HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

Many-valued logic (also multi- or multiple-valued logic) is a propositional calculus in which there are more than two truth values. Traditionally, in
Aristotle Aristotle (; 384–322 BC) was an Ancient Greek philosophy, Ancient Greek philosopher and polymath. His writings cover a broad range of subjects spanning the natural sciences, philosophy, linguistics, economics, politics, psychology, a ...
's logical calculus, there were only two possible values (i.e., "true" and "false") for any proposition. Classical two-valued logic may be extended to ''n''-valued logic for ''n'' greater than 2. Those most popular in the literature are three-valued (e.g., Łukasiewicz's and Kleene's, which accept the values "true", "false", and "unknown"), four-valued, nine-valued, the finite-valued (finitely-many valued) with more than three values, and the infinite-valued (infinitely-many-valued), such as fuzzy logic and probability logic.


History

It is ''wrong'' that the first known classical logician who did not fully accept the law of excluded middle was
Aristotle Aristotle (; 384–322 BC) was an Ancient Greek philosophy, Ancient Greek philosopher and polymath. His writings cover a broad range of subjects spanning the natural sciences, philosophy, linguistics, economics, politics, psychology, a ...
(who, ironically, is also generally considered to be the first classical logician and the "father of wo-valuedlogic"). In fact, Aristotle did ''not'' contest the universality of the law of excluded middle, but the universality of the bivalence principle: he admitted that this principle did not all apply to future events (''De Interpretatione'', ''ch. IX''), but he didn't create a system of multi-valued logic to explain this isolated remark. Until the coming of the 20th century, later logicians followed
Aristotelian logic In logic and formal semantics, term logic, also known as traditional logic, syllogistic logic or Aristotelian logic, is a loose name for an approach to formal logic that began with Aristotle and was developed further in ancient history mostly b ...
, which includes or assumes the law of the excluded middle. The 20th century brought back the idea of multi-valued logic. The Polish logician and philosopher Jan Łukasiewicz began to create systems of many-valued logic in 1920, using a third value, "possible", to deal with Aristotle's paradox of the sea battle. Meanwhile, the American mathematician, Emil L. Post (1921), also introduced the formulation of additional truth degrees with ''n'' ≥ 2, where ''n'' are the truth values. Later, Jan Łukasiewicz and Alfred Tarski together formulated a logic on ''n'' truth values where ''n'' ≥ 2. In 1932, Hans Reichenbach formulated a logic of many truth values where ''n''→∞. Kurt Gödel in 1932 showed that intuitionistic logic is not a finitely-many valued logic, and defined a system of Gödel logics intermediate between classical and intuitionistic logic; such logics are known as intermediate logics.


Examples


Kleene (strong) and Priest logic

Kleene's "(strong) logic of indeterminacy" (sometimes K_3^S) and Priest's "logic of paradox" add a third "undefined" or "indeterminate" truth value . The truth functions for
negation In logic, negation, also called the logical not or logical complement, is an operation (mathematics), operation that takes a Proposition (mathematics), proposition P to another proposition "not P", written \neg P, \mathord P, P^\prime or \over ...
(¬), conjunction (∧), disjunction (∨), implication (), and biconditional () are given by: The difference between the two logics lies in how tautologies are defined. In only is a ''designated truth value'', while in both and are (a logical formula is considered a tautology if it evaluates to a designated truth value). In Kleene's logic can be interpreted as being "underdetermined", being neither true nor false, while in Priest's logic can be interpreted as being "overdetermined", being both true and false. does not have any tautologies, while has the same tautologies as classical two-valued logic.


Bochvar's internal three-valued logic

Another logic is Dmitry Bochvar's "internal" three-valued logic B_3^I, also called Kleene's weak three-valued logic. Except for negation and biconditional, its truth tables are all different from the above. The intermediate truth value in Bochvar's "internal" logic can be described as "contagious" because it propagates in a formula regardless of the value of any other variable.


Belnap logic ()

Belnap's logic combines and . The overdetermined truth value is here denoted as ''B'' and the underdetermined truth value as ''N''.


Gödel logics ''Gk'' and ''G''

In 1932 Gödel defined a family G_k of many-valued logics, with finitely many truth values 0, \tfrac, \tfrac, \ldots, \tfrac, 1, for example G_3 has the truth values 0, \tfrac, 1 and G_4 has 0, \tfrac, \tfrac, 1. In a similar manner he defined a logic with infinitely many truth values, G_\infty, in which the truth values are all the real numbers in the interval , 1/math>. The designated truth value in these logics is 1. The conjunction \wedge and the disjunction \vee are defined respectively as the minimum and maximum of the operands: : \begin u \wedge v &:= \min\ \\ u \vee v &:= \max\ \end Negation \neg_G and implication \xrightarrow /math> are defined as follows: : \begin \neg_G u &= \begin 1, & \textu = 0 \\ 0, & \textu > 0 \end \\ pt u \mathrel v &= \begin 1, & \textu \leq v \\ v, & \textu > v \end \end Gödel logics are completely axiomatisable, that is to say it is possible to define a logical calculus in which all tautologies are provable. The implication above is the unique Heyting implication defined by the fact that the suprema and minima operations form a complete lattice with an infinite distributive law, which defines a unique complete Heyting algebra structure on the lattice.


Łukasiewicz logics and

Implication \xrightarrow /math> and negation \underset were defined by Jan Łukasiewicz through the following functions: : \begin \underset u &:= 1 - u \\ u \mathrel v &:= \min\ \end At first Łukasiewicz used these definitions in 1920 for his three-valued logic L_3, with truth values 0, \frac, 1. In 1922 he developed a logic with infinitely many values L_\infty, in which the truth values spanned the real numbers in the interval , 1/math>. In both cases the designated truth value was 1. By adopting truth values defined in the same way as for Gödel logics 0, \tfrac, \tfrac, \ldots, \tfrac , 1, it is possible to create a finitely-valued family of logics L_v, the abovementioned L_\infty and the logic L_, in which the truth values are given by the rational numbers in the interval ,1/math>. The set of tautologies in L_\infty and L_ is identical.


Product logic

In product logic we have truth values in the interval ,1/math>, a conjunction \odot and an implication \xrightarrow Pi/math>, defined as follows : \begin u \odot v &:= uv \\ u \mathrel v &:= \begin 1, & \text u \leq v \\ \frac, & \text u > v \end \end Additionally there is a negative designated value \overline that denotes the concept of ''false''. Through this value it is possible to define a negation \underset and an additional conjunction \underset as follows: : \begin \underset u &:= u \mathrel \overline \\ u \mathbin v &:= u \odot \left(u \mathrel v\right) \end and then u \mathbin v = \min\.


Post logics ''Pm''

In 1921 Post defined a family of logics P_m with (as in L_v and G_k) the truth values 0, \tfrac 1 , \tfrac 2 , \ldots, \tfrac , 1. Negation \underset and conjunction \underset and disjunction \underset are defined as follows: : \begin \underset u &:= \begin 1, & \text u = 0 \\ u - \frac, & \text u \not= 0 \end \\ pt u \mathbin v &:= \min\ \\ pt u \mathbin v &:= \max\ \end


Rose logics

In 1951, Alan Rose defined another family of logics for systems whose truth-values form lattices.


Relation to classical logic

Logics are usually systems intended to codify rules for preserving some
semantic Semantics is the study of linguistic Meaning (philosophy), meaning. It examines what meaning is, how words get their meaning, and how the meaning of a complex expression depends on its parts. Part of this process involves the distinction betwee ...
property of propositions across transformations. In classical
logic Logic is the study of correct reasoning. It includes both formal and informal logic. Formal logic is the study of deductively valid inferences or logical truths. It examines how conclusions follow from premises based on the structure o ...
, this property is "truth." In a valid argument, the truth of the derived proposition is guaranteed if the premises are jointly true, because the application of valid steps preserves the property. However, that property doesn't have to be that of "truth"; instead, it can be some other concept. Multi-valued logics are intended to preserve the property of designationhood (or being designated). Since there are more than two truth values, rules of inference may be intended to preserve more than just whichever corresponds (in the relevant sense) to truth. For example, in a three-valued logic, sometimes the two greatest truth-values (when they are represented as e.g. positive integers) are designated and the rules of inference preserve these values. Precisely, a valid argument will be such that the value of the premises taken jointly will always be less than or equal to the conclusion. For example, the preserved property could be ''justification'', the foundational concept of intuitionistic logic. Thus, a proposition is not true or false; instead, it is justified or flawed. A key difference between justification and truth, in this case, is that the law of excluded middle doesn't hold: a proposition that is not flawed is not necessarily justified; instead, it's only not proven that it's flawed. The key difference is the determinacy of the preserved property: One may prove that ''P'' is justified, that ''P'' is flawed, or be unable to prove either. A valid argument preserves justification across transformations, so a proposition derived from justified propositions is still justified. However, there are proofs in classical logic that depend upon the law of excluded middle; since that law is not usable under this scheme, there are propositions that cannot be proven that way.


Suszko's thesis


Functional completeness of many-valued logics

Functional completeness In Mathematical logic, logic, a functionally complete set of logical connectives or Boolean function, Boolean operators is one that can be used to express all possible truth tables by combining members of the Set (mathematics), set into a Boolean ...
is a term used to describe a special property of finite logics and algebras. A logic's set of connectives is said to be ''functionally complete'' or ''adequate'' if and only if its set of connectives can be used to construct a formula corresponding to every possible truth function. An adequate algebra is one in which every finite mapping of variables can be expressed by some composition of its operations. Classical logic: CL = (, ¬, →, ∨, ∧, ↔) is functionally complete, whereas no Łukasiewicz logic or infinitely many-valued logics has this property. We can define a finitely many-valued logic as being L''n'' ( ƒ1, ..., ƒ''m'') where ''n'' ≥ 2 is a given natural number. Post (1921) proves that assuming a logic is able to produce a function of any ''m''th order model, there is some corresponding combination of connectives in an adequate logic L''n'' that can produce a model of order ''m+1''.


Applications

Known applications of many-valued logic can be roughly classified into two groups. The first group uses many-valued logic to solve binary problems more efficiently. For example, a well-known approach to represent a multiple-output Boolean function is to treat its output part as a single many-valued variable and convert it to a single-output characteristic function (specifically, the indicator function). Other applications of many-valued logic include design of programmable logic arrays (PLAs) with input decoders, optimization of finite-state machines, testing, and verification. The second group targets the design of electronic circuits that employ more than two discrete levels of signals, such as many-valued memories, arithmetic circuits, and field programmable gate arrays (FPGAs). Many-valued circuits have a number of theoretical advantages over standard binary circuits. For example, the interconnect on and off chip can be reduced if signals in the circuit assume four or more levels rather than only two. In memory design, storing two instead of one bit of information per memory cell doubles the density of the memory in the same die size. Applications using arithmetic circuits often benefit from using alternatives to binary number systems. For example, residue and redundant number systems can reduce or eliminate the ripple-carry adder, ripple-through carries that are involved in normal binary addition or subtraction, resulting in high-speed arithmetic operations. These number systems have a natural implementation using many-valued circuits. However, the practicality of these potential advantages heavily depends on the availability of circuit realizations, which must be compatible or competitive with present-day standard technologies. In addition to aiding in the design of electronic circuits, many-valued logic is used extensively to test circuits for faults and defects. Basically all known automatic test pattern generation (ATG) algorithms used for digital circuit testing require a simulator that can resolve 5-valued logic (0, 1, x, D, D'). The additional values—x, D, and D'—represent (1) unknown/uninitialized, (2) a 0 instead of a 1, and (3) a 1 instead of a 0.


Research venues

An
IEEE The Institute of Electrical and Electronics Engineers (IEEE) is an American 501(c)(3) organization, 501(c)(3) public charity professional organization for electrical engineering, electronics engineering, and other related disciplines. The IEEE ...
International Symposium on Multiple-Valued Logic (ISMVL) has been held annually since 1970. It mostly caters to applications in digital design and verification. There is also a '' Journal of Multiple-Valued Logic and Soft Computing''.


See also

;Mathematical logic * Degrees of truth * Fuzzy logic * Gödel logic * Jaina seven-valued logic * Kleene logic * Kleene algebra (with involution) * Łukasiewicz logic * MV-algebra * Post logic * Principle of bivalence * A. N. Prior * Relevance logic ;Philosophical logic * False dilemma * ''Mu'' ;Digital logic * MVCML, multiple-valued current-mode logic * IEEE 1164 a nine-valued standard for
VHDL VHDL (Very High Speed Integrated Circuit Program, VHSIC Hardware Description Language) is a hardware description language that can model the behavior and structure of Digital electronics, digital systems at multiple levels of abstraction, ran ...
* IEEE 1364 a four-valued standard for Verilog * Three-state logic * Noise-based logic


References


Further reading

General * Augusto, Luis M. (2017). ''Many-valued logics: A mathematical and computational introduction.'' London: College Publications. 340 pages.
Webpage
* Béziau J.-Y. (1997), What is many-valued logic ? ''Proceedings of the 27th International Symposium on Multiple-Valued Logic'', IEEE Computer Society, Los Alamitos, pp. 117–121. * Malinowski, Gregorz, (2001), ''Many-Valued Logics,'' in Goble, Lou, ed., ''The Blackwell Guide to Philosophical Logic''. Blackwell. * * Cignoli, R. L. O., D'Ottaviano, I, M. L., Mundici, D., (2000).
Algebraic Foundations of Many-valued Reasoning
'. Kluwer. * * S. Gottwald, ''A Treatise on Many-Valued Logics.'' Studies in Logic and Computation, vol. 9, Research Studies Press: Baldock, Hertfordshire, England, 2001. * * * Hájek P., (1998), ''Metamathematics of fuzzy logic''. Kluwer. (Fuzzy logic understood as many-valued logic sui generis.) Specific * Alexandre Zinoviev, ''Philosophical Problems of Many-Valued Logic'', D. Reidel Publishing Company, 169p., 1963. * Prior A. 1957, ''Time and Modality. Oxford University Press'', based on his 1956 John Locke lectures * Goguen J.A. 1968/69, ''The logic of inexact concepts'', Synthese, 19, 325–373. * Chang C.C. and Keisler H. J. 1966. ''Continuous Model Theory'', Princeton, Princeton University Press. * Gerla G. 2001,
Fuzzy logic: Mathematical Tools for Approximate Reasoning
', Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht. * Novák, V., Perfilieva, I., Močkoř, J., (1999), ''Mathematical Principles of Fuzzy Logic. Kluwer, Boston. * Pavelka J. 1979, ''On fuzzy logic I: Many-valued rules of inference'', Zeitschr. f. math. Logik und Grundlagen d. Math., 25, 45–52. * Covers proof theory of many-valued logics as well, in the tradition of Hájek. * * * * *


External links

* * * IEEE Computer Society'
Technical Committee on Multiple-Valued Logic

Resources for Many-Valued Logic
by Reiner Hähnle, Chalmers University
Many-valued Logics W3 Server
(archived) * * Carlos Caleiro, Walter Carnielli, Marcelo E. Coniglio and João Marcos
Two's company: "The humbug of many logical values"
in {{DEFAULTSORT:Multi-Valued Logic