Linear Temporal Logic To Büchi Automaton
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
formal verification In the context of hardware and software systems, formal verification is the act of proving or disproving the correctness of intended algorithms underlying a system with respect to a certain formal specification or property, using formal met ...
, finite state model checking needs to find a
Büchi automaton In computer science and automata theory, a deterministic Büchi automaton is a theoretical machine which either accepts or rejects infinite inputs. Such a machine has a set of states and a transition function, which determines which state the machi ...
(BA) equivalent to a given linear temporal logic (LTL) formula, i.e., such that the LTL formula and the BA recognize the same
ω-language In formal language theory within theoretical computer science, an infinite word is an infinite-length sequence (specifically, an ω-length sequence) of symbols, and an ω-language is a set of infinite words. Here, ω refers to the first ordinal ...
. There are algorithms that translate an LTL formula to a BA.M.Y. Vardi and P. Wolper, Reasoning about infinite computations,
Information and Computation ''Information and Computation'' is a closed-access computer science journal published by Elsevier (formerly Academic Press). The journal was founded in 1957 under its former name ''Information and Control'' and given its current title in 1987. , ...
, 115(1994), 1–37.
Y. Kesten, Z. Manna, H. McGuire, A. Pnueli, A decision algorithm for full propositional temporal logic, CAV’93, Elounda, Greece, LNCS 697, Springer–Verlag, 97-109.R. Gerth, D. Peled, M.Y. Vardi and P. Wolper, "Simple On-The-Fly Automatic Verification of Linear Temporal Logic," Proc. IFIP/WG6.1 Symp. Protocol Specification, Testing, and Verification (PSTV95), pp. 3-18,Warsaw, Poland, Chapman & Hall, June 1995. P. Gastin and D. Oddoux, Fast LTL to Büchi automata translation, Thirteenth Conference on Computer Aided Verification (CAV ′01), number 2102 in LNCS, Springer-Verlag (2001), pp. 53–65. This transformation is normally done in two steps. The first step produces a generalized Büchi automaton (GBA) from a LTL formula. The second step translates this GBA into a BA, which involves a relatively easy construction. Since LTL is strictly less expressive than BA, the reverse construction is not always possible. The algorithms for transforming LTL to GBA differ in their construction strategies but they all have a common underlying principle, i.e., each state in the constructed automaton represents a set of LTL formulas that are ''expected'' to be satisfied by the remaining input word after occurrence of the state during a run.


Transformation from LTL to GBA

Here, two algorithms are presented for the construction. The first one provides a declarative and easy-to-understand construction. The second one provides an algorithmic and efficient construction. Both the algorithms assume that the input formula f is constructed using the set of propositional variables ''AP'' and f is in
negation normal form In mathematical logic, a formula is in negation normal form (NNF) if the negation operator (\lnot, ) is only applied to variables and the only other allowed Boolean operators are conjunction (\land, ) and disjunction (\lor, ). Negation normal for ...
. For each LTL formula f' without ¬ as top symbol, let ''neg''(f') = ¬f' and ''neg''(¬f') = f'. For a special case f'=true, let ''neg''(true) = false.


Declarative construction

Before describing the construction, we need to present a few auxiliary definitions. For an LTL formula ''f'', Let ''cl''( f ) be the smallest set of formulas that satisfies the following conditions: ''cl''( f ) is closure of sub-formulas of f under ''neg''. Note that ''cl''( f ) may contain formulas that are not in negation normal form. The subsets of ''cl''( f ) are going to serve as states of the equivalent GBA. We aim to construct the GBA such that if a state ''corresponds'' to a subset M ⊆ ''cl''( f ) then the GBA has an accepting run starting from the state for a word if and only if the word satisfies every formula in M and violates every formula in ''cl''( f ) \ M. For this reason, we will not consider each formula set M that is clearly inconsistent or subsumed by a strict superset M' such that M and M' are equiv-satisfiable. A set M ⊆ ''cl''( f ) is ''maximally consistent'' if it satisfies the following conditions: Let ''cs''( f ) be the set of maximally consistent subsets of ''cl''( f ). We are going to use only ''cs''( f ) as the states of GBA. ;GBA construction An equivalent
GBA The (GBA) is a 32-bit handheld game console developed, manufactured and marketed by Nintendo as the successor to the Game Boy Color. It was released in Japan on March 21, 2001, in North America on June 11, 2001, in the PAL region on June 22, 2 ...
to f is ''A''= (∪''cs''( f ), 2''AP'', Δ,,F), where * Δ = Δ1 ∪ Δ2 ** (M, a, M') ∈ Δ1 iff ( M' ∩''AP'' ) ⊆ a ⊆ and: *** X f1 ∈ M iff f1 ∈ M'; *** f1 U f2 ∈ M iff f2 ∈ M or ( f1 ∈ M and f1 U f2 ∈ M' ); *** f1 R f2 ∈ M iff f1 ∧ f2 ∈ M or ( f2 ∈ M and f1 R f2 ∈ M' ) ** Δ2 = * For each f1 U f2 ∈ ''cl''( f ),  ∈ F The three conditions in definition of Δ1 ensure that any run of ''A'' does not violate semantics of the temporal operators. Note that F is a set of sets of states. The sets in F are defined to capture a property of operator U that can not be verified by comparing two consecutive states in a run, i.e., if f1 U f2 is true in some state then eventually f2 is true at some state later. Let ω-word ''w''= a1, a2,... over alphabet 2''AP''. Let ''w''i = ai, ai+1,... . Let M''w'' = , which we call ''satisfying'' set. Due to the definition of ''cs''(f), M''w'' ∈ ''cs''(f). We can define a sequence ρ''w'' = init, M''w''1, M''w''2,... . Due to the definition of ''A'', if w \vDash f then ρ''w'' must be an accepting run of ''A'' over ''w''. Conversely, lets assume ''A'' accepts ''w''. Let ρ = init, M1, M2,... be a run of ''A'' over ''w''. The following theorem completes the rest of the correctness proof. Theorem 1: For all i > 0, M''w''i = Mi. Proof: The proof is by induction on the structure of f' ∈ ''cl''(f). * Base cases: ** f' = true. By definitions, f' ∈ M''w''i and f' ∈ Mi. ** f' = p. By definition of ''A'', p ∈ Mi iff p ∈ ai iff p ∈ M''w''i. * Induction steps: ** f' = f1 ∧ f2. Due to the definition of consistent sets, f1 ∧ f2 ∈ Mi iff f1 ∈ Mi and f2 ∈ Mi. Due to induction hypothesis, f1 ∈ M''w''i and f2 ∈ M''w''i. Due to definition of satisfying set, f1 ∧ f2 ∈ M''w''i. ** f' = ¬f1, f' = f1 ∨ f2, f' = X f1 or f' = f1 R f2. The proofs are very similar to the last one. ** f' = f1 U f2. The proof of equality is divided in two entailment proofs. *** If f1 U f2 ∈ Mi, then f1 U f2 ∈ M''w''i. By the definition of the transitions of ''A'', we can have the following two cases. **** f2 ∈ Mi. By induction hypothesis, f2 ∈ M''w''i. So, f1 U f2 ∈ M''w''i. **** f1 ∈ Mi and f1 U f2 ∈ Mi+1. And due to the acceptance condition of ''A'', there is at least one index j ≥ i such that f2 ∈ Mj. Let j' be the smallest of these indices. We prove the result by induction on k = . If k = j', then f2 ∈ Mk, we apply same argument as in the case of f2 ∈ Mi. If i ≤ k < j', then f2 ∉ Mk, and so f1 ∈ Mk and f1 U f2 ∈ Mk+1. Due to induction hypothesis on f', we have f1 ∈ M''w''k. Due to induction hypothesis on indices, we also have f1 U f2 ∈ M''w''k+1. Due to definition of the semantics of LTL, f1 U f2 ∈ M''w''k. *** If f1 U f2 ∈ M''w''i, then f1 U f2 ∈ Mi. Due to the LTL semantics, we can have the following two cases. **** f2 ∈ M''w''i. By induction hypothesis, f2 ∈ Mi. So, f1 U f2 ∈ Mi. **** f1 ∈ M''w''i and f1 U f2 ∈ M''w''i+1. Due to the LTL semantics, there is at least one index j ≥ i such that f2 ∈ Mj. Let j' be the smallest of these indices. Proceed now as in proof of the converse entailment. Due to the above theorem, M''w''1 = M1. Due to the definition of the transitions of ''A'', f ∈ M1. Therefore, f ∈ M''w''1 and ''w'' \vDash f.


Gerth et al. algorithm

The following algorithm is due to Gerth, Peled, Vardi, and Wolper. A verified construction mechanism of this by Schimpf, Merz and Smaus is also available.A. Schimpf, S. Merz, and J.-G. Smaus, "Construction of Büchi Automata for LTL Model Checking Verified in Isabelle/HOL," Proc. International Conference on Theorem Proving in Higher Order Logics (TPHOLs 2009), pp. 424-439, Munich, Germany, Springer, August 2009. The previous construction creates exponentially many states upfront and many of those states may be unreachable. The following algorithm avoids this upfront construction and has two steps. In the first step, it incrementally constructs a directed graph. In the second step, it builds a labeled generalized Büchi automaton (LGBA) by defining nodes of the graph as states and directed edges as transitions. This algorithm takes reachability into account and may produce a smaller automaton but the worst-case complexity remains the same. The nodes of the graph are labeled by sets of formulas and are obtained by decomposing formulas according to their Boolean structure, and by expanding the temporal operators in order to separate what has to be true immediately from what has to be true from the next state onwards. For example, let us assume that an LTL formula f1 U f2 appears in the label of a node. f1 U f2 is equivalent to f2 ∨ ( f1 ∧ X(f1 U f2) ). The equivalent expansion suggests that f1 U f2 is true in one of the following two conditions. # f1 holds at the current time and (f1 U f2) holds at the next time step, or # f2 holds at the current time step The two cases can be encoded by creating two states (nodes) of the automaton and the automaton may non-deterministically jump to either of them. In the first case, we have offloaded a part of burden of proof in the next time step therefore we also create another state (node) that will carry the obligation for next time step in its label. We also need to consider temporal operator R that may cause such case split. f1 R f2 is equivalent to ( f1 ∧ f2) ∨ ( f2 ∧ X(f1 R f2) ) and this equivalent expansion suggests that f1 R f2 is true in one of the following two conditions. # f2 holds at the current time and (f1 R f2) holds at the next time step, or # ( f1 ∧ f2) holds at the current time step. To avoid many cases in the following algorithm, let us define functions ''curr1'', ''next1'' and ''curr2'' that encode the above equivalences in the following table. We have also added disjunction case in the above table since it also causes a case split in the automaton. Following are the two steps of the algorithm. ;Step 1. create_graph In the following box, we present the first part of the algorithm that builds a directed graph. ''create_graph'' is the entry function, which expects the input formula f in the
negation normal form In mathematical logic, a formula is in negation normal form (NNF) if the negation operator (\lnot, ) is only applied to variables and the only other allowed Boolean operators are conjunction (\land, ) and disjunction (\lor, ). Negation normal for ...
. It calls recursive function ''expand'' that builds the graph by populating global variables ''Nodes'', ''Incoming'', ''Now'', and ''Next''. The set ''Nodes'' stores the set of nodes in the graph. The map ''Incoming'' maps each node of ''Nodes'' to a subset of ''Nodes'' ∪ , which defines the set of incoming edges. ''Incoming'' of a node may also contain a special symbol init that is used in the final automaton construction to decide the set of initial states. ''Now'' and ''Next'' map each node of ''Nodes'' to a set of LTL formulas. For a node q, ''Now''(q) denotes the set of formulas that must be satisfied by the rest of the input word if the automaton is currently at node(state) q. ''Next''(q) denotes the set of formulas that must be satisfied by the rest of the input word if the automaton is currently at the next node(state) after q. function expand(LTLSet curr, LTLSet old, LTLSet next, NodeSet incoming) The code of ''expand'' is labelled with line numbers for easy reference. Each call to ''expand'' aims to add a node and its successors nodes in the graph. The parameters of the call describes a potential new node. * The first parameter ''curr'' contains the set of formulas that are yet to be expanded. * The second parameter ''old'' contains the set of formulas that are already expanded. * The third parameter ''next'' is the set of the formula using which successor node will be created. * The fourth parameter ''incoming'' defines set of incoming edges when the node is added to the graph. At line 1, the if condition checks if ''curr'' contains any formula to be expanded. If the ''curr'' is empty then at line 2 the if condition checks if there already exists a state q' with same set of expanded formulas. If that is the case, then we do not add a redundant node, but we add parameter ''incoming'' in ''Incoming''(q') at line 3. Otherwise, we add a new node q using the parameters at lines 5–9 and we start expanding a successor node of q using ''next''(q) as its unexpanded set of formulas at line 10. In the case ''curr'' is not empty, then we have more formulas to expand and control jumps from line 1 to 12. At lines 12–14, a formula f from ''curr'' is selected and moved to ''old''. Depending on structure of f, the rest of the function executes. * If f is a literal, then expansion continues at line 20, but if ''old'' already contains ''neg''(f) or f=false, then ''old'' contains an inconsistent formula and we discard this node by not making any recursive all at line 18. * If f = f1 ∧ f2, then f1 and f2 are added to ''curr'' and a recursive call is made for further expansion at line 22. * If f = X f1, then f1 is added to ''next'' for the successor of the current node under consideration at line 24. * If f = f1 ∨ f2, f = f1 U f2, or f = f1 R f2 then the current node is divided into two nodes and for each node a recursive call is made. For the recursive calls, ''curr'' and ''next'' are modified using functions ''curr1'', ''next1'', and ''curr2'' that were defined in the above table. ; Step 2. LGBA construction Let (''Nodes'', ''Now'', ''Incoming'') = create_graph(f). An equivalent LGBA to f is ''A''=(''Nodes'', 2''AP'', ''L'', Δ, ''Q''0, F), where * ''L'' = * Δ = * ''Q''0 = * For each sub-formula g = g1 U g2, let Fg = , then F = Note that node labels in the algorithmic construction do not contain negation of sub-formulas of f. In the declarative construction a node has the set of formulas that are expected to be true. The algorithmic construction ensures the correctness without the need of all the true formulas to be present in a node label.


Tools


SPOT LTL2TGBA
- LTL2TGBA translator included in Object-oriented model checking library SPOT. Online translator available.
LTL2BA
- Fast LTL to BA translator via alternating automata. Online translator available.
LTL3BA
- An up-to-date improvement of LTL2BA.


References

{{DEFAULTSORT:Linear temporal logic to Buchi automaton Automata (computation) Model checking Temporal logic