is, a preorder), with the additional property that every pair of elements ha ...
and let
where
Then
is a prefilter that
covers and if
is
totally ordered
In mathematics, a total or linear order is a partial order in which any two elements are comparable. That is, a total order is a binary relation \leq on some set X, which satisfies the following for all a, b and c in X:
# a \leq a ( reflexive ...
then
is also closed under finite intersections. This particular prefilter
forms a
base for a topology on
in which all sets of the form
are also open.
The same is true of the topology
where
is the filter on
generated by
With this topology, convergent nets can be viewed as continuous functions in the following way.
Let
be a topological space, let
let
be a
net
Net or net may refer to:
Mathematics and physics
* Net (mathematics), a filter-like topological generalization of a sequence
* Net, a linear system of divisors of dimension 2
* Net (polyhedron), an arrangement of polygons that can be folded up ...
in
and let
denote the set of all open neighborhoods of
If the net
converges to
then
is necessarily continuous although in general, the converse is false (for example, consider if
is constant and not equal to
).
But if in addition to continuity, the preimage under
of every
is not empty, then the net
will necessarily converge to
In this way, the empty set is all that separates net convergence and continuity.
Another way in which a convergent nets can be viewed as continuous functions is, for any given
and net
to first extend the net to a new net
where
is a new symbol, by defining
for every
If
is endowed with the topology
then
(that is, the net
converges to
) if and only if
is a continuous function. Moreover,
is always a
dense subset
In topology and related areas of mathematics, a subset ''A'' of a topological space ''X'' is said to be dense in ''X'' if every point of ''X'' either belongs to ''A'' or else is arbitrarily "close" to a member of ''A'' — for instance, the ra ...
of
Topological properties and prefilters
Neighborhoods and topologies
The neighborhood filter of a nonempty subset
in a topological space
is equal to the intersection of all neighborhood filters of all points in
If
then
is open in
if and only if whenever
is a filter on
and
then
Suppose
are topologies on
Then
is finer than
(that is,
) if and only if whenever
is a filter on
if
then
Consequently,
if and only if for every filter
and every
if and only if
However, it is possible that
while also for every filter
converges to point of
if and only if
converges to point of
Closure
If
then the following are equivalent:
- is a limit point of the prefilter that is,
- There exists a prefilter such that
- There exists a prefilter such that
- is a cluster point of the prefilter
- The prefilter meshes with the neighborhood filter
- The prefilter meshes with some (or equivalently, with every) prefilter of
The following are equivalent:
- is a limit points of
- There exists a prefilter such that
Closed sets
If
is not empty then the following are equivalent:
- is a closed subset of
- If is a prefilter on such that then
- If is a prefilter on such that is an accumulation points of then
- If is such that the neighborhood filter meshes with then
* The proof of this characterization depends the ultrafilter lemma, which depends on the
axiom of choice
In mathematics, the axiom of choice, or AC, is an axiom of set theory equivalent to the statement that ''a Cartesian product of a collection of non-empty sets is non-empty''. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection ...
.
Hausdorffness
The following are equivalent:
- is a
Hausdorff space
In topology and related branches of mathematics, a Hausdorff space ( , ), separated space or T2 space is a topological space where, for any two distinct points, there exist neighbourhoods of each which are disjoint from each other. Of the m ...
.
- Every prefilter on converges to at most one point in
- The above statement but with the word "prefilter" replaced by any one of the following: filter, ultra prefilter, ultrafilter.
Compactness
As discussed
in this article, the Ultrafilter Lemma is closely related to many important theorems involving compactness.
The following are equivalent:
- is a
compact space
In mathematics, specifically general topology, compactness is a property that seeks to generalize the notion of a closed and bounded subset of Euclidean space by making precise the idea of a space having no "punctures" or "missing endpoints", ...
.
- Every ultrafilter on converges to at least one point in
* That this condition implies compactness can be proven by using only the ultrafilter lemma. That compactness implies this condition can be proven without the ultrafilter lemma (or even the axiom of choice).
- The above statement but with the word "ultrafilter" replaced by any one of the following: ultra prefilter, filter, prefilter.
- For every filter there exists a filter such that and converges to some point of
- The above statement but with each instance of the word "filter" replaced by: prefilter.
- Every filter on has at least one cluster point in
* That this condition is equivalent to compactness can be proven by using only the ultrafilter lemma.
- The above statement but with the word "prefilter" replaced by any one of the following: prefilter.
- Alexander subbase theorem: There exists a
subbase
In topology, a subbase (or subbasis, prebase, prebasis) for a topological space X with topology T is a subcollection B of T that generates T, in the sense that T is the smallest topology containing B. A slightly different definition is used by so ...
such that every cover of by sets in has a finite subcover.
* That this condition is equivalent to compactness can be proven by using only the ultrafilter lemma.
If
is the set of all complements of compact subsets of a given topological space
then
is a filter on
if and only if
is compact.
Continuity
Let
is a map between topological spaces
Given
the following are equivalent:
- is
continuous
Continuity or continuous may refer to:
Mathematics
* Continuity (mathematics), the opposing concept to discreteness; common examples include
** Continuous probability distribution or random variable in probability and statistics
** Continuous ...
at
- Definition: For every neighborhood of there exists some neighborhood of such that
- If is a filter on such that then
- The above statement but with the word "filter" replaced by "prefilter".
The following are equivalent:
- is continuous.
- If is a prefilter on such that then
- If is a limit point of a prefilter then is a limit point of
- Any one of the above two statements but with the word "prefilter" replaced by any one of the following: filter.
If
is a prefilter on
is a cluster point of
is continuous, then
is a cluster point in
of the prefilter
A subset
of a topological space
is
dense
Density (volumetric mass density or specific mass) is the substance's mass per unit of volume. The symbol most often used for density is ''ρ'' (the lower case Greek letter rho), although the Latin letter ''D'' can also be used. Mathematically ...
in
if and only if for every
the trace
of the neighborhood filter
along
does not contain the empty set (in which case it will be a filter on
).
Suppose
is a continuous map into a Hausdorff
regular space
In topology and related fields of mathematics, a topological space ''X'' is called a regular space if every closed subset ''C'' of ''X'' and a point ''p'' not contained in ''C'' admit non-overlapping open neighborhoods. Thus ''p'' and ''C'' ca ...
and that
is a dense subset of a topological space
Then
has a
continuous extension
In mathematics, a continuous function is a function such that a continuous variation (that is a change without jump) of the argument induces a continuous variation of the value of the function. This means that there are no abrupt changes in value ...
if and only if for every
the prefilter
converges to some point in
Furthermore, this continuous extension will be unique whenever it exists.
Products
Suppose
is a non–empty family of non–empty topological spaces and that is a family of prefilters where each
is a prefilter on
Then the product
of these prefilters (defined above) is a prefilter on the product space
which as usual, is endowed with the
product topology
In topology and related areas of mathematics, a product space is the Cartesian product of a family of topological spaces equipped with a natural topology called the product topology. This topology differs from another, perhaps more natural-s ...
.
If
then
if and only if
Suppose
are topological spaces,
is a prefilter on
having
as a cluster point, and
is a prefilter on
having
as a cluster point.
Then
is a cluster point of
in the product space
However, if
then there exist sequences
such that both of these sequences have a cluster point in
but the sequence
does have a cluster point in
Example application: The ultrafilter lemma along with the axioms of
ZF imply
Tychonoff's theorem
In mathematics, Tychonoff's theorem states that the product of any collection of compact topological spaces is compact with respect to the product topology. The theorem is named after Andrey Nikolayevich Tikhonov (whose surname sometimes is trans ...
for compact Hausdorff spaces:
Let
be compact
topological spaces.
Assume that the ultrafilter lemma holds (because of the Hausdorff assumption, this proof does need the full strength of the
axiom of choice
In mathematics, the axiom of choice, or AC, is an axiom of set theory equivalent to the statement that ''a Cartesian product of a collection of non-empty sets is non-empty''. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection ...
; the ultrafilter lemma suffices).
Let
be given the product topology (which makes
a Hausdorff space) and for every
let
denote this product's projections.
If
then
is compact and the proof is complete so assume
Despite the fact that
because the axiom of choice is not assumed, the projection maps
are not guaranteed to be surjective.
Let
be an ultrafilter on
and for every
let
denote the ultrafilter on
generated by the ultra prefilter
Because
is compact and Hausdorff, the ultrafilter
converges to a unique limit point
(because of
's uniqueness, this definition does not require the axiom of choice).
Let
where
satisfies
for every
The characterization of convergence in the product topology that was given above implies that
Thus every ultrafilter on
converges to some point of
which implies that
is compact (recall that this implication's proof only required the ultrafilter lemma).
Examples of applications of prefilters
Uniformities and Cauchy prefilters
A
uniform space
In the mathematical field of topology, a uniform space is a set with a uniform structure. Uniform spaces are topological spaces with additional structure that is used to define uniform properties such as completeness, uniform continuity and unifo ...
is a set
equipped with a filter on
that has certain properties. A or is a prefilter on
whose upward closure is a uniform space.
A prefilter
on a uniform space
with uniformity
is called a if for every entourage
there exists some
that is , which means that
A is a minimal element (with respect to
or equivalently, to
) of the set of all Cauchy filters on
Examples of minimal Cauchy filters include the neighborhood filter
of any point
Every convergent filter on a uniform space is Cauchy. Moreover, every cluster point of a Cauchy filter is a limit point.
A uniform space
is called (resp. ) if every Cauchy prefilter (resp. every elementary Cauchy prefilter) on
converges to at least one point of
(replacing all instance of the word "prefilter" with "filter" results in equivalent statement).
Every compact uniform space is complete because any Cauchy filter has a cluster point (by compactness), which is necessarily also a limit point (since the filter is Cauchy).
Uniform spaces were the result of attempts to generalize notions such as "uniform continuity" and "uniform convergence" that are present in metric spaces. Every topological vector space, and more generally, every topological group can be made into a uniform space in a canonical way. Every uniformity also generates a canonical induced topology. Filters and prefilters play an important role in the theory of uniform spaces. For example, the completion of a Hausdorff uniform space (even if it is not Metrizable space, metrizable) is typically constructed by using minimal Cauchy filters.
Nets are less ideal for this construction because their domains are extremely varied (for example, the class of all Cauchy nets is not a set); sequences cannot be used in the general case because the topology might not be metrizable, First-countable space, first–countable, or even Sequential space, sequential.
The set of all on a Hausdorff topological vector space (TVS)
can made into a vector space and topologized in such a way that it becomes a Complete topological vector space, completion of
(with the assignment
becoming a TVS-embedding, linear topological embedding that identifies
as a dense vector subspace of this completion).
More generally, a Cauchy space, is a pair
consisting of a set
together a family
of (proper) filters, whose members are declared to be "", having all of the following properties:
# For each
the discrete ultrafilter at
is an element of
# If
is a subset of a proper filter
then
# If
and if each member of
intersects each member of
then
The set of all Cauchy filters on a uniform space forms a Cauchy space. Every Cauchy space is also a convergence space.
A map
between two Cauchy spaces is called if the image of every Cauchy filter in
is a Cauchy filter in
Unlike the
category of topological spaces, the Category (mathematics), category of Cauchy spaces and Cauchy continuous maps is Cartesian closed, and contains the category of proximity spaces.
Convergence of nets of sets
There is often a personal preference of nets over filters or filters over nets. This example shows that the choice between nets and filters is not a dichotomy by combining them together.
A or a refers to a
net
Net or net may refer to:
Mathematics and physics
* Net (mathematics), a filter-like topological generalization of a sequence
* Net, a linear system of divisors of dimension 2
* Net (polyhedron), an arrangement of polygons that can be folded up ...
in the
power set
In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is post ...
of
that is, a net of sets in
is a function from a non–empty
directed set
In mathematics, a directed set (or a directed preorder or a filtered set) is a nonempty set A together with a reflexive and transitive binary relation \,\leq\, (that is, a preorder), with the additional property that every pair of elements ha ...
into
However, a "net in
" will always refer to a net valued in
and never to a net valued in
although for emphasis or contrast, a net in
may also be referred to as a .
A net
of sets in
is called a (resp. , , , etc.) if every
has this property.
Similarly,
is called (resp. , , , etc.) if there is some index
such that this is true of
for every index
The following definition generalizes that of a #Tail of a net, tail of a net of points.
Suppose
is a net of sets in
Define for every index
the to be the set
and define the or generated by
to be the family
The family
is a prefilter if and only if it does not contain the empty set, which is equivalent to
not being eventually empty; in this case the upward closure in
of this prefilter of tails is called the or in
generated by
A net
(of sets or points) is eventually contained in a set
if and only if
so
is eventually empty if and only if
Nets of sets arise naturally when pulling back nets in a function's codomain.
If
is a map and
is a net of sets (or points) then let
and
that is,
denotes the net of sets
defined by
The tail of
starting at an index
is equal to
and similarly, the tail of
starting at
is
Consequently,
where this family is a prefilter if and only if
is a prefilter; similarly,
One useful consequence of this definition is that
is a prefilter if and only if
(or for points, )
meaning that for every index
there is some
such that
(where this intersection means
if
is a point instead of a set).
In particular,
(meaning that
for some
) is a necessary condition for
to be a prefilter. So even if a net
of points in
cannot be pulled back by
to a net
of in
(say because it is not entirely/eventually in the image of
), it is nevertheless still possible to talk about the net of
and its properties (such as convergence or clustering).
Convergence and clustering
Consideration of the following bijective correspondence leads naturally to the definitions of convergence and clustering for a net of sets, which are defined analogously to the original definitions given for a net of points.
(Nets of points
Nets of singleton sets): Every net
of points in
can be uniquely associated with the
and conversely, every net of singleton sets in
is uniquely associated with a (defined in the obvious way).
The tail of
starting at an index
is equal to that of
(that is, to
); consequently,
This makes it apparent that the following definition of "#Convergent net of sets, convergence of a net of sets" in
is indeed a generalization of #Convergent net, the original definition of "convergence of a net of points" in
(because
if and only if
); similarly, a net of points clusters at a given point or subset
(according to #Cluster point of a net, the original definition) if and only if its associated net of singleton sets clusters at
(according to #Cluster point of a net of sets, the definition below).
A net of sets
is said to to a given point or subset
of
written
if
which recall was defined to mean that
Explicitly, this happens if and only if for every neighborhood
of
there exists some index
such that
Similarly,
is said to a given point or subset
of
if
meshes with
(written
); explicitly, this means that
for every index
and neighborhood
of
Every net of sets that is eventually empty converges to every point/subset. However, a net of sets converges to
if and only if it is eventually empty. No net of sets clusters at
If a net of sets converges to
then it will cluster at
if and only if it is not eventually empty (which implies
).
If
is a net in
then
is a net of sets in
and for any point or subset
of
converges to (respectively, clusters at)
in
if and only if this is true of
This statement remains true if
is instead a net of sets.
If
is a map and
is a net (of points or of sets) then
converges to (respectively, clusters at) some given point or subset of
if and only if every neighborhood of it contains (respectively, intersects) some set of the form
Moreover, the net
converges in
to some given point or subset if and only if this is true of
Prefilters and nets of sets
If
is a prefilter on
then
is a (partially ordered) directed set, so that the identity map
is a net of sets in
Every prefilter can be canonically identified with this net of sets (that is, with its identity map when the prefilter/domain is directed by
).
Thus it is significantly easier to canonically associate every prefilter with a net of than with a net of (as was #Prefilters to nets, done above), and because the relationship is also much simpler, it is easier utilize.
For instance, it is readily seen that the tail of the net
starting at a given index
is equal to
(in other words, the tail starting at an index is the index itself) so that
(that is, this net's tails are its indices) and the prefilter
converges to (respectively, clusters at) a given point or subset if and only if the same is true of its canonical net of sets
In particular, information (including intuition and visualizations) about how or why a prefilter
converges to (or doesn't converge to, or clusters at, etc.) a point or set can almost immediately be obtained from information about how/why the net of sets
does the same (or vice versa).
Applications
Some applications are now given showing how nets of sets can be used to characterize various properties.
In the statements below, unless indicated otherwise,
and the net
are in
(not sets) and the map
is not necessarily surjective.
- A map is Closed map, closed (meaning it sends closed sets to closed subset of ) if and only if whenever then
* In comparison, is Continuity (topology), continuous if and only if whenever then
This characterization remains true if are allowed to be sets (instead of restricted to being points) such that
Assume is closed and
If then is in the open set so that implies that is eventually empty and thus that in
So assume and let be an open neighborhood of in
It remains to show that for some index
Since is closed, is an open neighborhood of in so there must exists some index such that
This implies where the right hand side is a subset of as desired.
For the converse, assume that implies Let be closed and assume it is not empty. Let be a net in (meaning for all ) and let be such that It remains to show that The hypotheses guarantee that The fact that every fiber is not empty and that these fibers converge to imply that
Since is open, were it true that then there would exist some index such that which is impossible since for every index
Thus so there is some which proves that
- A map is Open map, open (meaning it sends open sets to open subset of ) if and only if whenever and is a net that clusters at then clusters at
* In comparison, is Continuity (topology), continuous if and only if whenever is a net that Net (mathematics)#cluster point, clusters at a point then clusters at
This characterization remains true if are allowed to be sets.
For the non-trivial direction, suppose that is not an open map. Pick an open subset such that is not open in where non-openness means that there is some point such that is not a neighborhood of in
Explicitly, this means that for every neighborhood of in which guarantees the existence of some
Let denote the neighborhood filter of in and direct it by to make into a net that converges to in which implies that clusters at in
Because there is some
But does not clusters at since for every
- A map is Open map, open if and only if whenever then any closed subset of that contains
[A set means that for every index ] will necessarily also contain
* In comparison, by the Continuity (topology)#Closure operator and interior operator definitions, closure characterization of continuity, is continuous if and only if whenever then any closed subset of that contains will necessarily also contain
This characterization remains true if is allowed to be a net of sets that is not eventually empty (instead of being a net of points) while continues to be a point (such that ); the same is true of the quotient map characterization below.
If is any subset then it is readily verified that
This implies that a map is open if and only if whenever is closed in then is closed in
This characterization of "open map" combined with the convergent net characterization of closed sets produces the desired conclusion: is open if and only if whenever and is a closed subset of that contains then necessarily
- A continuous surjection is a quotient map if and only if whenever then any closed subset of that contains will necessarily also contain (A set is saturated if )
- A subset is closed in if and only if for every point and every net of subsets of that is not eventually empty, if then
- A map is continuous if and only if whenever and are sets or points in such that then
The proof is essentially identical to the usual proof involving only nets of points. One direction (that whose conclusion is that is continuous) only requires consideration of nets of points and so it is omitted. So suppose that the map is continuous and that Let be an open neighborhood of in Then is an open neighborhood of in so there exists some index such that Thus as desired.
- A map is continuous if and only if whenever is a net of sets or points in that clusters at (respectively, converges to) some given point or subset of then clusters at (respectively, converges to) in
Topologizing the set of prefilters
Starting with nothing more than a set
it is possible to topologize the set
of all filter bases on
with the , which is named after Marshall Harvey Stone.
To reduce confusion, this article will adhere to the following notational conventions:
- Lower case letters for elements
- Upper case letters for subsets
- Upper case calligraphy letters for subsets (or equivalently, for elements such as prefilters).
- Upper case double–struck letters for subsets
For every
let
where
[As a side note, had the definitions of "filter" and "prefilter" not required propriety then the degenerate dual ideal would have been a prefilter on so that in particular, with ] These sets will be the basic open subsets of the Stone topology.
If
then
From this inclusion, it is possible to deduce all of the subset inclusions displayed below with the exception of
[This is because the inclusion is the only one in the sequence below whose proof uses the defining assumption that ]
For all
where in particular, the equality
shows that the family
is a Pi-system,
–system that forms a Basis (topology), basis for a topology on
called the . It is henceforth assumed that
carries this topology and that any subset of
carries the induced subspace topology.
In contrast to most other general constructions of topologies (for example, the Product topology, product, Quotient topology, quotient, Subspace topology, subspace topologies, etc.), this topology on
was defined with using anything other than the set
there were preexisting Mathematical structure, structures or assumptions on
so this topology is completely independent of everything other than
(and its subsets).
The following criteria can be used for checking for Point of closure, points of closure and neighborhoods.
If
then:
- : belongs to the closure of if and only if
- : is a neighborhood of if and only if there exists some such that (that is, such that for all ).
It will be henceforth assumed that
because otherwise
and the topology is
which is uninteresting.
Subspace of ultrafilters
The set of ultrafilters on
(with the subspace topology) is a Stone space, meaning that it is compact, Hausdorff, and Totally disconnected space, totally disconnected.
If
has the discrete topology then the map
defined by sending
to the principal ultrafilter at
is a topological embedding whose image is a dense subset of
(see the article Stone–Čech compactification#Construction using ultrafilters, Stone–Čech compactification for more details).
Relationships between topologies on
and the Stone topology on
Every
induces a canonical map
defined by
which sends
to the neighborhood filter of
The map
is injective if and only if
(that is, a Kolmogorov space) and moreover, if
then
Thus every
can be identified with the canonical map
which allows
to be canonically identified as a subset of
(as a side note, it is now possible to place on
and thus also on
the topology of pointwise convergence on
so that it now makes sense to talk about things such as sequences of topologies on
converging pointwise).
For every
the surjection
is continuous, Open and closed maps, closed, and open.
In particular, for every
topology
the map
is a topological embedding.
In addition, if
is a map such that
(which is true of
for instance), then for every
the set
is a neighborhood (in the subspace topology) of
See also
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
Notes
Proofs
Citations
References
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
* (Provides an introductory review of filters in topology and in metric spaces.)
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
{{Topology
Filters
General topology