HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In the foundations of mathematics, Morse–Kelley set theory (MK), Kelley–Morse set theory (KM), Morse–Tarski set theory (MT), Quine–Morse set theory (QM) or the system of Quine and Morse is a first-order
axiomatic set theory Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory, as a branch of mathematics, is mostly concern ...
that is closely related to von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel set theory (NBG). While von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel set theory restricts the bound variables in the schematic formula appearing in the
axiom schema In mathematical logic, an axiom schema (plural: axiom schemata or axiom schemas) generalizes the notion of axiom. Formal definition An axiom schema is a formula in the metalanguage of an axiomatic system, in which one or more schematic variables ...
of Class Comprehension to range over sets alone, Morse–Kelley set theory allows these bound variables to range over
proper class Proper may refer to: Mathematics * Proper map, in topology, a property of continuous function between topological spaces, if inverse images of compact subsets are compact * Proper morphism, in algebraic geometry, an analogue of a proper map f ...
es as well as sets, as first suggested by
Quine Quine may refer to: * Quine (surname), people with the surname ''Quine'' * Willard Van Orman Quine, the philosopher, or things named after him: ** Quine (computing), a program that produces its source code as output ** Quine–McCluskey algorithm, ...
in 1940 for his system ML. Morse–Kelley set theory is named after mathematicians
John L. Kelley John L. Kelley (December 6, 1916, Kansas – November 26, 1999, Berkeley, California) was an American mathematician at the University of California, Berkeley, who worked in general topology and functional analysis. Kelley's 1955 text, ''General ...
and Anthony Morse and was first set out by and later in an appendix to Kelley's textbook ''General Topology'' (1955), a graduate level introduction to
topology In mathematics, topology (from the Greek words , and ) is concerned with the properties of a geometric object that are preserved under continuous deformations, such as stretching, twisting, crumpling, and bending; that is, without closing ho ...
. Kelley said the system in his book was a variant of the systems due to Thoralf Skolem and Morse. Morse's own version appeared later in his book ''A Theory of Sets'' (1965). While von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel set theory is a conservative extension of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (ZFC, the canonical set theory) in the sense that a statement in the language of ZFC is provable in NBG if and only if it is provable in ZFC, Morse–Kelley set theory is a
proper extension In mathematical logic, a conservative extension is a supertheory of a theory which is often convenient for proving theorems, but proves no new theorems about the language of the original theory. Similarly, a non-conservative extension is a superthe ...
of ZFC. Unlike von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel set theory, where the axiom schema of Class Comprehension can be replaced with finitely many of its instances, Morse–Kelley set theory cannot be finitely axiomatized.


MK axioms and ontology

NBG and MK share a common
ontology In metaphysics, ontology is the philosophical study of being, as well as related concepts such as existence, becoming, and reality. Ontology addresses questions like how entities are grouped into categories and which of these entities ...
. The
universe of discourse In the formal sciences, the domain of discourse, also called the universe of discourse, universal set, or simply universe, is the set of entities over which certain variables of interest in some formal treatment may range. Overview The doma ...
consists of classes. Classes that are members of other classes are called sets. A class that is not a set is a
proper class Proper may refer to: Mathematics * Proper map, in topology, a property of continuous function between topological spaces, if inverse images of compact subsets are compact * Proper morphism, in algebraic geometry, an analogue of a proper map f ...
. The primitive atomic sentences involve membership or equality. With the exception of Class Comprehension, the following axioms are the same as those for NBG, inessential details aside. The symbolic versions of the axioms employ the following notational devices: * The upper case letters other than ''M'', appearing in Extensionality, Class Comprehension, and Foundation, denote variables ranging over classes. A lower case letter denotes a variable that cannot be a
proper class Proper may refer to: Mathematics * Proper map, in topology, a property of continuous function between topological spaces, if inverse images of compact subsets are compact * Proper morphism, in algebraic geometry, an analogue of a proper map f ...
, because it appears to the left of an ∈. As MK is a one-sorted theory, this notational convention is only
mnemonic A mnemonic ( ) device, or memory device, is any learning technique that aids information retention or retrieval (remembering) in the human memory for better understanding. Mnemonics make use of elaborative encoding, retrieval cues, and image ...
. * The monadic predicate \ Mx, whose intended reading is "the class ''x'' is a set", abbreviates \exists W(x \in W). * The
empty set In mathematics, the empty set is the unique set having no elements; its size or cardinality (count of elements in a set) is zero. Some axiomatic set theories ensure that the empty set exists by including an axiom of empty set, while in oth ...
\varnothing is defined by \forall x (x \not \in \varnothing). * The class ''V'', the universal class having all possible sets as members, is defined by \forall x (Mx \to x \in V). ''V'' is also the von Neumann universe.
Extensionality In logic, extensionality, or extensional equality, refers to principles that judge objects to be equal if they have the same external properties. It stands in contrast to the concept of intensionality, which is concerned with whether the internal ...
: Classes having the same members are the same class. :\forall X \, \forall Y \, ( \forall z \, (z \in X \leftrightarrow z \in Y) \rightarrow X = Y). A set and a class having the same extension are identical. Hence MK is not a two-sorted theory, appearances to the contrary notwithstanding. Foundation: Each nonempty class ''A'' is disjoint from at least one of its members. :\forall A \not = \varnothing \rightarrow \exists b (b \in A \land \forall c (c \in b \rightarrow c \not\in A)) Class Comprehension: Let φ(''x'') be any formula in the language of MK in which ''x'' is a free variable and ''Y'' is not free. φ(''x'') may contain parameters that are either sets or proper classes. More consequentially, the quantified variables in φ(''x'') may range over all classes and not just over all sets; ''this is the only way MK differs from NBG''. Then there exists a class Y=\ whose members are exactly those sets ''x'' such that \phi(x) comes out true. Formally, if ''Y'' is not free in φ: :\forall W_1 ... W_n \exists Y \forall x \in Y \leftrightarrow (\phi(x, W_1, ... W_n) \land Mx) Pairing: For any sets ''x'' and ''y'', there exists a set z=\ whose members are exactly ''x'' and ''y''. :\forall x \, \forall y \, (Mx \land My) \rightarrow \exists z \, (Mz \land \forall s \, [ s \in z \leftrightarrow (s = x \, \lor \, s = y)">s \in z \leftrightarrow (s = x \, \lor \, s = y)">(Mx \land My) \rightarrow \exists z \, (Mz \land \forall s \, [ s \in z \leftrightarrow (s = x \, \lor \, s = y) Pairing licenses the unordered pair in terms of which the
ordered pair In mathematics, an ordered pair (''a'', ''b'') is a pair of objects. The order in which the objects appear in the pair is significant: the ordered pair (''a'', ''b'') is different from the ordered pair (''b'', ''a'') unless ''a'' = ''b''. (In co ...
, \langle x,y \rangle, may be defined in the usual way, as \ \. With ordered pairs in hand, Class Comprehension enables defining
relations Relation or relations may refer to: General uses *International relations, the study of interconnection of politics, economics, and law on a global level *Interpersonal relationship, association or acquaintance between two or more people *Public ...
and function (set theory), functions on sets as sets of ordered pairs, making possible the next axiom: Axiom of limitation of size, Limitation of Size: ''C'' is a
proper class Proper may refer to: Mathematics * Proper map, in topology, a property of continuous function between topological spaces, if inverse images of compact subsets are compact * Proper morphism, in algebraic geometry, an analogue of a proper map f ...
if and only if '' V'' can be mapped one-to-one into ''C''. :\begin \forall C lnot MC \leftrightarrow \exists F ( \forall x [Mx \rightarrow \exists s (s \in C \land \langle x, s \rangle \in F)\land \\ \qquad \forall x \forall y \forall s [(\langle x, s \rangle \in F \land \langle y, s \rangle \in F) \rightarrow x = y])]. \end The formal version of this axiom resembles the
axiom schema of replacement In set theory, the axiom schema of replacement is a schema of axioms in Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (ZF) that asserts that the image of any set under any definable mapping is also a set. It is necessary for the construction of certain infi ...
, and embodies the class function ''F''. The next section explains how Limitation of Size is stronger than the usual forms of the
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, or AC, is an axiom of set theory equivalent to the statement that ''a Cartesian product of a collection of non-empty sets is non-empty''. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection ...
.
Power set In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is ...
: Let ''p'' be a class whose members are all possible
subset In mathematics, set ''A'' is a subset of a set ''B'' if all elements of ''A'' are also elements of ''B''; ''B'' is then a superset of ''A''. It is possible for ''A'' and ''B'' to be equal; if they are unequal, then ''A'' is a proper subset o ...
s of the set ''a''. Then ''p'' is a set. :\forall a \, \forall p \, Ma \land \forall x \, \in p \leftrightarrow \forall y \, (y \in x \rightarrow y \in a)">Ma \land \forall x \, Union: Let s=\bigcup a be the sum class of the set ''a'', namely the union (set theory)">union of all members of ''a''. Then ''s'' is a set. :\forall a \, \forall s \, [(Ma \land \forall x \, [x \in s \leftrightarrow \exists y \, (x \in y \land y \in a)]) \rightarrow Ms]. axiom of infinity, Infinity: There exists an inductive set ''y'', meaning that (i) the
empty set In mathematics, the empty set is the unique set having no elements; its size or cardinality (count of elements in a set) is zero. Some axiomatic set theories ensure that the empty set exists by including an axiom of empty set, while in oth ...
is a member of ''y''; (ii) if ''x'' is a member of ''y'', then so is x \cup \.. :\exists y y \land \varnothing \in y \land \forall z(z \in y \rightarrow \exists x [x \in y \land \forall w (w \in x \leftrightarrow [w = z \lor w \in z] )]. Note that ''p'' and ''s'' in Power Set and Union are universally, not existentially, quantified, as Class Comprehension suffices to establish the existence of ''p'' and ''s''. Power Set and Union only serve to establish that ''p'' and ''s'' cannot be proper classes. The above axioms are shared with other set theories as follows: * ZFC and NBG: Pairing, Power Set, Union, Infinity; * NBG (and ZFC, if quantified variables were restricted to sets): Extensionality, Foundation; * NBG: Limitation of Size.


Discussion

Monk (1980) and Rubin (1967) are set theory texts built around MK; Rubin's
ontology In metaphysics, ontology is the philosophical study of being, as well as related concepts such as existence, becoming, and reality. Ontology addresses questions like how entities are grouped into categories and which of these entities ...
includes urelements. These authors and Mendelson (1997: 287) submit that MK does what is expected of a set theory while being less cumbersome than ZFC and NBG. MK is strictly stronger than ZFC and its conservative extension NBG, the other well-known set theory with
proper class Proper may refer to: Mathematics * Proper map, in topology, a property of continuous function between topological spaces, if inverse images of compact subsets are compact * Proper morphism, in algebraic geometry, an analogue of a proper map f ...
es. In fact, NBG—and hence ZFC—can be proved consistent in MK. MK's strength stems from its axiom schema of Class Comprehension being impredicative, meaning that φ(''x'') may contain quantified variables ranging over classes. The quantified variables in NBG's axiom schema of Class Comprehension are restricted to sets; hence Class Comprehension in NBG must be predicative. (Separation with respect to sets is still impredicative in NBG, because the quantifiers in φ(''x'') may range over all sets.) The NBG axiom schema of Class Comprehension can be replaced with finitely many of its instances; this is not possible in MK. MK is consistent relative to ZFC augmented by an axiom asserting the existence of strongly inaccessible cardinals. The only advantage of the axiom of limitation of size is that it implies the axiom of global choice. Limitation of Size does not appear in Rubin (1967), Monk (1980), or Mendelson (1997). Instead, these authors invoke a usual form of the local
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, or AC, is an axiom of set theory equivalent to the statement that ''a Cartesian product of a collection of non-empty sets is non-empty''. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection ...
, and an "axiom of replacement," asserting that if the domain of a class function is a set, its range is also a set. Replacement can prove everything that Limitation of Size proves, except prove some form of the
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, or AC, is an axiom of set theory equivalent to the statement that ''a Cartesian product of a collection of non-empty sets is non-empty''. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection ...
.
Limitation of Size In the philosophy of mathematics, specifically the philosophical foundations of set theory, limitation of size is a concept developed by Philip Jourdain and/or Georg Cantor to avoid Cantor's paradox. It identifies certain "inconsistent multiplicitie ...
plus ''I'' being a set (hence the universe is nonempty) renders provable the sethood of the empty set; hence no need for an
axiom of empty set In axiomatic set theory, the axiom of empty set is a statement that asserts the existence of a set with no elements. It is an axiom of Kripke–Platek set theory and the variant of general set theory that Burgess (2005) calls "ST," and a demonstrab ...
. Such an axiom could be added, of course, and minor perturbations of the above axioms would necessitate this addition. The set ''I'' is not identified with the limit ordinal \omega, as ''I'' could be a set larger than \omega. In this case, the existence of \omega would follow from either form of Limitation of Size. The class of von Neumann ordinals can be well-ordered. It cannot be a set (under pain of paradox); hence that class is a proper class, and all proper classes have the same size as ''V''. Hence ''V'' too can be well-ordered. MK can be confused with second-order ZFC, ZFC with
second-order logic In logic and mathematics, second-order logic is an extension of first-order logic, which itself is an extension of propositional logic. Second-order logic is in turn extended by higher-order logic and type theory. First-order logic quantifies ...
(representing second-order objects in set rather than predicate language) as its background logic. The language of second-order ZFC is similar to that of MK (although a set and a class having the same extension can no longer be identified), and their syntactical resources for practical proof are almost identical (and are identical if MK includes the strong form of Limitation of Size). But the
semantics Semantics (from grc, σημαντικός ''sēmantikós'', "significant") is the study of reference, meaning, or truth. The term can be used to refer to subfields of several distinct disciplines, including philosophy, linguistics and compu ...
of second-order ZFC are quite different from those of MK. For example, if MK is consistent then it has a countable first-order model, while second-order ZFC has no countable models.


Model theory

ZFC, NBG, and MK each have models describable in terms of ''V'', the
von Neumann universe of sets In set theory and related branches of mathematics, the von Neumann universe, or von Neumann hierarchy of sets, denoted by ''V'', is the class of hereditary well-founded sets. This collection, which is formalized by Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (ZF ...
in ZFC. Let the inaccessible cardinal κ be a member of ''V''. Also let Def(''X'') denote the Δ0 definable
subset In mathematics, set ''A'' is a subset of a set ''B'' if all elements of ''A'' are also elements of ''B''; ''B'' is then a superset of ''A''. It is possible for ''A'' and ''B'' to be equal; if they are unequal, then ''A'' is a proper subset o ...
s of ''X'' (see
constructible universe In mathematics, in set theory, the constructible universe (or Gödel's constructible universe), denoted by , is a particular class of sets that can be described entirely in terms of simpler sets. is the union of the constructible hierarchy . It ...
). Then: * ''V''κ is model of ZFC; * Def(''V''κ) is a model of Mendelson's version of NBG, which excludes global choice, replacing limitation of size by replacement and ordinary choice; * ''V''κ+1, the
power set In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is ...
of ''V''κ, is a model of MK.


History

MK was first set out in and popularized in an appendix to J. L. Kelley's (1955) ''General Topology'', using the axioms given in the next section. The system of Anthony Morse's (1965) ''A Theory of Sets'' is equivalent to Kelley's, but formulated in an idiosyncratic formal language rather than, as is done here, in standard
first-order logic First-order logic—also known as predicate logic, quantificational logic, and first-order predicate calculus—is a collection of formal systems used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. First-order logic uses quanti ...
. The first set theory to include impredicative class comprehension was Quine's ML, that built on New Foundations rather than on ZFC. Impredicative class comprehension was also proposed in
Mostowski Mostowski (feminine: Mostowska, plural: Mostowscy) is a surname. It may refer to: * Mostowski Palace ( pl, Pałac Mostowskich), an 18th-century palace in Warsaw * Andrzej Mostowski (1913 - 1975), a Polish mathematician ** Mostowski collapse lemma, ...
(1951) and Lewis (1991).


The axioms in Kelley's ''General Topology''

The axioms and definitions in this section are, but for a few inessential details, taken from the Appendix to Kelley (1955). The explanatory remarks below are not his. The Appendix states 181 theorems and definitions, and warrants careful reading as an abbreviated exposition of axiomatic set theory by a working mathematician of the first rank. Kelley introduced his axioms gradually, as needed to develop the topics listed after each instance of ''Develop'' below. Notations appearing below and now well-known are not defined. Peculiarities of Kelley's notation include: * He did ''not'' distinguish variables ranging over classes from those ranging over sets; * ''domain f'' and ''range f'' denote the domain and range of the function ''f''; this peculiarity has been carefully respected below; * His primitive logical language includes class abstracts of the form \ \, "the class of all sets ''x'' satisfying ''A''(''x'')." Definition: ''x'' is a ''set'' (and hence not a
proper class Proper may refer to: Mathematics * Proper map, in topology, a property of continuous function between topological spaces, if inverse images of compact subsets are compact * Proper morphism, in algebraic geometry, an analogue of a proper map f ...
) if, for some ''y'', x \in y. I. Extent: For each ''x'' and each ''y'', ''x=y'' if and only if for each ''z'', z \in x when and only when z \in y. Identical to ''Extensionality'' above. I would be identical to the
axiom of extensionality In axiomatic set theory and the branches of logic, mathematics, and computer science that use it, the axiom of extensionality, or axiom of extension, is one of the axioms of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory. It says that sets having the same elemen ...
in ZFC, except that the scope of I includes proper classes as well as sets. II. Classification (schema): An axiom results if in : For each \beta, \beta \in \ if and only if \beta is a set and B, 'α' and 'β' are replaced by variables, ' ''A'' ' by a formula Æ, and ' ''B'' ' by the formula obtained from Æ by replacing each occurrence of the variable that replaced α by the variable that replaced β provided that the variable that replaced β does not appear bound in ''A''. ''Develop'': Boolean
algebra of sets In mathematics, the algebra of sets, not to be confused with the mathematical structure of ''an'' algebra of sets, defines the properties and laws of sets, the set-theoretic operations of union, intersection, and complementation and the r ...
. Existence of the null class and of the universal class ''V''. III. Subsets: If ''x'' is a set, there exists a set ''y'' such that for each ''z'', if z \subseteq x, then z \in y. The import of III is that of ''Power Set'' above. Sketch of the proof of Power Set from III: for any ''class'' ''z'' that is a subclass of the set ''x'', the class ''z'' is a member of the set ''y'' whose existence III asserts. Hence ''z'' is a set. ''Develop'': ''V'' is not a set. Existence of singletons.
Separation Separation may refer to: Films * ''Separation'' (1967 film), a British feature film written by and starring Jane Arden and directed by Jack Bond * ''La Séparation'', 1994 French film * ''A Separation'', 2011 Iranian film * ''Separation'' (20 ...
provable. IV. Union: If ''x'' and ''y'' are both sets, then x \cup y is a set. The import of IV is that of ''Pairing'' above. Sketch of the proof of Pairing from IV: the singleton \ of a set ''x'' is a set because it is a subclass of the power set of ''x'' (by two applications of III). Then IV implies that \ is a set if ''x'' and ''y'' are sets. ''Develop'': Unordered and
ordered pair In mathematics, an ordered pair (''a'', ''b'') is a pair of objects. The order in which the objects appear in the pair is significant: the ordered pair (''a'', ''b'') is different from the ordered pair (''b'', ''a'') unless ''a'' = ''b''. (In co ...
s,
relations Relation or relations may refer to: General uses *International relations, the study of interconnection of politics, economics, and law on a global level *Interpersonal relationship, association or acquaintance between two or more people *Public ...
, functions, domain, range,
function composition In mathematics, function composition is an operation that takes two functions and , and produces a function such that . In this operation, the function is applied to the result of applying the function to . That is, the functions and ...
. V. Substitution: If ''f'' is a lassfunction and ''domain f'' is a set, then ''range f'' is a set. The import of V is that of the
axiom schema of replacement In set theory, the axiom schema of replacement is a schema of axioms in Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (ZF) that asserts that the image of any set under any definable mapping is also a set. It is necessary for the construction of certain infi ...
in NBG and ZFC. VI. Amalgamation: If ''x'' is a set, then \bigcup x is a set. The import of VI is that of ''Union'' above. IV and VI may be combined into one axiom.Kelley (1955), p. 261, fn †. ''Develop'':
Cartesian product In mathematics, specifically set theory, the Cartesian product of two sets ''A'' and ''B'', denoted ''A''×''B'', is the set of all ordered pairs where ''a'' is in ''A'' and ''b'' is in ''B''. In terms of set-builder notation, that is : A\ ...
, injection,
surjection In mathematics, a surjective function (also known as surjection, or onto function) is a function that every element can be mapped from element so that . In other words, every element of the function's codomain is the image of one element of ...
, bijection, order theory. VII. Regularity: If x \neq \varnothing there is a member ''y'' of ''x'' such that x \cap y = \varnothing. The import of VII is that of ''Foundation'' above. ''Develop'': Ordinal numbers,
transfinite induction Transfinite induction is an extension of mathematical induction to well-ordered sets, for example to sets of ordinal numbers or cardinal numbers. Its correctness is a theorem of ZFC. Induction by cases Let P(\alpha) be a property defined for ...
. VIII. Infinity: There exists a set ''y'', such that \varnothing \in y and x \cup \ \in y whenever x \in y. This axiom, or equivalents thereto, are included in ZFC and NBG. VIII asserts the unconditional existence of two sets, the infinite inductive set ''y'', and the null set \varnothing. \varnothing is a set simply because it is a member of ''y''. Up to this point, everything that has been proved to exist is a class, and Kelley's discussion of sets was entirely hypothetical. ''Develop'':
Natural number In mathematics, the natural numbers are those numbers used for counting (as in "there are ''six'' coins on the table") and ordering (as in "this is the ''third'' largest city in the country"). Numbers used for counting are called '' cardinal ...
s, N is a set, Peano axioms,
integer An integer is the number zero (), a positive natural number (, , , etc.) or a negative integer with a minus sign ( −1, −2, −3, etc.). The negative numbers are the additive inverses of the corresponding positive numbers. In the language ...
s,
rational number In mathematics, a rational number is a number that can be expressed as the quotient or fraction of two integers, a numerator and a non-zero denominator . For example, is a rational number, as is every integer (e.g. ). The set of all ra ...
s,
real number In mathematics, a real number is a number that can be used to measurement, measure a ''continuous'' one-dimensional quantity such as a distance, time, duration or temperature. Here, ''continuous'' means that values can have arbitrarily small var ...
s. Definition: ''c'' is a ''choice function'' if ''c'' is a function and c(x) \in x for each member ''x'' of ''domain c''. IX. Choice: There exists a choice function ''c'' whose domain is V - \.. IX is very similar to the axiom of global choice derivable from ''Limitation of Size'' above. ''Develop'':
Equivalents ''Equivalents'' is a series of photographs of clouds taken by Alfred Stieglitz from 1925 to 1934. They are generally recognized as the first photographs intended to free the subject matter from literal interpretation, and, as such, are some of t ...
of the axiom of choice. As is the case with ZFC, the development of the
cardinal number In mathematics, cardinal numbers, or cardinals for short, are a generalization of the natural numbers used to measure the cardinality (size) of sets. The cardinality of a finite set is a natural number: the number of elements in the set. T ...
s requires some form of choice. If the scope of all quantified variables in the above axioms is restricted to sets, all axioms except III and the schema IV are ZFC axioms. IV is provable in ZFC. Hence the Kelley treatment of MK makes very clear that all that distinguishes MK from ZFC are variables ranging over
proper class Proper may refer to: Mathematics * Proper map, in topology, a property of continuous function between topological spaces, if inverse images of compact subsets are compact * Proper morphism, in algebraic geometry, an analogue of a proper map f ...
es as well as sets, and the Classification schema.


Notes


References

*
John L. Kelley John L. Kelley (December 6, 1916, Kansas – November 26, 1999, Berkeley, California) was an American mathematician at the University of California, Berkeley, who worked in general topology and functional analysis. Kelley's 1955 text, ''General ...
1975 (1955) ''General Topology''. Springer. Earlier ed., Van Nostrand. Appendix, "Elementary Set Theory." * Lemmon, E. J. (1986) ''Introduction to Axiomatic Set Theory''. Routledge & Kegan Paul. * David K. Lewis (1991) ''Parts of Classes''. Oxford: Basil Blackwell. * The definitive treatment of the closely related set theory NBG, followed by a page on MK. Harder than Monk or Rubin. * Monk, J. Donald (1980) ''Introduction to Set Theory''. Krieger. Easier and less thorough than Rubin. * Morse, A. P., (1965) ''A Theory of Sets''. Academic Press. * . * Rubin, Jean E. (1967) ''Set Theory for the Mathematician''. San Francisco: Holden Day. More thorough than Monk; the ontology includes urelements. * .


External links


Download ''General Topology'' (1955) by John L. Kelley in various formats. The appendix contains Kelley's axiomatic development of MK.
From Foundations of Mathematics (FOM) discussion group:



{{DEFAULTSORT:Morse-Kelly set theory Systems of set theory