In
semantics
Semantics (from grc, σημαντικός ''sēmantikós'', "significant") is the study of reference, meaning, or truth. The term can be used to refer to subfields of several distinct disciplines, including philosophy, linguistics and compu ...
,
mathematical logic
Mathematical logic is the study of formal logic within mathematics. Major subareas include model theory, proof theory, set theory, and recursion theory. Research in mathematical logic commonly addresses the mathematical properties of formal ...
and related disciplines, the principle of compositionality is the principle that the meaning of a complex expression is determined by the meanings of its constituent expressions and the rules used to combine them. This principle is also called Frege's principle, because
Gottlob Frege
Friedrich Ludwig Gottlob Frege (; ; 8 November 1848 – 26 July 1925) was a German philosopher, logician, and mathematician. He was a mathematics professor at the University of Jena, and is understood by many to be the father of analytic ph ...
is widely credited for the first modern formulation of it. The principle was never explicitly stated by Frege, and it was arguably already assumed by
George Boole
George Boole (; 2 November 1815 – 8 December 1864) was a largely self-taught English mathematician, philosopher, and logician, most of whose short career was spent as the first professor of mathematics at Queen's College, Cork in ...
decades before Frege's work.
The principle of compositionality is highly debated in linguistics, and among its most challenging problems there are the issues of
contextuality, the non-compositionality of
idiomatic expressions, and the non-compositionality of
quotation
A quotation is the repetition of a sentence, phrase, or passage from speech or text that someone has said or written. In oral speech, it is the representation of an utterance (i.e. of something that a speaker actually said) that is introduced by ...
s.
History
Discussion of compositionality started to appear at the beginning of the 19th century, during which it was debated whether what was most fundamental in language was compositionality or
contextuality, and compositionality was usually preferred.
Frege (1848-1925) never adhered to the principle of compositionality as it is known today, and the first to explicitly formulate it was Freges' student
Rudolf Carnap in 1947.
[Janssen (2012)]
Overview
The principle of compositionality states that in a meaningful expression, if the
lexical parts are taken out of the sentence, what remains will be the rules of composition. Take, for example, the sentence "Socrates was a man". Once the meaningful lexical items are taken away—"Socrates" and "man"—what is left is the pseudo-sentence, "S was a M". The task becomes a matter of describing what the connection is between S and M.
Among the most prominent linguistic problems that challenge the principle of compositionality are the issues of
contextuality, the non compositionality of
idiomatic expressions, and the non compositionality of
quotation
A quotation is the repetition of a sentence, phrase, or passage from speech or text that someone has said or written. In oral speech, it is the representation of an utterance (i.e. of something that a speaker actually said) that is introduced by ...
s.
[Pelletier (2016) section ''"12 This Chapter"'']
It is frequently taken to mean that every operation of the
syntax should be associated with an operation of the semantics that acts on the meanings of the constituents combined by the syntactic operation. As a guideline for constructing semantic theories, this is generally taken, as in the influential work on the philosophy of language by
Donald Davidson, to mean that every construct of the syntax should be associated by a clause of the
T-schema with an operator in the semantics that specifies how the meaning of the whole expression is built from constituents combined by the syntactic rule. In some general mathematical theories (especially those in the tradition of
Montague grammar __notoc__
Montague grammar is an approach to natural language semantics, named after American logician Richard Montague. The Montague grammar is based on mathematical logic, especially higher-order predicate logic and lambda calculus, and makes use ...
), this guideline is taken to mean that the interpretation of a language is essentially given by a
homomorphism
In algebra, a homomorphism is a structure-preserving map between two algebraic structures of the same type (such as two groups, two rings, or two vector spaces). The word ''homomorphism'' comes from the Ancient Greek language: () meaning "sa ...
between an algebra of syntactic representations and an algebra of semantic objects.
The principle of compositionality also exists in a similar form in the
compositionality of programming languages.
Critiques
The principle of compositionality has been the subject of intense debate. Indeed, there is no general agreement as to how the principle is to be interpreted, although there have been several attempts to provide formal definitions of it.
[Szabó, Zoltán Gendler (2012)]
Compositionality
. In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. First published Thu Apr 8, 2004; substantive revision Fri Dec 7, 2012
Scholars are also divided as to whether the principle should be regarded as a factual claim, open to
empirical testing; an
analytic truth, obvious from the nature of language and meaning; or a
methodological principle to guide the development of theories of syntax and semantics. The Principle of Compositionality has been attacked in all three spheres, although so far none of the criticisms brought against it have been generally regarded as compelling. Most proponents of the principle, however, make certain exceptions for
idiomatic expressions in natural language.
The principle of compositionality usually holds when only syntactic factors play in the increased complexity of
sentence processing
Sentence processing takes place whenever a reader or listener processes a language utterance, either in isolation or in the context of a conversation or a text. Many studies of the human language comprehension process have focused on reading of s ...
, while it becomes more problematic and questionable when the complexity increase is due to sentence or discourse
context,
semantic memory, or
sensory cues. Among the problematic phenomena for traditional theories of compositionality is that of
logical metonymy
Logic is the study of correct reasoning. It includes both formal and informal logic. Formal logic is the science of deductively valid inferences or of logical truths. It is a formal science investigating how conclusions follow from premis ...
, which has been studied at least since the mid 1990s by linguists
James Pustejovsky
James Pustejovsky (born 1956) is an American computer scientist. He is the TJX Feldberg professor of computer science at Brandeis University in Waltham, Massachusetts, United States. His expertise includes theoretical and computational modelin ...
and
Ray Jackendoff.
[Chersoni, E., Lenci, A., & Blache, P. (2017, August). ]
Logical metonymy in a distributional model of sentence comprehension
'. In Sixth Joint Conference on Lexical and Computational Semantics (* SEM 2017) (pp. 168-177).[Ray Jackendoff. 1997. The Architecture of the Language Faculty. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.] Logical metonymies are sentences like ''John began the book'', where the verb ''to begin'' requires (
subcategorizes) an event as its argument, but in a logical metonymy an object (i.e. ''the book'') is found instead, and this forces to interpret the sentence by inferring an implicit event ("reading", "writing", or other prototypical actions performed on a book).
The problem for compositionality is that the meaning of reading or writing is not present in the words of the sentence, neither in "begin" nor in "book".
Further, in the context of the philosophy of language, the principle of compositionality does not explain all of meaning. For example, you cannot infer
sarcasm
Sarcasm is the caustic use of words, often in a humorous way, to mock someone or something. Sarcasm may employ ambivalence, although it is not necessarily ironic. Most noticeable in spoken word, sarcasm is mainly distinguished by the inflection ...
purely on the basis of words and their composition, yet a phrase used sarcastically means something completely different from the same phrase uttered straightforwardly. Thus, some theorists argue that the principle has to be revised to take into account linguistic and extralinguistic
context, which includes the tone of voice used, common ground between the speakers, the intentions of the speaker, and so on.
See also
*
Componential analysis Componential analysis (feature analysis or contrast analysis) is the analysis of words through structured sets of semantic features, which are given as "present", "absent" or "indifferent with reference to feature". The method thus departs from the ...
*
Context principle
*
Semantics (computer science)
In programming language theory, semantics is the rigorous mathematical study of the meaning of programming languages. Semantics assigns computational meaning to valid strings in a programming language syntax.
Semantics describes the proces ...
*
Semantics of logic
*
Garden-path sentence
*
Initial algebra
*
Levels of Processing model
*
Opaque context — another problem for compositionality
*
Referential transparency — in programming languages
*
Semantic decomposition (natural language processing)
Notes
References
* Baggio, G., Van Lambalgen, M., & Hagoort, P. (2012)
The processing consequences of compositionality', in M. Werning, W. Hinzen, & E. Machery (Eds.),
The Oxford handbook of compositionality' (pp. 655–672).
* Janssen, T. M. (2012)
Compositionality: Its historic context', in M. Werning, W. Hinzen, & E. Machery (Eds.),
The Oxford handbook of compositionality', pp. 19-46, Oxford University Press.
* Pelletier, Francis Jeffry (2001)
Did Frege believe Frege’s principle?', in ''Journal of Logic, Language, and Information'' 10:87–114.
* Pelletier, Francis Jeffry (2016)
Semantic Compositionality' in
M. Aronoff (ed)
The Oxford Research Encyclopedia of Linguistics', Oxford UP.
Further reading
* Ferreira, F., Bailey, K. G., & Ferraro, V. (2002).
Good-enough representations in language comprehension' in ''Current directions in psychological science'', 11(1), 11-15.
* Ferreira, F., & Patson, N. D. (2007).
The ‘good enough’approach to language comprehension' in ''Language and Linguistics Compass'', 1(1‐2), 71-83.
* (2004) revisions i
20052007201220172020
* Werning, Markus; & Edouard Machery, & Gerhard Schurz (Eds., 2004)
The Compositionality of Meaning and Content', Vol. I & II, Ontos
* Werning, Markus; & Wolfram Hinzen, & Edouard Machery (Eds., 2012)
The Oxford Handbook of Compositionality', Oxford University Press
{{Formal semantics
Semantics
Principles
Philosophy of language
Formal semantics (natural language)