Type theory
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
mathematics Mathematics is a field of study that discovers and organizes methods, Mathematical theory, theories and theorems that are developed and Mathematical proof, proved for the needs of empirical sciences and mathematics itself. There are many ar ...
and
theoretical computer science Theoretical computer science is a subfield of computer science and mathematics that focuses on the Abstraction, abstract and mathematical foundations of computation. It is difficult to circumscribe the theoretical areas precisely. The Associati ...
, a type theory is the formal presentation of a specific type system. Type theory is the academic study of type systems. Some type theories serve as alternatives to
set theory Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies Set (mathematics), sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory – as a branch of mathema ...
as a foundation of mathematics. Two influential type theories that have been proposed as foundations are: * Typed λ-calculus of
Alonzo Church Alonzo Church (June 14, 1903 – August 11, 1995) was an American computer scientist, mathematician, logician, and philosopher who made major contributions to mathematical logic and the foundations of theoretical computer science. He is bes ...
* Intuitionistic type theory of Per Martin-Löf Most computerized proof-writing systems use a type theory for their foundation. A common one is Thierry Coquand's Calculus of Inductive Constructions.


History

Type theory was created to avoid paradoxes in naive set theory and formal logic, such as Russell's paradox which demonstrates that, without proper axioms, it is possible to define the set of all sets that are not members of themselves; this set both contains itself and does not contain itself. Between 1902 and 1908,
Bertrand Russell Bertrand Arthur William Russell, 3rd Earl Russell, (18 May 1872 – 2 February 1970) was a British philosopher, logician, mathematician, and public intellectual. He had influence on mathematics, logic, set theory, and various areas of analytic ...
proposed various solutions to this problem. By 1908, Russell arrived at a ramified theory of types together with an axiom of reducibility, both of which appeared in Whitehead and Russell's '' Principia Mathematica'' published in 1910, 1912, and 1913. This system avoided contradictions suggested in Russell's paradox by creating a hierarchy of types and then assigning each concrete mathematical entity to a specific type. Entities of a given type were built exclusively of subtypes of that type, thus preventing an entity from being defined using itself. This resolution of Russell's paradox is similar to approaches taken in other formal systems, such as Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory.''Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'
(rev. Mon Oct 12, 2020) Russell’s Paradox
3. Early Responses to the Paradox
Type theory is particularly popular in conjunction with
Alonzo Church Alonzo Church (June 14, 1903 – August 11, 1995) was an American computer scientist, mathematician, logician, and philosopher who made major contributions to mathematical logic and the foundations of theoretical computer science. He is bes ...
's
lambda calculus In mathematical logic, the lambda calculus (also written as ''λ''-calculus) is a formal system for expressing computability, computation based on function Abstraction (computer science), abstraction and function application, application using var ...
. One notable early example of type theory is Church's simply typed lambda calculus. Church's theory of types helped the formal system avoid the Kleene–Rosser paradox that afflicted the original untyped lambda calculus. Church demonstrated that it could serve as a foundation of mathematics and it was referred to as a higher-order logic. In the modern literature, "type theory" refers to a typed system based around lambda calculus. One influential system is Per Martin-Löf's intuitionistic type theory, which was proposed as a foundation for constructive mathematics. Another is Thierry Coquand's calculus of constructions, which is used as the foundation by Rocq (previously known as ''Coq''), Lean, and other computer proof assistants. Type theory is an active area of research, one direction being the development of homotopy type theory.


Applications


Mathematical foundations

The first computer proof assistant, called Automath, used type theory to encode mathematics on a computer. Martin-Löf specifically developed intuitionistic type theory to encode ''all'' mathematics to serve as a new foundation for mathematics. There is ongoing research into mathematical foundations using homotopy type theory. Mathematicians working in
category theory Category theory is a general theory of mathematical structures and their relations. It was introduced by Samuel Eilenberg and Saunders Mac Lane in the middle of the 20th century in their foundational work on algebraic topology. Category theory ...
already had difficulty working with the widely accepted foundation of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory. This led to proposals such as Lawvere's Elementary Theory of the Category of Sets (ETCS). Homotopy type theory continues in this line using type theory. Researchers are exploring connections between dependent types (especially the identity type) and algebraic topology (specifically homotopy).


Proof assistants

Much of the current research into type theory is driven by proof checkers, interactive proof assistants, and automated theorem provers. Most of these systems use a type theory as the mathematical foundation for encoding proofs, which is not surprising, given the close connection between type theory and programming languages: * LF is used by Twelf, often to define other type theories; * many type theories which fall under higher-order logic are used by the HOL family of provers and PVS; * computational type theory is used by NuPRL; * calculus of constructions and its derivatives are used by Rocq (previously known as ''Coq''), Matita, and Lean; * UTT (Luo's Unified Theory of dependent Types) is used by Agda which is both a programming language and proof assistant Many type theories are supported by LEGO and Isabelle. Isabelle also supports foundations besides type theories, such as ZFC. Mizar is an example of a proof system that only supports set theory.


Programming languages

Any static program analysis, such as the type checking algorithms in the semantic analysis phase of
compiler In computing, a compiler is a computer program that Translator (computing), translates computer code written in one programming language (the ''source'' language) into another language (the ''target'' language). The name "compiler" is primaril ...
, has a connection to type theory. A prime example is Agda, a programming language which uses UTT (Luo's Unified Theory of dependent Types) for its type system. The programming language ML was developed for manipulating type theories (see LCF) and its own type system was heavily influenced by them.


Linguistics

Type theory is also widely used in formal theories of semantics of natural languages, especially Montague grammar and its descendants. In particular, categorial grammars and pregroup grammars extensively use type constructors to define the types (''noun'', ''verb'', etc.) of words. The most common construction takes the basic types e and t for individuals and truth-values, respectively, and defines the set of types recursively as follows: * if a and b are types, then so is \langle a,b\rangle; * nothing except the basic types, and what can be constructed from them by means of the previous clause are types. A complex type \langle a,b\rangle is the type of functions from entities of type a to entities of type b. Thus one has types like \langle e,t\rangle which are interpreted as elements of the set of functions from entities to truth-values, i.e.
indicator function In mathematics, an indicator function or a characteristic function of a subset of a set is a function that maps elements of the subset to one, and all other elements to zero. That is, if is a subset of some set , then the indicator functio ...
s of sets of entities. An expression of type \langle\langle e,t\rangle,t\rangle is a function from sets of entities to truth-values, i.e. a (indicator function of a) set of sets. This latter type is standardly taken to be the type of natural language quantifiers, like '' everybody'' or ''nobody'' ( Montague 1973, Barwise and Cooper 1981). Type theory with records is a formal semantics representation framework, using '' records'' to express ''type theory types''. It has been used in
natural language processing Natural language processing (NLP) is a subfield of computer science and especially artificial intelligence. It is primarily concerned with providing computers with the ability to process data encoded in natural language and is thus closely related ...
, principally
computational semantics Computational semantics is the study of how to automate the process of constructing and reasoning with semantics, meaning representations of natural language expressions. It consequently plays an important role in natural language processing, nat ...
and dialogue systems.


Social sciences

Gregory Bateson introduced a theory of logical types into the social sciences; his notions of double bind and logical levels are based on Russell's theory of types.


Logic

A type theory is a
mathematical logic Mathematical logic is the study of Logic#Formal logic, formal logic within mathematics. Major subareas include model theory, proof theory, set theory, and recursion theory (also known as computability theory). Research in mathematical logic com ...
, which is to say it is a collection of rules of inference that result in judgments. Most logics have judgments asserting "The
proposition A proposition is a statement that can be either true or false. It is a central concept in the philosophy of language, semantics, logic, and related fields. Propositions are the object s denoted by declarative sentences; for example, "The sky ...
\varphi is true", or "The formula \varphi is a well-formed formula". A type theory has judgments that define types and assign them to a collection of formal objects, known as terms. A term and its type are often written together as \mathrm:\mathsf.


Terms

A term in logic is recursively defined as a constant symbol, variable, or a
function application In mathematics, function application is the act of applying a function to an argument from its domain so as to obtain the corresponding value from its range. In this sense, function application can be thought of as the opposite of function abs ...
, where a term is applied to another term. Constant symbols could include the natural number 0, the Boolean value \mathrm, and functions such as the successor function \mathrm and conditional operator \mathrm. Thus some terms could be 0, (\mathrm\,0), (\mathrm\,(\mathrm\,0)), and (\mathrm\,\mathrm\,0\,(\mathrm\,0)).


Judgments

Most type theories have 4 judgments: * "T is a type" * "t is a term of type T" * "Type T_1 is equal to type T_2" * "Terms t_1 and t_2 both of type T are equal" Judgments may follow from assumptions. For example, one might say "assuming x is a term of type \mathsf and y is a term of type \mathsf, it follows that (\mathrm\,x\,y\,y) is a term of type \mathsf". Such judgments are formally written with the turnstile symbol \vdash. x:\mathsf,y:\mathsf\vdash(\textrm\,x\,y\,y): \mathsf If there are no assumptions, there will be nothing to the left of the turnstile. \vdash \mathrm:\mathsf\to\mathsf The list of assumptions on the left is the ''context'' of the judgment. Capital greek letters, such as \Gamma and \Delta, are common choices to represent some or all of the assumptions. The 4 different judgments are thus usually written as follows. Some textbooks use a triple equal sign \equiv to stress that this is judgmental equality and thus an extrinsic notion of equality. The judgments enforce that every term has a type. The type will restrict which rules can be applied to a term.


Rules of Inference

A type theory's inference rules say what judgments can be made, based on the existence of other judgments. Rules are expressed as a Gentzen-style deduction using a horizontal line, with the required input judgments above the line and the resulting judgment below the line. For example, the following inference rule states a substitution rule for judgmental equality. \begin \Gamma\vdash t:T_1 \qquad \Delta\vdash T_1 = T_2 \\ \hline \Gamma,\Delta\vdash t:T_2 \end The rules are syntactic and work by rewriting. The metavariables \Gamma, \Delta, t, T_1, and T_2 may actually consist of complex terms and types that contain many function applications, not just single symbols. To generate a particular judgment in type theory, there must be a rule to generate it, as well as rules to generate all of that rule's required inputs, and so on. The applied rules form a proof tree, where the top-most rules need no assumptions. One example of a rule that does not require any inputs is one that states the type of a constant term. For example, to assert that there is a term 0 of type \mathsf, one would write the following. \begin \hline \vdash 0 : nat \\ \end


Type inhabitation

Generally, the desired conclusion of a proof in type theory is one of type inhabitation. The decision problem of type inhabitation (abbreviated by \exists t.\Gamma \vdash t : \tau?) is: :Given a context \Gamma and a type \tau, decide whether there exists a term t that can be assigned the type \tau in the type environment \Gamma. Girard's paradox shows that type inhabitation is strongly related to the consistency of a type system with Curry–Howard correspondence. To be sound, such a system must have uninhabited types. A type theory usually has several rules, including ones to: * create a judgment (known as a ''context'' in this case) * add an assumption to the context (context ''weakening'') * rearrange the assumptions * use an assumption to create a variable * define reflexivity, symmetry and transitivity for judgmental equality * define substitution for application of lambda terms * list all the interactions of equality, such as substitution * define a hierarchy of type universes * assert the existence of new types Also, for each "by rule" type, there are 4 different kinds of rules * "type formation" rules say how to create the type * "term introduction" rules define the canonical terms and constructor functions, like "pair" and "S". * "term elimination" rules define the other functions like "first", "second", and "R". * "computation" rules specify how computation is performed with the type-specific functions. For examples of rules, an interested reader may follow Appendix A.2 of the ''Homotopy Type Theory'' book, or read Martin-Löf's Intuitionistic Type Theory.


Connections to foundations

The logical framework of a type theory bears a resemblance to intuitionistic, or constructive, logic. Formally, type theory is often cited as an implementation of the Brouwer–Heyting–Kolmogorov interpretation of intuitionistic logic. Additionally, connections can be made to
category theory Category theory is a general theory of mathematical structures and their relations. It was introduced by Samuel Eilenberg and Saunders Mac Lane in the middle of the 20th century in their foundational work on algebraic topology. Category theory ...
and computer programs.


Intuitionistic logic

When used as a foundation, certain types are interpreted to be propositions (statements that can be proven), and terms inhabiting the type are interpreted to be proofs of that proposition. When some types are interpreted as propositions, there is a set of common types that can be used to connect them to make a Boolean algebra out of types. However, the logic is not classical logic but intuitionistic logic, which is to say it does not have the law of excluded middle nor double negation. Under this intuitionistic interpretation, there are common types that act as the logical operators: Because the law of excluded middle does not hold, there is no term of type \Pi a.A+ (A\to\bot). Likewise, double negation does not hold, so there is no term of type \Pi A.((A\to\bot)\to\bot)\to A. It is possible to include the law of excluded middle and double negation into a type theory, by rule or assumption. However, terms may not compute down to canonical terms and it will interfere with the ability to determine if two terms are judgementally equal to each other.


Constructive mathematics

Per Martin-Löf proposed his intuitionistic type theory as a foundation for constructive mathematics. Constructive mathematics requires when proving "there exists an x with property P(x)", one must construct a particular x and a proof that it has property P. In type theory, existence is accomplished using the dependent product type, and its proof requires a term of that type. An example of a non-constructive proof is
proof by contradiction In logic, proof by contradiction is a form of proof that establishes the truth or the validity of a proposition by showing that assuming the proposition to be false leads to a contradiction. Although it is quite freely used in mathematical pr ...
. The first step is assuming that x does not exist and refuting it by contradiction. The conclusion from that step is "it is not the case that x does not exist". The last step is, by double negation, concluding that x exists. Constructive mathematics does not allow the last step of removing the double negation to conclude that x exists. Most of the type theories proposed as foundations are constructive, and this includes most of the ones used by proof assistants. It is possible to add non-constructive features to a type theory, by rule or assumption. These include operators on continuations such as call with current continuation. However, these operators tend to break desirable properties such as canonicity and parametricity.


Curry-Howard correspondence

The Curry–Howard correspondence is the observed similarity between logics and programming languages. The implication in logic, "A \to B" resembles a function from type "A" to type "B". For a variety of logics, the rules are similar to expressions in a programming language's types. The similarity goes farther, as applications of the rules resemble programs in the programming languages. Thus, the correspondence is often summarized as "proofs as programs". The opposition of terms and types can also be viewed as one of ''implementation'' and ''specification''. By program synthesis, (the computational counterpart of) type inhabitation can be used to construct (all or parts of) programs from the specification given in the form of type information.


Type inference

Many programs that work with type theory (e.g., interactive theorem provers) also do type inferencing. It lets them select the rules that the user intends, with fewer actions by the user.


Research areas


Category theory

Although the initial motivation for
category theory Category theory is a general theory of mathematical structures and their relations. It was introduced by Samuel Eilenberg and Saunders Mac Lane in the middle of the 20th century in their foundational work on algebraic topology. Category theory ...
was far removed from foundationalism, the two fields turned out to have deep connections. As John Lane Bell writes: "In fact categories can ''themselves'' be viewed as type theories of a certain kind; this fact alone indicates that type theory is much more closely related to category theory than it is to set theory." In brief, a category can be viewed as a type theory by regarding its objects as types (or ''sorts'' ), i.e. "Roughly speaking, a category may be thought of as a type theory shorn of its syntax." A number of significant results follow in this way: * cartesian closed categories correspond to the typed λ-calculus ( Lambek, 1970); * C-monoids (categories with products and exponentials and one non-terminal object) correspond to the untyped λ-calculus (observed independently by Lambek and Dana Scott around 1980); * locally cartesian closed categories correspond to Martin-Löf type theories (Seely, 1984). The interplay, known as categorical logic, has been a subject of active research since then; see the monograph of Jacobs (1999) for instance.


Homotopy type theory

Homotopy type theory attempts to combine type theory and category theory. It focuses on equalities, especially equalities between types. Homotopy type theory differs from intuitionistic type theory mostly by its handling of the equality type. In 2016, cubical type theory was proposed, which is a homotopy type theory with normalization.


Definitions


Terms and types


Atomic terms

The most basic types are called atoms, and a term whose type is an atom is known as an atomic term. Common atomic terms included in type theories are
natural number In mathematics, the natural numbers are the numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, and so on, possibly excluding 0. Some start counting with 0, defining the natural numbers as the non-negative integers , while others start with 1, defining them as the positive in ...
s, often notated with the type \mathsf,
Boolean logic In mathematics and mathematical logic, Boolean algebra is a branch of algebra. It differs from elementary algebra in two ways. First, the values of the variable (mathematics), variables are the truth values ''true'' and ''false'', usually denot ...
values (\mathrm/\mathrm), notated with the type \mathsf, and formal variables, whose type may vary. For example, the following may be atomic terms. * 42:\mathsf * \mathrm:\mathsf * x:\mathsf * y:\mathsf


Function terms

In addition to atomic terms, most modern type theories also allow for functions. Function types introduce an arrow symbol, and are defined inductively: If \sigma and \tau are types, then the notation \sigma\to\tau is the type of a function which takes a parameter of type \sigma and returns a term of type \tau. Types of this form are known as ''simple'' types. Some terms may be declared directly as having a simple type, such as the following term, \mathrm, which takes in two natural numbers in sequence and returns one natural number. \mathrm:\mathsf\to (\mathsf\to\mathsf) Strictly speaking, a simple type only allows for one input and one output, so a more faithful reading of the above type is that \mathrm is a function which takes in a natural number and returns a function of the form \mathsf\to\mathsf. The parentheses clarify that \mathrm does not have the type (\mathsf\to \mathsf)\to\mathsf, which would be a function which takes in a function of natural numbers and returns a natural number. The convention is that the arrow is right associative, so the parentheses may be dropped from \mathrm's type.


Lambda terms

New function terms may be constructed using lambda expressions, and are called lambda terms. These terms are also defined inductively: a lambda term has the form (\lambda v .t), where v is a formal variable and t is a term, and its type is notated \sigma\to\tau, where \sigma is the type of v, and \tau is the type of t. The following lambda term represents a function which doubles an input natural number. (\lambda x.\mathrm\,x\,x): \mathsf\to\mathsf The variable is x and (implicit from the lambda term's type) must have type \mathsf . The term \mathrm\,x\,x has type \mathsf , which is seen by applying the function application inference rule twice. Thus, the lambda term has type \mathsf\to\mathsf, which means it is a function taking a natural number as an
argument An argument is a series of sentences, statements, or propositions some of which are called premises and one is the conclusion. The purpose of an argument is to give reasons for one's conclusion via justification, explanation, and/or persu ...
and returning a natural number. A lambda term is often referred to as an anonymous function because it lacks a name. The concept of anonymous functions appears in many programming languages.


Inference Rules


Function application

The power of type theories is in specifying how terms may be combined by way of inference rules. Type theories which have functions also have the inference rule of
function application In mathematics, function application is the act of applying a function to an argument from its domain so as to obtain the corresponding value from its range. In this sense, function application can be thought of as the opposite of function abs ...
: if t is a term of type \sigma\to\tau, and s is a term of type \sigma, then the application of t to s, often written (t\,s), has type \tau. For example, if one knows the type notations 0:\textsf, 1:\textsf, and 2:\textsf, then the following type notations can be deduced from function application. * (\mathrm\,1): \textsf\to\textsf * ((\mathrm\,2)\,0): \textsf * ((\mathrm\,1)((\mathrm\,2)\,0)): \textsf Parentheses indicate the order of operations; however, by convention, function application is left associative, so parentheses can be dropped where appropriate. In the case of the three examples above, all parentheses could be omitted from the first two, and the third may simplified to \mathrm\,1\, (\mathrm\,2\,0): \textsf.


Reductions

Type theories that allow for lambda terms also include inference rules known as \beta-reduction and \eta-reduction. They generalize the notion of function application to lambda terms. Symbolically, they are written * (\lambda v. t)\,s\rightarrow t \colon= s/math> (\beta-reduction). * (\lambda v. t\, v)\rightarrow t, if v is not a free variable in t (\eta-reduction). The first reduction describes how to evaluate a lambda term: if a lambda expression (\lambda v .t) is applied to a term s, one replaces every occurrence of v in t with s. The second reduction makes explicit the relationship between lambda expressions and function types: if (\lambda v. t\, v) is a lambda term, then it must be that t is a function term because it is being applied to v. Therefore, the lambda expression is equivalent to just t, as both take in one argument and apply t to it. For example, the following term may be \beta-reduced. (\lambda x.\mathrm\,x\,x)\,2\rightarrow \mathrm\,2\,2 In type theories that also establish notions of equality for types and terms, there are corresponding inference rules of \beta-equality and \eta-equality.


Common terms and types


Empty type

The empty type has no terms. The type is usually written \bot or \mathbb 0. One use for the empty type is proofs of type inhabitation. If for a type a, it is consistent to derive a function of type a\to\bot, then a is ''uninhabited'', which is to say it has no terms.


Unit type

The unit type has exactly 1 canonical term. The type is written \top or \mathbb 1 and the single canonical term is written \ast. The unit type is also used in proofs of type inhabitation. If for a type a, it is consistent to derive a function of type \top\to a, then a is ''inhabited'', which is to say it must have one or more terms.


Boolean type

The Boolean type has exactly 2 canonical terms. The type is usually written \textsf or \mathbb B or \mathbb 2. The canonical terms are usually \mathrm and \mathrm.


Natural numbers

Natural numbers are usually implemented in the style of Peano Arithmetic. There is a canonical term 0:\mathsf for zero. Canonical values larger than zero use iterated applications of a successor function \mathrm:\mathsf\to\mathsf.


Type constructors

Some type theories allow for types of complex terms, such as functions or lists, to depend on the types of its arguments; these are called type constructors. For example, a type theory could have the dependent type \mathsf\,a, which should correspond to lists of terms, where each term must have type a. In this case, \mathsf has the kind U\to U, where U denotes the
universe The universe is all of space and time and their contents. It comprises all of existence, any fundamental interaction, physical process and physical constant, and therefore all forms of matter and energy, and the structures they form, from s ...
of all types in the theory.


Product type

The product type, \times, depends on two types, and its terms are commonly written as ordered pairs (s,t). The pair (s,t) has the product type \sigma\times\tau, where \sigma is the type of s and \tau is the type of t. Each product type is then usually defined with eliminator functions \mathrm:\sigma\times\tau\to\sigma and \mathrm:\sigma\times\tau\to\tau. * \mathrm\,(s,t) returns s, and * \mathrm\,(s,t) returns t. Besides ordered pairs, this type is used for the concepts of
logical conjunction In logic, mathematics and linguistics, ''and'' (\wedge) is the Truth function, truth-functional operator of conjunction or logical conjunction. The logical connective of this operator is typically represented as \wedge or \& or K (prefix) or ...
and intersection.


Sum type

The sum type is written as either + or \sqcup. In programming languages, sum types may be referred to as tagged unions. Each type \sigma\sqcup\tau is usually defined with constructors \mathrm:\sigma\to(\sigma\sqcup\tau) and \mathrm:\tau\to(\sigma\sqcup\tau), which are injective, and an eliminator function \mathrm:(\sigma\to\rho)\to(\tau\to\rho)\to(\sigma\sqcup\tau)\to\rho such that * \mathrm\,f\,g\,(\mathrm\,x) returns f\,x, and * \mathrm\,f\,g\,(\mathrm\,y) returns g\,y. The sum type is used for the concepts of logical disjunction and union.


Polymorphic types

Some theories also allow terms to have their definitions depend on types. For instance, an identity function of any type could be written as \lambda x.x:\forall\alpha. \alpha\to\alpha. The function is said to be polymorphic in \alpha, or generic in x. As another example, consider a function \mathrm, which takes in a \mathsf\,a and a term of type a, and returns the list with the element at the end. The type annotation of such a function would be \mathrm:\forall\,a.\mathsf\,a\to a\to\mathsf\,a, which can be read as "for any type a, pass in a \mathsf\,a and an a, and return a \mathsf\,a". Here \mathrm is polymorphic in a.


Products and sums

With polymorphism, the eliminator functions can be defined generically for ''all'' product types as \mathrm:\forall\,\sigma\,\tau.\sigma\times\tau\to\sigma and \mathrm:\forall\,\sigma\,\tau.\sigma\times\tau\to\tau. * \mathrm\,(s,t) returns s, and * \mathrm\,(s,t) returns t. Likewise, the sum type constructors can be defined for all valid types of sum members as \mathrm:\forall\,\sigma\,\tau.\sigma\to(\sigma\sqcup\tau) and \mathrm:\forall\,\sigma\,\tau.\tau\to(\sigma\sqcup\tau), which are injective, and the eliminator function can be given as \mathrm:\forall\,\sigma\,\tau\,\rho.(\sigma\to\rho)\to(\tau\to\rho)\to(\sigma\sqcup\tau)\to\rho such that * \mathrm\,f\,g\,(\mathrm\,x) returns f\,x, and * \mathrm\,f\,g\,(\mathrm\,y) returns g\,y.


Dependent typing

Some theories also permit types to be dependent on terms instead of types. For example, a theory could have the type \mathsf\,n, where n is a term of type \mathsf encoding the length of the vector. This allows for greater specificity and type safety: functions with vector length restrictions or length matching requirements, such as the
dot product In mathematics, the dot product or scalar productThe term ''scalar product'' means literally "product with a Scalar (mathematics), scalar as a result". It is also used for other symmetric bilinear forms, for example in a pseudo-Euclidean space. N ...
, can encode this requirement as part of the type. There are foundational issues that can arise from dependent types if a theory is not careful about what dependencies are allowed, such as Girard's Paradox. The logician Henk Barendegt introduced the lambda cube as a framework for studying various restrictions and levels of dependent typing.


Dependent products and sums

Two common type dependencies, dependent product and dependent sum types, allow for the theory to encode BHK intuitionistic logic by acting as equivalents to universal and existential quantification; this is formalized by Curry–Howard Correspondence. As they also connect to products and sums in
set theory Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies Set (mathematics), sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory – as a branch of mathema ...
, they are often written with the symbols \Pi and \Sigma, respectively. Sum types are seen in dependent pairs, where the second type depends on the value of the first term. This arises naturally in computer science where functions may return different types of outputs based on the input. For example, the Boolean type is usually defined with an eliminator function \mathrm, which takes three arguments and behaves as follows. * \mathrm\,\mathrm\,x\,y returns x, and * \mathrm\,\mathrm\,x\,y returns y. Ordinary definitions of \mathrm require x and y to have the same type. If the type theory allows for dependent types, then it is possible to define a dependent type x:\mathsf\,\vdash\,\mathrm\,x:U\to U\to U such that * \mathrm\,\mathrm\,\sigma\,\tau returns \sigma, and * \mathrm\,\mathrm\,\sigma\,\tau returns \tau. The type of \mathrm may then be written as \forall\,\sigma\,\tau.\Pi_.\sigma\to\tau\to\mathrm\,x\,\sigma\,\tau.


Identity type

Following the notion of Curry-Howard Correspondence, the identity type is a type introduced to mirror propositional equivalence, as opposed to the judgmental (syntactic) equivalence that type theory already provides. An identity type requires two terms of the same type and is written with the symbol =. For example, if x+1 and 1+x are terms, then x+1=1+x is a possible type. Canonical terms are created with a reflexivity function, \mathrm. For a term t, the call \mathrm\,t returns the canonical term inhabiting the type t=t. The complexities of equality in type theory make it an active research topic; homotopy type theory is a notable area of research that mainly deals with equality in type theory.


Inductive types

Inductive types are a general template for creating a large variety of types. In fact, all the types described above and more can be defined using the rules of inductive types. Two methods of generating inductive types are induction-recursion and induction-induction. A method that only uses lambda terms is Scott encoding. Some proof assistants, such as Rocq (previously known as ''Coq'') and Lean, are based on the calculus for inductive constructions, which is a calculus of constructions with inductive types.


Differences from set theory

The most commonly accepted foundation for mathematics is first-order logic with the
language Language is a structured system of communication that consists of grammar and vocabulary. It is the primary means by which humans convey meaning, both in spoken and signed language, signed forms, and may also be conveyed through writing syste ...
and axioms of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice, abbreviated ZFC. Type theories having sufficient expressibility may also act as a foundation of mathematics. There are a number of differences between these two approaches. * Set theory has both
rules Rule or ruling may refer to: Human activity * The exercise of political or personal control by someone with authority or power * Business rule, a rule pertaining to the structure or behavior internal to a business * School rule, a rule tha ...
and axioms, while type theories only have rules. Type theories, in general, do not have axioms and are defined by their rules of inference. * Classical set theory and logic have the law of excluded middle. When a type theory encodes the concepts of "and" and "or" as types, it leads to intuitionistic logic, and does not necessarily have the law of excluded middle. * In set theory, an element is not restricted to one set. The element can appear in subsets and unions with other sets. In type theory, terms (generally) belong to only one type. Where a subset would be used, type theory can use a predicate function or use a dependently-typed product type, where each element x is paired with a proof that the subset's property holds for x. Where a union would be used, type theory uses the sum type, which contains new canonical terms. * Type theory has a built-in notion of computation. Thus, "1+1" and "2" are different terms in type theory, but they compute to the same value. Moreover, functions are defined computationally as lambda terms. In set theory, "1+1=2" means that "1+1" is just another way to refer the value "2". Type theory's computation does require a complicated concept of equality. * Set theory encodes numbers as sets. Type theory can encode numbers as functions using Church encoding, or more naturally as inductive types, and the construction closely resembles Peano's axioms. * In type theory, proofs are types whereas in set theory, proofs are part of the underlying first-order logic. Proponents of type theory will also point out its connection to constructive mathematics through the BHK interpretation, its connection to logic by the Curry–Howard isomorphism, and its connections to
Category theory Category theory is a general theory of mathematical structures and their relations. It was introduced by Samuel Eilenberg and Saunders Mac Lane in the middle of the 20th century in their foundational work on algebraic topology. Category theory ...
.


Properties of type theories

Terms usually belong to a single type. However, there are set theories that define "subtyping". Computation takes place by repeated application of rules. Many types of theories are strongly normalizing, which means that any order of applying the rules will always end in the same result. However, some are not. In a normalizing type theory, the one-directional computation rules are called "reduction rules", and applying the rules "reduces" the term. If a rule is not one-directional, it is called a "conversion rule". Some combinations of types are equivalent to other combinations of types. When functions are considered "exponentiation", the combinations of types can be written similarly to algebraic identities. Thus, + A \cong A, \times A \cong A, + \cong , A^ \cong A^B \times A^C, A^ \cong (A^B)^C.


Axioms

Most type theories do not have axioms. This is because a type theory is defined by its rules of inference. This is a source of confusion for people familiar with Set Theory, where a theory is defined by both the rules of inference for a logic (such as first-order logic) and axioms about sets. Sometimes, a type theory will add a few axioms. An axiom is a judgment that is accepted without a derivation using the rules of inference. They are often added to ensure properties that cannot be added cleanly through the rules. Axioms can cause problems if they introduce terms without a way to compute on those terms. That is, axioms can interfere with the normalizing property of the type theory. Some commonly encountered axioms are: * "Axiom K" ensures "uniqueness of identity proofs". That is, that every term of an identity type is equal to reflexivity. * "Univalence Axiom" holds that equivalence of types is equality of types. The research into this property led to cubical type theory, where the property holds without needing an axiom. * "Law of Excluded Middle" is often added to satisfy users who want classical logic, instead of intuitionistic logic. The Axiom of Choice does not need to be added to type theory, because in most type theories it can be derived from the rules of inference. This is because of the constructive nature of type theory, where proving that a value exists requires a method to compute the value. The Axiom of Choice is less powerful in type theory than most set theories, because type theory's functions must be computable and, being syntax-driven, the number of terms in a type must be countable. (See .)


List of type theories


Major

* Simply typed lambda calculus which is a higher-order logic * Intuitionistic type theory * System F * LF is often used to define other type theories * Calculus of constructions and its derivatives


Minor

* Automath * ST type theory * UTT (Luo's Unified Theory of dependent Types) * some forms of combinatory logic * others defined in the lambda cube (also known as pure type systems) * others under the name typed lambda calculus


Active research

* Homotopy type theory explores equality of types * Cubical Type Theory is an implementation of homotopy type theory


See also

* Class (set theory) * Type–token distinction


Further reading

* * * Covers type theory in depth, including polymorphic and dependent type extensions. Gives categorical semantics. * * Provides a historical survey of the developments of the theory of types with a focus on the decline of the theory as a foundation of mathematics over the four decades following the publication of the second edition of 'Principia Mathematica'. * Intended as a type theory counterpart of
Paul Halmos Paul Richard Halmos (; 3 March 1916 – 2 October 2006) was a Kingdom of Hungary, Hungarian-born United States, American mathematician and probabilist who made fundamental advances in the areas of mathematical logic, probability theory, operat ...
's (1960) '' Naïve Set Theory'' * * * A good introduction to simple type theory for computer scientists; the system described is not exactly Church's STT though
Book review
* * * * Montague, R. (1973) "The proper treatment of quantification in ordinary English". In K. J. J. Hintikka, J. M. E. Moravcsik, and P. Suppes (eds.), ''Approaches to Natural Language'' (Synthese Library, 49), Dordrecht: Reidel, 221–242; reprinted in Portner and Partee (eds.) 2002, pp. 17–35. See
Montague Semantics
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.''


Notes


References


External links


Introductory material


Type Theory at nLab
which has articles on many topics.
Intuitionistic Type Theory
article at the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Lambda Calculi with Types
book by Henk Barendregt
Calculus of Constructions / Typed Lambda Calculus
textbook style paper by Helmut Brandl
Intuitionistic Type Theory
notes by Per Martin-Löf
Programming in Martin-Löf's Type Theory
book
Homotopy Type Theory
book, which proposed homotopy type theory as a mathematical foundation.


Advanced material

*
The TYPES Forum
— moderated e-mail forum focusing on type theory in computer science, operating since 1987. * tp://ftp.cs.cornell.edu/pub/nuprl/doc/book.ps.gz The Nuprl Book "Introduction to Type Theory."
Types Project lecture notes
of summer schools 2005–2008 ** Th

has introductory lectures

many lectures and some notes.

includin
Robert Harper's talks on YouTube



Andrej Bauer's blog
{{DEFAULTSORT:Type Theory Systems of formal logic Hierarchy