Albert, Bishop Of Halberstadt
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

Albert of Saxony ( Latin: ''Albertus de Saxonia''; c. 1320 – 8 July 1390) was a German
philosopher A philosopher is a person who practices or investigates philosophy. The term ''philosopher'' comes from the grc, φιλόσοφος, , translit=philosophos, meaning 'lover of wisdom'. The coining of the term has been attributed to the Greek th ...
and mathematician known for his contributions to logic and physics. He was bishop of Halberstadt from 1366 until his death.


Life

Albert was born at
Rickensdorf Bahrdorf () is a Municipalities of Germany, municipality in the Helmstedt (district), district of Helmstedt, in Lower Saxony, Germany. The municipality consists of four villages: * Bahrdorf (including Blanken) * Mackendorf (including Klinkerwerk ...
near
Helmstedt Helmstedt (; Eastphalian: ''Helmstidde'') is a town on the eastern edge of the German state of Lower Saxony. It is the capital of the District of Helmstedt. The historic university and Hanseatic city conserves an important monumental heritage of ...
, the son of a farmer in a small village; but because of his talent, he was sent to study at the University of Prague and the University of Paris. At Paris, he became a master of arts (a professor), and held this post from 1351 until 1362. He also studied theology at the College of Sorbonne, although without receiving a degree. In 1353, he was
rector Rector (Latin for the member of a vessel's crew who steers) may refer to: Style or title *Rector (ecclesiastical), a cleric who functions as an administrative leader in some Christian denominations *Rector (academia), a senior official in an edu ...
of the University of Paris. After 1362, Albert went to the court of Pope Urban V in
Avignon Avignon (, ; ; oc, Avinhon, label=Provençal dialect, Provençal or , ; la, Avenio) is the Prefectures in France, prefecture of the Vaucluse Departments of France, department in the Provence-Alpes-Côte d'Azur Regions of France, region of So ...
as an envoy of Rudolf IV, Duke of Austria, in order to negotiate the founding of the University of Vienna. The negotiations were successful, and Albert became the first rector of this University in 1365. In 1366, Albert was elected bishop of Halberstadt (counted as Albert III), Halberstadt being the diocese in which he was born. As Bishop of Halberstadt, he allied himself with Magnus with the Necklace, Duke of Brunswick-Lüneburg, against Gebhard of Berg, Bishop of Hildesheim, and was taken prisoner by Gebhard in the battle of Dinckler in 1367. He died at Halberstadt in 1390.


Philosophy

Albert was a pupil of Jean Buridan and was very much influenced by Buridan's teachings on physics and logic. As a natural philosopher, he contributed to the spread of Parisian natural philosophy throughout Italy and central Europe. Similar to Buridan, Albert combined critical analysis of language with epistemological pragmatism. Albert distinguishes, as his teacher did, between what is absolutely impossible or contradictory and what is impossible “in the common course of nature” and considers hypotheses under circumstances that are not naturally possible but imaginable given God's absolute power. Albert refused to extend the reference of a physical term to
supernatural Supernatural refers to phenomena or entities that are beyond the laws of nature. The term is derived from Medieval Latin , from Latin (above, beyond, or outside of) + (nature) Though the corollary term "nature", has had multiple meanings si ...
, purely imaginary possibilities. Later regarded as one of the principal adherents of nominalism, along with his near contemporaries at Paris, namely Buridan and Marsilius of Inghen, whose works are often so similar as to be confused with each other. The subsequent wide circulation of Albert's work made him a better-known figure in some areas than more important contemporaries like Buridan and Nicole Oresme. Albert's work in logic also shows strong influence by William of Ockham, whose commentaries on the ''logica vetus'' (i. e. on Porphyry, and Aristotle's ''
Categoriae The ''Categories'' ( Greek Κατηγορίαι ''Katēgoriai''; Latin ''Categoriae'' or ''Praedicamenta'') is a text from Aristotle's '' Organon'' that enumerates all the possible kinds of things that can be the subject or the predicate of a ...
'' and ''
De interpretatione ''De Interpretatione'' or ''On Interpretation'' (Greek: Περὶ Ἑρμηνείας, ''Peri Hermeneias'') is the second text from Aristotle's ''Organon'' and is among the earliest surviving philosophical works in the Western tradition to deal ...
'') were made the subject of a series of works called ''Quaestiones'' by Albert. Albert of Saxony's teachings on logic and metaphysics were extremely influential. The theory of impetus introduced a third stage to the two stage theory of John Philoponus.Michael McCloskey: ''Impetustheorie und Intuition in der Physik.''. In: ''Newtons Universum''. Verlag Spektrum der Wissenschaft: Heidelberg 1990, , p. 18. # Initial stage. Motion is in a straight line in direction of impetus which is dominant while gravity is insignificant # Intermediate stage. Path begins to deviate downwards from straight line as part of a great circle as air resistance slows projectile and gravity recovers. # Last stage. Gravity alone draws projectile downwards vertically as all impetus is spent. This theory was a precursor to the modern theory of inertia. Although Buridan remained the predominant figure in logic, Albert's ''Perutilis logica'' (c. 1360) was destined to serve as a popular text because of its systematic nature and also because it takes up and develops essential aspects of the Ockhamist position. Albert accepted Ockham's conception of the nature of a
sign A sign is an object, quality, event, or entity whose presence or occurrence indicates the probable presence or occurrence of something else. A natural sign bears a causal relation to its object—for instance, thunder is a sign of storm, or me ...
. Albert believed that signification rests on a referential relation of the sign to the individual thing, and that the spoken sign depends for its signification on the conceptual sign. Albert followed Ockham in his conception of universals and in his theory of
supposition Supposition theory was a branch of medieval logic that was probably aimed at giving accounts of issues similar to modern accounts of reference, plurality, tense, and modality, within an Aristotelian context. Philosophers such as John Buridan, W ...
. Specifically, Albert preserved Ockham's notion of simple supposition, understood as the direct reference of a term to the concept on which it depends when it signifies an extra-mental thing. Albert followed Ockham in his theory of categories and contrary to Buridan, refused to treat quantity as a feature of reality in its own right, but rather reduced it to a disposition of
substance Substance may refer to: * Matter, anything that has mass and takes up space Chemistry * Chemical substance, a material with a definite chemical composition * Drug substance ** Substance abuse, drug-related healthcare and social policy diagnosis ...
and quality. Albert established signification through a referential relation to a singular thing defining the relation of the spoken to conceptual signs as a relation of subordination. Albert's treatment of relation was highly original. Although, like Ockham, he refused to construe relations as things distinct from
absolute Absolute may refer to: Companies * Absolute Entertainment, a video game publisher * Absolute Radio, (formerly Virgin Radio), independent national radio station in the UK * Absolute Software Corporation, specializes in security and data risk manage ...
entities, he clearly ascribed them to an act of the soul by which absolute entities are compared and placed in relation to each other. He therefore completely rejected certain propositions Ockham had admitted reasonable, even if he did not construe them in the same way. Albert's voluminous collection of ''Sophismata'' (c. 1359) examined various sentences that raise difficulties of interpretation due to the presence of syncategorematic terms such as quantifiers and certain prepositions, which, according to medieval logicians, do not have a proper and determinate signification but rather modify the signification of the other terms in the propositions in which they occur. In his ''Sophismata,'' he followed
William Heytesbury William of Heytesbury, or William Heytesbury, called in Latin Guglielmus Hentisberus or Tisberus (c. 1313 – 1372/1373), was an English philosopher and logician, best known as one of the Oxford Calculators of Merton College, Oxford, where he was ...
. In his analysis of
epistemic Epistemology (; ), or the theory of knowledge, is the branch of philosophy concerned with knowledge. Epistemology is considered a major subfield of philosophy, along with other major subfields such as ethics, logic, and metaphysics. Episte ...
verbs or of
infinity Infinity is that which is boundless, endless, or larger than any natural number. It is often denoted by the infinity symbol . Since the time of the ancient Greeks, the philosophical nature of infinity was the subject of many discussions amo ...
, Albert admitted that a proposition has its own signification, which is not that of its terms: just like a syncategorematic term, a proposition signifies a “mode of a thing.” Albert made use of the idea of the distinguishable signification of the proposition in defining truth and in dealing with “
insolubles In the Middle Ages, variations on the liar paradox were studied under the name of ''insolubilia'' ("insolubles"). Overview Although the liar paradox was well known in antiquity, interest seems to have lapsed until the twelfth century, when it ap ...
” or paradoxes of
self-reference Self-reference occurs in natural or formal languages when a sentence, idea or formula refers to itself. The reference may be expressed either directly—through some intermediate sentence or formula—or by means of some encoding. In philoso ...
. In this work he shows that since every proposition, by its very form, signifies that it is true, an insoluble proposition will turn out to be false because it will signify at once both that it is true and that it is false. Albert also authored commentaries on ''Ars Vetus'', a set of twenty-five ''Quaestiones logicales'' (c. 1356) that involved semantical problems and the status of logic, and ''Quaestiones'' on the ''Posterior Analytics''. Albert explored in a series of disputed questions the status of logic and semantics, as well as the theory of reference and truth. Albert was influenced by English logicians and was influential in the diffusion of terminist logic in central Europe. Albert is considered a major contributor in his theory of consequences, found in his ''Perutilis Logica''. Albert took a major step forward in the medieval theory of logical deduction. But it was his commentary on Aristotle's '' Physics'' that was especially widely read. Many manuscripts of it can be found in France and Italy, in Erfurt and Prague. Albert's ''Physics'' basically guaranteed the transmission of the Parisian tradition to Italy, where it was authoritative along with the works of Heytesbury and
John Dumbleton John of Dumbleton (Latin ''Ioannes De Dumbleton''; c. 1310 – c. 1349) was a member of the Dumbleton village community in Gloucestershire, a southwestern county in England. Although obscure, he is considered a significant English fourteenth- ...
. His commentary on Aristotle's '' De caelo'' was also influential, eventually eclipsing Buridan's commentary on this text. Blasius of Parma read it in Bologna between 1379 and 1382. A little later, it enjoyed a wide audience at Vienna. His ''Treatise on Proportions'' was often quoted in Italy where, in addition to the texts of
Thomas Bradwardine Thomas Bradwardine (c. 1300 – 26 August 1349) was an English cleric, scholar, mathematician, physicist, courtier and, very briefly, Archbishop of Canterbury. As a celebrated scholastic philosopher and doctor of theology, he is often call ...
and Oresme, it influenced the application of the theory of proportions to motion. Albert's commentaries on the ''
Nicomachean Ethics The ''Nicomachean Ethics'' (; ; grc, Ἠθικὰ Νικομάχεια, ) is Aristotle's best-known work on ethics, the science of the good for human life, which is the goal or end at which all our actions aim. (I§2) The aim of the inquiry is ...
'' and the '' Economics'' also survive (both unedited), as well as several short mathematical texts, most notably ''Tractatus proportionum'' (c. 1353). Although Albert studied theology in Paris, no theological writing survived. Albert played an essential role in the diffusion throughout Italy and central Europe of Parisian ideas which bore the mark of Buridan's teachings, but which were also clearly shaped by Albert's own grasp of English innovations. At the same time, Albert was not merely a compiler of the work of others. He knew how to construct proofs of undeniable originality on many topics in logic and physics.


Works

*''Perutilis Logica Magistri Alberti de Saxonia'' (''Very Useful Logic''), Venice 1522 and Hildesheim 1974 (reproduction) *''Albert of Saxony's Twenty-Five Disputed Questions on Logic. A Critical Edition of His Quaestiones circa logicam'', by Michael J. Fitzgerald, Leiden: Brill, 2002 *''Quaestiones in artem veterem'' critical edition by Angel Muñoz Garcia, Maracaibo, Venezuela: Universidad del Zulia,1988 *''Quaestiones on the Posterior Analytics'' *''Quaestiones logicales'' (''Logical Questions'') *''De consequentiis'' (On Consequences) - attributed *''De locis dialecticis'' (On Dialectical Topics) - attributed *''Sophismata et Insolubilia et Obligationes'', Paris 1489 and Hildesheim 1975 (reproduction) *''Expositio et quaestiones in Aristotelis Physicam ad Albertum de Saxonia attributae'' critical edition by Benoit Patar, Leuven, Peeters Publishers, 1999 *''Questiones subtilissime in libros Aristotelis de caelo et mundo, Venetiis, 1492. Questiones subtilissime super libros posteriorum, Venetiis 1497'' Hildesheim 1986 (reproduction) *''Alberti de Saxonia Quæstiones in Aristotelis De cælo'' critical edition by Benoit Patar, Leuven, Peeters Publishers, 2008 *''De latudinibus'', Padua 1505 *''De latitudinibus formarum'' *''De maximo et minimo'' *''De quadratura circuli'' - ''Question on the Squaring of the Circle'' *''Tractatus proportionum'', Venice 1496 and Vienna 1971: editor Hubertus L. Busard


Modern editions and English translations

* ''Tractatus proportionum'': ''Der Tractatus proportionum von Albert von Sachsen'', Osterreichische Akademie der Wissenschaften, math.-nat. Klasse, Denkschriften 116(2):44–72. Springer, Vienna, 1971. * ''Perutilis logica'', Latin text and Spanish translation by A. Muñoz-Garcia, Universidad Nacional Autonoma de Mexico, 1988. * ''Quaestiones in Artem Veterem'', Latin text and Spanish translation by A. Muñoz-Garcia, Maracaibo, Universidad del Zulia, 1988. * ''De proprietates terminorum'' (second tract of the ''Perutilis logica''), edited by C. Kann, ''Die Eigenschaften der Termini'', Brill, Leiden, 1993. * ''Quaestiones super libros Physicorum'', edited by B. Patar, ''Expositio et Quaestiones in Aristotelis Physicam ad Albertum de Saxonia attributae'', Louvain, Peeters, 1999 (3 volumes). * ''Quaestiones circa Logicam: Twenty-Five Disputed Questions on Logic,'' trans. Michael J. Fitzgerald, Dallas Medieval Texts and Translations 9, Louvain and Paris: Peeters, 2010.


See also

*
John Buridan Jean Buridan (; Latin: ''Johannes Buridanus''; – ) was an influential 14th-century French philosopher. Buridan was a teacher in the faculty of arts at the University of Paris for his entire career who focused in particular on logic and the wo ...
* List of Roman Catholic scientist-clerics


References


Further reading

* Joel Biard (ed.), ''Itinéraires d’Albert de Saxe. Paris Vienne au XIVe siècle'', Paris, Vrin, 1991. * Grant, Edward, ''A Companion to Philosophy in the Middle Ages'', In Gracia, J., J., E. & Noone, T. B. (Eds.), Blackwell Companions to Philosophy, Malden, MA: Blackwell, 2003. * * Pasnau, Robert, ''The Cambridge History of Medieval Philosophy'', Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010. * * J.M.M.H. Thijssen, ''The Buridan School Reassessed. John Buridan and Albert of Saxony'', Vivarium 42, 2004, pp. 18–42.


External links

* * *
Zedlers Universal-Lexicon, vol. 1, p. 542
* {{DEFAULTSORT:Albert of Saxony 1316 births 1390 deaths People from Helmstedt (district) 14th-century German philosophers Catholic philosophers Roman Catholic Prince-Bishops of Halberstadt 14th-century German Roman Catholic bishops Scholastic philosophers Latin commentators on Aristotle 14th-century German mathematicians Medieval German mathematicians 14th-century Latin writers Academics of the University of Vienna University of Paris faculty Rectors of the University of Paris Charles University alumni Catholic clergy scientists German logicians German philosophers German male writers 14th-century German writers Medieval physicists