Rowbottom Cardinal
   HOME
*





Rowbottom Cardinal
In set theory, a Rowbottom cardinal, introduced by , is a certain kind of large cardinal number. An uncountable cardinal number \kappa is said to be ''\lambda- Rowbottom'' if for every function ''f'': kappa;sup><ω → λ (where λ < κ) there is a set ''H'' of order type \kappa that is quasi- for ''f'', i.e., for every ''n'', the ''f''-image of the set of ''n''-element subsets of ''H'' has < \lambda elements. \kappa is ''Rowbottom'' if it is ''\omega_1 - Rowbottom''. Every is Rowbottom, and every Rowbottom cardinal is

picture info

Set Theory
Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory, as a branch of mathematics, is mostly concerned with those that are relevant to mathematics as a whole. The modern study of set theory was initiated by the German mathematicians Richard Dedekind and Georg Cantor in the 1870s. In particular, Georg Cantor is commonly considered the founder of set theory. The non-formalized systems investigated during this early stage go under the name of '' naive set theory''. After the discovery of paradoxes within naive set theory (such as Russell's paradox, Cantor's paradox and the Burali-Forti paradox) various axiomatic systems were proposed in the early twentieth century, of which Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (with or without the axiom of choice) is still the best-known and most studied. Set theory is commonly employed as a foundational ...
[...More Info...]      
[...Related Items...]     OR:     [Wikipedia]   [Google]   [Baidu]  


Large Cardinal
In the mathematical field of set theory, a large cardinal property is a certain kind of property of transfinite cardinal numbers. Cardinals with such properties are, as the name suggests, generally very "large" (for example, bigger than the least α such that α=ωα). The proposition that such cardinals exist cannot be proved in the most common axiomatization of set theory, namely ZFC, and such propositions can be viewed as ways of measuring how "much", beyond ZFC, one needs to assume to be able to prove certain desired results. In other words, they can be seen, in Dana Scott's phrase, as quantifying the fact "that if you want more you have to assume more". There is a rough convention that results provable from ZFC alone may be stated without hypotheses, but that if the proof requires other assumptions (such as the existence of large cardinals), these should be stated. Whether this is simply a linguistic convention, or something more, is a controversial point among distinct philo ...
[...More Info...]      
[...Related Items...]     OR:     [Wikipedia]   [Google]   [Baidu]  


Uncountable Set
In mathematics, an uncountable set (or uncountably infinite set) is an infinite set that contains too many elements to be countable. The uncountability of a set is closely related to its cardinal number: a set is uncountable if its cardinal number is larger than that of the set of all natural numbers. Characterizations There are many equivalent characterizations of uncountability. A set ''X'' is uncountable if and only if any of the following conditions hold: * There is no injective function (hence no bijection) from ''X'' to the set of natural numbers. * ''X'' is nonempty and for every ω-sequence of elements of ''X'', there exists at least one element of X not included in it. That is, ''X'' is nonempty and there is no surjective function from the natural numbers to ''X''. * The cardinality of ''X'' is neither finite nor equal to \aleph_0 (aleph-null, the cardinality of the natural numbers). * The set ''X'' has cardinality strictly greater than \aleph_0. The first three ...
[...More Info...]      
[...Related Items...]     OR:     [Wikipedia]   [Google]   [Baidu]  


picture info

Cardinal Number
In mathematics, cardinal numbers, or cardinals for short, are a generalization of the natural numbers used to measure the cardinality (size) of sets. The cardinality of a finite set is a natural number: the number of elements in the set. The ''transfinite'' cardinal numbers, often denoted using the Hebrew symbol \aleph ( aleph) followed by a subscript, describe the sizes of infinite sets. Cardinality is defined in terms of bijective functions. Two sets have the same cardinality if, and only if, there is a one-to-one correspondence (bijection) between the elements of the two sets. In the case of finite sets, this agrees with the intuitive notion of size. In the case of infinite sets, the behavior is more complex. A fundamental theorem due to Georg Cantor shows that it is possible for infinite sets to have different cardinalities, and in particular the cardinality of the set of real numbers is greater than the cardinality of the set of natural numbers. It is also possible for ...
[...More Info...]      
[...Related Items...]     OR:     [Wikipedia]   [Google]   [Baidu]  


Homogeneous (large Cardinal Property)
In set theory and in the context of a large cardinal property, a subset, ''S'', of ''D'' is homogeneous for a function ''f'' if ''f'' is constant in finite subsets of ''S''. More precisely, given a set ''D'', let \mathcal_(D) be the set of all finite subsets of ''D'' (see Powerset#Subsets of limited cardinality) and let f: \mathcal_(D) \to B be a function defined in this set. On these conditions, ''S'' is homogeneous for ''f'' if, for every natural number ''n'', ''f'' is constant in the set \mathcal_(S). That is, ''f'' is constant on the unordered ''n''-tuples of elements of ''S''. See also *Ramsey's theorem *Ramsey_cardinal In mathematics, a Ramsey cardinal is a certain kind of large cardinal number introduced by and named after Frank P. Ramsey, whose theorem establishes that ω enjoys a certain property that Ramsey cardinals generalize to the uncountable case. Let ... {{settheory-stub Large cardinals ...
[...More Info...]      
[...Related Items...]     OR:     [Wikipedia]   [Google]   [Baidu]  




Ramsey Cardinal
In mathematics, a Ramsey cardinal is a certain kind of large cardinal number introduced by and named after Frank P. Ramsey, whose theorem establishes that ω enjoys a certain property that Ramsey cardinals generalize to the uncountable case. Let 'κ''sup><ω denote the set of all finite subsets of ''κ''. A cardinal number ''κ'' is called Ramsey if, for every function :''f'': 'κ''sup><ω → there is a set ''A'' of cardinality ''κ'' that is homogeneous for ''f''. That is, for every ''n'', the function ''f'' is constant on the subsets of cardinality ''n'' from ''A''. A cardinal ''κ'' is called ineffably Ramsey if ''A'' can be chosen to be a stationary subset of ''κ''. A cardinal ''κ'' is called virtually Ramsey if for every function :''f'': 'κ''sup><ω → there is ''C'', a closed and unbounded subset of ''κ'', so that for every ''λ'' in ''C'' of uncountable

Jónsson Cardinal
In set theory, a Jónsson cardinal (named after Bjarni Jónsson) is a certain kind of large cardinal number. An uncountable cardinal number κ is said to be ''Jónsson'' if for every function ''f'': sup><ω → κ there is a set ''H'' of order type κ such that for each ''n'', ''f'' restricted to ''n''-element subsets of ''H'' omits at least one value in κ. Every is Jónsson. By a theorem of Eugene M. Kleinberg, the theories ZFC + “there is a ” and ZFC + “there is a Jónsson cardinal” are equiconsistent.

Singular Cardinal
Singular may refer to: * Singular, the grammatical number that denotes a unit quantity, as opposed to the plural and other forms * Singular homology * SINGULAR, an open source Computer Algebra System (CAS) * Singular or sounder, a group of boar, see List of animal names * Singular matrix, a matrix that is not invertible * Singular measure, a measure or probability distribution whose support has zero Lebesgue (or other) measure * Singular cardinal, an infinite cardinal number that is not a regular cardinal * The property of a ''singularity'' or ''singular point'' in various meanings; see Singularity (other) * Singular (band), a Thai jazz pop duo *'' Singular: Act I'', a 2018 studio album by Sabrina Carpenter *'' Singular: Act II'', a 2019 studio album by Sabrina Carpenter See also * Singulair, Merck trademark for the drug Montelukast * Cingular Wireless AT&T Mobility LLC, also known as AT&T Wireless and marketed as simply AT&T, is an American telecommunications company ...
[...More Info...]      
[...Related Items...]     OR:     [Wikipedia]   [Google]   [Baidu]  


Axiom Of Determinacy
In mathematics, the axiom of determinacy (abbreviated as AD) is a possible axiom for set theory introduced by Jan Mycielski and Hugo Steinhaus in 1962. It refers to certain two-person topological games of length ω. AD states that every game of a certain type is determined; that is, one of the two players has a winning strategy. Steinhaus and Mycielski's motivation for AD was its interesting consequences, and suggested that AD could be true in the smallest natural model L(R) of a set theory, which accepts only a weak form of the axiom of choice (AC) but contains all real and all ordinal numbers. Some consequences of AD followed from theorems proved earlier by Stefan Banach and Stanisław Mazur, and Morton Davis. Mycielski and Stanisław Świerczkowski contributed another one: AD implies that all sets of real numbers are Lebesgue measurable. Later Donald A. Martin and others proved more important consequences, especially in descriptive set theory. In 1988, John R. Steel an ...
[...More Info...]      
[...Related Items...]     OR:     [Wikipedia]   [Google]   [Baidu]  


picture info

Axiom Of Choice
In mathematics, the axiom of choice, or AC, is an axiom of set theory equivalent to the statement that ''a Cartesian product of a collection of non-empty sets is non-empty''. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of sets, each containing at least one element, it is possible to construct a new set by arbitrarily choosing one element from each set, even if the collection is infinite. Formally, it states that for every indexed family (S_i)_ of nonempty sets, there exists an indexed set (x_i)_ such that x_i \in S_i for every i \in I. The axiom of choice was formulated in 1904 by Ernst Zermelo in order to formalize his proof of the well-ordering theorem. In many cases, a set arising from choosing elements arbitrarily can be made without invoking the axiom of choice; this is, in particular, the case if the number of sets from which to choose the elements is finite, or if a canonical rule on how to choose the elements is available – some distinguishin ...
[...More Info...]      
[...Related Items...]     OR:     [Wikipedia]   [Google]   [Baidu]