HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

Buddhist logico-epistemology is a term used in Western scholarship to describe
Buddhist Buddhism, also known as Buddhadharma and Dharmavinaya, is an Indian religion and List of philosophies, philosophical tradition based on Pre-sectarian Buddhism, teachings attributed to the Buddha, a wandering teacher who lived in the 6th or ...
systems of ' (
epistemic Epistemology is the branch of philosophy that examines the nature, origin, and limits of knowledge. Also called "the theory of knowledge", it explores different types of knowledge, such as propositional knowledge about facts, practical knowledg ...
tool, valid cognition) and ' (reasoning, logic). While the term may refer to various Buddhist systems and views on reasoning and epistemology, it is most often used to refer to the work of the "Epistemological school" (Sanskrit: ), i.e. the school of Dignaga and
Dharmakirti Dharmakīrti (fl. ;), was an influential Indian Buddhist philosopher who worked at Nālandā.Tom Tillemans (2011)Dharmakirti Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy He was one of the key scholars of epistemology ( pramāṇa) in Buddhist philo ...
which developed from the 5th through 7th centuries and remained the main system of Buddhist reasoning until the decline of Buddhism in India. The early Buddhist texts show that the historical Buddha was familiar with certain rules of reasoning used for debating purposes and made use of these against his opponents. He also seems to have held certain ideas about epistemology and reasoning, though he did not put forth a logico-epistemological system. The
Theravada ''Theravāda'' (; 'School of the Elders'; ) is Buddhism's oldest existing school. The school's adherents, termed ''Theravādins'' (anglicized from Pali ''theravādī''), have preserved their version of the Buddha's teaching or ''Dharma (Buddhi ...
'' Kathāvatthu'' contains some rules on debate and reasoning. The first Buddhist thinker to discuss logical and epistemic issues systematically was
Vasubandhu Vasubandhu (; Tibetan: དབྱིག་གཉེན་ ; floruit, fl. 4th to 5th century CE) was an influential Indian bhikkhu, Buddhist monk and scholar. He was a philosopher who wrote commentary on the Abhidharma, from the perspectives of th ...
in his ''Vāda-vidhi'' (''A Method for Argumentation''). A mature system of Buddhist logic and epistemology was founded by the Buddhist scholar
Dignāga Dignāga (also known as ''Diṅnāga'', ) was an Indian Buddhist philosopher and logician. He is credited as one of the Buddhism, Buddhist founders of Indian logic (''hetu vidyā'') and Buddhist atomism, atomism. Dignāga's work laid the grou ...
(–540 CE) in his ''magnum opus'', the '' Pramāṇa-samuccaya''.Alt URL
/ref>
Dharmakirti Dharmakīrti (fl. ;), was an influential Indian Buddhist philosopher who worked at Nālandā.Tom Tillemans (2011)Dharmakirti Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy He was one of the key scholars of epistemology ( pramāṇa) in Buddhist philo ...
further developed this system with several innovations in his ''
Pramanavarttika The ''Pramāṇavārttika'' (Brahmi: 𑀧𑁆𑀭𑀫𑀸𑀡𑀯𑀸𑀭𑁆𑀢𑁆𑀢𑀺𑀓, ''Commentary on Valid Cognition''; Tib. ''tshad ma rnam 'grel'') is an influential Buddhist text on pramana (valid instruments of knowledge, episte ...
'' ("Commentary on Valid Cognition"). His work was influential on all later Buddhist philosophical systems as well as on numerous Hindu thinkers. It also became the main source of epistemology and reasoning in
Tibetan Buddhism Tibetan Buddhism is a form of Buddhism practiced in Tibet, Bhutan and Mongolia. It also has a sizable number of adherents in the areas surrounding the Himalayas, including the Indian regions of Ladakh, Gorkhaland Territorial Administration, D ...
.


Definition

Scholars such as H.N. Randle and Fyodor Shcherbatskoy (1930s) initially employed terms such as “Indian Logic” and “Buddhist Logic” to refer to the Indian tradition of
inference Inferences are steps in logical reasoning, moving from premises to logical consequences; etymologically, the word '' infer'' means to "carry forward". Inference is theoretically traditionally divided into deduction and induction, a distinct ...
( anumāna),
epistemology Epistemology is the branch of philosophy that examines the nature, origin, and limits of knowledge. Also called "the theory of knowledge", it explores different types of knowledge, such as propositional knowledge about facts, practical knowle ...
(
pramana ''Pramana'' (; IAST: Pramāṇa) literally means " proof" and "means of knowledge".
), and "science of causes" (''hetu-vidyā''). This tradition developed in the orthodox
Hindu Hindus (; ; also known as Sanātanīs) are people who religiously adhere to Hinduism, also known by its endonym Sanātana Dharma. Jeffery D. Long (2007), A Vision for Hinduism, IB Tauris, , pp. 35–37 Historically, the term has also be ...
tradition known as
Nyaya Nyāya (Sanskrit: न्यायः, IAST: nyāyaḥ), literally meaning "justice", "rules", "method" or "judgment", is one of the six orthodox (Āstika) schools of Hindu philosophy. Nyāya's most significant contributions to Indian philosophy ...
as well as in
Buddhist philosophy Buddhist philosophy is the ancient Indian Indian philosophy, philosophical system that developed within the religio-philosophical tradition of Buddhism. It comprises all the Philosophy, philosophical investigations and Buddhist logico-episte ...
. Logic in classical India, writes
Bimal Krishna Matilal Bimal Krishna Matilal (1 June 1935 – 8 June 1991) was an eminent philosopher whose writings presented the Indian philosophical tradition as a comprehensive system of logic incorporating most issues addressed by themes in Western philosophy. ...
, is "the systematic study of informal inference-patterns, the rules of debate, the identification of sound inference vis-à-vis sophistical argument, and similar topics." As Matilal notes, this tradition developed out of systematic debate theory (''vadavidyā''):
Logic as the study of the form of correct arguments and inference patterns, developed in India from the methodology of philosophical debate. The art of conducting a philosophical debate was prevalent probably as early as the time of the
Buddha Siddhartha Gautama, most commonly referred to as the Buddha (),* * * was a wandering ascetic and religious teacher who lived in South Asia during the 6th or 5th century BCE and founded Buddhism. According to Buddhist legends, he was ...
and the
Mahavira Mahavira (Devanagari: महावीर, ), also known as Vardhamana (Devanagari: वर्धमान, ), was the 24th ''Tirthankara'' (Supreme Preacher and Ford Maker) of Jainism. Although the dates and most historical details of his lif ...
(Jina), but it became more systematic and methodical a few hundred years later.
"Indian Logic" is a different system than modern derivatives of
classical logic Classical logic (or standard logic) or Frege–Russell logic is the intensively studied and most widely used class of deductive logic. Classical logic has had much influence on analytic philosophy. Characteristics Each logical system in this c ...
(such as modern
predicate calculus Predicate or predication may refer to: * Predicate (grammar), in linguistics * Predication (philosophy) * several closely related uses in mathematics and formal logic: **Predicate (mathematical logic) ** Propositional function **Finitary relation, ...
): ''anumāna''-theory, a system in its own right. "Indian Logic" was also influenced by the study of grammar, whereas Classical Logic—which principally informed modern Western Logic—was influenced by the study of mathematics. A key difference between Western Logic and Indian Logic is that certain epistemological issues are included within Indian Logic, whereas in modern Western Logic they are deliberately excluded. Indian Logic includes general questions regarding the "nature of the derivation of knowledge,"
epistemology Epistemology is the branch of philosophy that examines the nature, origin, and limits of knowledge. Also called "the theory of knowledge", it explores different types of knowledge, such as propositional knowledge about facts, practical knowle ...
, from information supplied by evidence, evidence which in turn may be another item of knowledge. For this reason, other scholars use the term "logico-epistemology" to refer to this tradition, emphasizing the centrality of the epistemic project for Indian logical reasoning. * According to Georges Dreyfus, while Western logic tends to be focused on formal validity and deduction:
The concern of Indian "logicians" is quite different. They intend to provide a critical and systematic analysis of the diverse means of correct cognition that we use practically in our quest for knowledge. In this task, they discuss the nature and types of pramana. Although Indian philosophers disagree on the types of cognition that can be considered valid, most recognize perception and inference as valid. Within this context, which is mostly epistemological and practically oriented, topics such as the nature and types of correct reasoning that pertain to logic in the large sense of the word are discussed.


Pramana

(Tib. ) is often translated as "valid cognition" or "instrument of knowledge" and refers to epistemic ways of knowing.
Epistemological Epistemology is the branch of philosophy that examines the nature, origin, and limits of knowledge. Also called "the theory of knowledge", it explores different types of knowledge, such as propositional knowledge about facts, practical knowled ...
justification distinguishes
Buddhist Buddhism, also known as Buddhadharma and Dharmavinaya, is an Indian religion and List of philosophies, philosophical tradition based on Pre-sectarian Buddhism, teachings attributed to the Buddha, a wandering teacher who lived in the 6th or ...
pramana from orthodox Hindu philosophy. All schools of
Indian logic The development of Indian logic dates back to the Chandahsutra of Pingala and '' anviksiki'' of Medhatithi Gautama (c. 6th century BCE); the Sanskrit grammar rules of Pāṇini (c. 5th century BCE); the Vaisheshika school's analysis of atomism (c. ...
recognize various sets of "valid justifications for knowledge" or ''pramana''. Buddhist logico-epistemology was influenced by the
Nyāya Nyāya (Sanskrit: न्यायः, IAST: nyāyaḥ), literally meaning "justice", "rules", "method" or "judgment", is one of the six orthodox ( Āstika) schools of Hindu philosophy. Nyāya's most significant contributions to Indian philosoph ...
school's methodology, but where the Nyaya recognised a set of four pramanas—perception, inference, comparison, and testimony—the Buddhists (i.e. the school of Dignaga) only recognized two: perception and inference. For Dignaga, comparison and testimony are just special forms of inference. Most Indic ''pramanavada'' accept "
perception Perception () is the organization, identification, and interpretation of sensory information in order to represent and understand the presented information or environment. All perception involves signals that go through the nervous syste ...
" (Sanskrit: ) and "inference" (Sanskrit: ), but for some schools of orthodox Hinduism the "received textual tradition" (Sanskrit: ) is an epistemological category equal to perception and inference. The Buddhist logical tradition of Dignaga and Dharmakirti accept scriptural tradition ''only'' if it accords with and . This view is thus in line with the Buddha's injunction in the '' Kalama Sutta'' not to accept anything on mere tradition or scripture.


Early Buddhist background


Epistemology

The time of the Gautama Buddha was a lively intellectual culture with many differing philosophical theories. KN Jayatilleke, in his "Early Buddhist Theory of Knowledge", uses the Pali Nikayas to glean the possible epistemological views of the historical Buddha and those of his contemporaries. According to his analysis of the ''Saṅgārava-sutta'' ( AN 3.60), during the Buddha's time, Indian views were divided into three major camps with regards to knowledge:Jayatilleke, K. N. ''Early Buddhist Theory of Knowledge'', London, 1963 *The Traditionalists (''anussavika'') who regarded knowledge as being derived from scriptural sources (the Brahmins who upheld the Vedas). *The Rationalists (''takki vimamsi'') who only used reasoning or ''takka'' (the skeptics and materialists). *The "Experientialists" who held that besides reasoning, a kind of supra-normal yogic insight was able to bring about unique forms of knowledge (the Jains, the middle and late Upanishadic sages). The Buddha rejected the first view in several texts such as the '' Kalama sutta'', arguing that a claim to scriptural authority (''sadda'') was not a source of knowledge, as was claimed by the later Hindu Mimamsa school. The Buddha also seems to have criticized those who used reason (''takka''). According to Jayatilleke, in the Pali Nikayas, this term refers "primarily to denote the reasoning that was employed to construct and defend metaphysical theories and perhaps meant the reasoning of sophists and dialecticians only in a secondary sense". The Buddha rejected metaphysical speculations, and put aside certain questions which he named the unanswerables (''avyakatas''), including questions about the soul and if the universe is eternal or not. The Buddha's epistemological view has been a subject of debate among modern scholars. Some such as David Kalupahana, have seen him first and foremost as an empiricist because of his teaching that knowledge required verification through the six sense fields ( ayatanas). The '' Kalama sutta'' states that verification through one's own personal experience (and the experiences of the wise) is an important means of knowledge. However, the Buddha's view of truth was also based on the soteriological and therapeutic concern of ending suffering. In the ''"Discourse to Prince Abhaya"'' (MN.I.392–4) the Buddha states that a belief should only be accepted if it leads to wholesome consequences. This has led scholars such as Mrs Rhys Davids and Vallée-Poussin to see the Buddha's view as a form of
Pragmatism Pragmatism is a philosophical tradition that views language and thought as tools for prediction, problem solving, and action, rather than describing, representing, or mirroring reality. Pragmatists contend that most philosophical topics� ...
. This sense of truth as what is useful is also shown by the Buddha's parable of the arrow. K. N. Jayatilleke sees Buddha's epistemological view as a kind of
empiricism In philosophy, empiricism is an epistemological view which holds that true knowledge or justification comes only or primarily from sensory experience and empirical evidence. It is one of several competing views within epistemology, along ...
which also includes a particular view of causation (
dependent origination A dependant (US spelling: dependent) is a person who relies on another as a primary source of income and usually assistance with activities of daily living. A common-law spouse who is financially supported by their partner may also be included ...
): "inductive
inference Inferences are steps in logical reasoning, moving from premises to logical consequences; etymologically, the word '' infer'' means to "carry forward". Inference is theoretically traditionally divided into deduction and induction, a distinct ...
s in Buddhism are based on a theory of causation. These inferences are made on the data of
perception Perception () is the organization, identification, and interpretation of sensory information in order to represent and understand the presented information or environment. All perception involves signals that go through the nervous syste ...
. What is considered to constitute knowledge are direct inferences made on the basis of such perceptions." Jayatilleke argues the Buddhas statements in the Nikayas tacitly imply an adherence to some form of correspondence theory, this is most explicit in the ''Apannaka Sutta'' ( MN 60). He also notes that
Coherentism In philosophical epistemology, there are two types of coherentism: the coherence theory of truth, and the coherence theory of justification (also known as epistemic coherentism). Coherent truth is divided between an anthropological approach, w ...
is also taken as a criterion for truth in the Nikayas, which contains many instances of the Buddha debating opponents by showing how they have contradicted themselves. He also notes that the Buddha seems to have held that utility and truth go hand in hand, and therefore something which is true is also useful (and vice versa, something false is not useful for ending suffering). Echoing this view, Christian Coseru writes:
canonical sources make quite clear that several distinct factors play a crucial role in the acquisition of knowledge. These are variously identified with the testimony of sense experience, introspective or intuitive experience, inferences drawn from these two types of experience, and some form of coherentism, which demands that truth claims remain consistent across the entire corpus of doctrine. Thus, to the extent that Buddhists employ reason, they do so primarily in order further to advance the empirical investigation of phenomena.


Debate and analysis

The Early Buddhist Texts show that during this period many different kinds of philosophers often engaged in public debates (''vivada''). The early texts also mention that there was a set procedure (''patipada'') for these debates and that if someone does not abide by it they are unsuitable to be debated. There also seems to have been at least a basic conception of valid and invalid reasoning, including, according to Jayatilleke, fallacies (''hetvabhasah'') such as '' petitio principii''. Various fallacies were further covered under what were called ''nigrahasthana'' or "reasons for censure" by which one could lose the debate. Other ''nigrahasthanas'' included ''arthantaram'' or "shifting the topic", and not giving a coherent reply. According to Jayatilleke, ' pure reasoning' or '
a priori ('from the earlier') and ('from the later') are Latin phrases used in philosophy to distinguish types of knowledge, Justification (epistemology), justification, or argument by their reliance on experience. knowledge is independent from any ...
' reasoning is rejected by the Buddha as a source of knowledge. While reason could be useful in deliberation, it could not establish truth on its own. In contrast to his opponents, the Buddha termed himself a defender of 'analysis' or vibhajjavada'''. He held that after proper rational analysis, assertions could be classified in the following way: *Those assertions which can be asserted or denied categorically (''ekamsika'') *Those which cannot be asserted or denied categorically (''anekamsika''), which the Buddha further divided into: **Those which after analysis (''vibhajja-'') could be known to be true or false. **Those like the ''avyakata''-theses, which could not be thus known. This view of analysis differed from that of the Jains, which held that all views were ''anekamsika'' and also were relative, that is, they were true or false depending on the standpoint one viewed it from ('' anekantavada''). The early texts also mention that the Buddha held there to be "four kinds of explanations of questions." * a question which ought to be explained categorically * a question which ought to be answered with a counter question * a question which ought to be set aside (''thapaniya'') * a question which ought to be explained analytically The Buddha also made use of various terms which reveal some of his views on meaning and language. For example, he held that many concepts or designations (''paññatti'') could be used in conventional everyday speech while at the same time not referring to anything that exists ultimately (such as the pronouns like "I" and "Me"). Richard Hayes likewise points to the ''Potthapada sutta'' as an example of the Early Buddhist tendency towards a
nominalist In metaphysics, nominalism is the view that universals and abstract objects do not actually exist other than being merely names or labels. There are two main versions of nominalism. One denies the existence of universals—that which can be inst ...
perspective on language and meaning in contrast to the
Brahmanical The historical Vedic religion, also called Vedism or Brahmanism, and sometimes ancient Hinduism or Vedic Hinduism, constituted the religious ideas and practices prevalent amongst some of the Indo-Aryan peoples of the northwest Indian subcontin ...
view which tended to see language as reflecting real existents. The Buddha also divided statements (''bhasitam'') into two types with regards to their meaning: those which were intelligible, meaningful (''sappatihirakatam'') and those meaningless or incomprehensible (''appatihirakatam''). According to Jayatilleke, "in the Nikayas it is considered meaningless to make a statement unless the speaker could attach a verifiable content to each of its terms." This is why the Buddha held that statements about the existence of a self or soul ('' atman'') were ultimately meaningless, because they could not be verified. The Buddha, like his contemporaries, also made use of the "four corners" ('' catuṣkoṭi'') logical structure as a tool in argumentation. According to Jayatilleke, these "four forms of predication" can be rendered thus: #S is P, e.g. ''atthi paro loko'' (there is a next world). #S is not P, e.g. ''natthi paro loko'' (there is no next world). #S is and is not P, e.g. ''atthi ca natthi ca paro loko'' (there is and is no next world). #S neither is nor is not P, e.g. ''n'ev'atthi na natthi paro loko'' (there neither is nor is there no next world) The Buddha in the Nikayas seems to regard these as "'the four possible positions or logical alternatives that a proposition can take". Jayatilleke notes that the last two are clearly non- Aristotelian in nature. The Buddhists in the Nikayas use this logical structure to analyze the truth of statements and classify them. When all four were denied regarding a statement or question, it was held to be meaningless and thus set aside or rejected (but ''not negated'').


Two levels of Truth

The early texts mention two modes of discourse used by the Buddha. Jayatilleke writes:
when he is speaking about things or persons we should not presume that he is speaking about entities or substances; to this extent his meaning is to be inferred (''neyyattha-''). But when he is pointing out the misleading implications of speech or using language without these implications, his meaning is plain and direct and nothing is to be inferred (''nitattha-''). This is a valid distinction which certainly holds good for the Nikäyas at least, in the light of the above-statement.
The later commentarial and
Abhidharma The Abhidharma are a collection of Buddhist texts dating from the 3rd century BCE onwards, which contain detailed scholastic presentations of doctrinal material appearing in the canonical Buddhist scriptures and commentaries. It also refers t ...
literature began to use this distinction as an epistemic one. They spoke of two levels of truth, the conventional (''samutti)'', and the absolute (''paramattha''). This theory of double truth became very influential in later Buddhist epistemic discourse.


''Kathāvatthu''

The
Theravada ''Theravāda'' (; 'School of the Elders'; ) is Buddhism's oldest existing school. The school's adherents, termed ''Theravādins'' (anglicized from Pali ''theravādī''), have preserved their version of the Buddha's teaching or ''Dharma (Buddhi ...
'' Kathāvatthu'' (''Points of Controversy'') is a Pali Buddhist text which discusses the proper method for critical discussions on doctrine. Its date is debated by scholars but it might date to the time of
Ashoka Ashoka, also known as Asoka or Aśoka ( ; , ; – 232 BCE), and popularly known as Ashoka the Great, was List of Mauryan emperors, Emperor of Magadha from until #Death, his death in 232 BCE, and the third ruler from the Mauryan dynast ...
(C. 240 BC). Western scholarship by St. Schayer and following him A. K. Warder, have argued that there is an "anticipations of propositional logic" in the text. However, according to Jonardon Ganeri "the leading concern of the text is with issues of ''balance'' and ''fairness'' in the conduct of a dialogue and it recommends a strategy of argumentation which guarantees that both parties to a point of controversy have their arguments properly weighed and considered."Ganeri, Jonardon. Argumentation, dialogue and the "Kathāvatthu", Journal of Indian Philosophy August 2001, Volume 29, Issue 4, pp. 485–493 In the ''Kathāvatthu'', a proper reasoned dialogue (''vadayutti'') is structured as follows: there is a point of contention – whether A is B; this is divided into several 'openings' (''atthamukha''): #Is A B? #Is A not B? #Is A B everywhere? #Is A B always? #Is A B in everything? #Is A not B everywhere? #Is A not B always? #Is A not B in everything? These help clarify the attitude of someone towards their thesis in the proceeding argumentative process. Jonardon Ganeri outlines the process thus:
Each such ‘opening’ now proceeds as an independent dialogue, and each is divided into five stages: the way forward (anuloma), the way back (patikamma), the refutation (niggaha), the application (upanayana) and the conclusion (niggamana). In the way forward, the proponent solicits from the respondent the endorsement of a thesis and then tries to argue against it. On the way back, the respondent turns the tables, soliciting from the proponent the endorsement of the counter-thesis, and then trying argue against it. In the refutation, the respondent, continuing, seeks to refute the argument that the proponent had advanced against the thesis. The application and conclusion repeat and reaffirm that the proponent’s argument against the respondent’s thesis is unsound, while the respondent’s argument against the proponent’s counter-thesis is sound.


''Milindapanha''

Another Buddhist text which depicts the standards for rational debate among Buddhists is the '' Milindapanha'' (''"Questions of
Menander Menander (; ; c. 342/341 – c. 290 BC) was a Greek scriptwriter and the best-known representative of Athenian Ancient Greek comedy, New Comedy. He wrote 108 comedies and took the prize at the Lenaia festival eight times. His record at the Cit ...
"'', 1st century BCE) which is a dialogue between the Buddhist monk Nagasena and an Indo-Greek King. In describing the art of debate and dialogue, Nagasena states:
When scholars talk a matter over one with another, then is there a winding up, an unravelling, one or other is convicted of error, and he then acknowledges his mistake; distinctions are drawn, and contra-distinctions; and yet thereby they are not angered.
The various elements outlined here make up the standard procedure of Buddhist debate theory. There is an 'unravelling' or explication (''nibbethanam'') of one's thesis and stances and then there is also a 'winding up' ending in the censure (''niggaho'') of one side based on premises he has accepted and the rejoinders of his opponent.


Abhidharma views

The Buddhist Abhidharma schools developed a classification of four types of reasoning which became widely used in Buddhist thought. The
Mahayana Mahāyāna ( ; , , ; ) is a term for a broad group of Buddhist traditions, Buddhist texts#Mahāyāna texts, texts, Buddhist philosophy, philosophies, and practices developed in ancient India ( onwards). It is considered one of the three main ex ...
philosopher
Asanga Asaṅga (Sanskrit: असंग, , ; Romaji: ''Mujaku'') (fl. 4th century C.E.) was one of the most important spiritual figures of Mahayana Buddhism and the founder of the Yogachara school.Engle, Artemus (translator), Asanga, ''The Bodhisattva P ...
in his ''
Abhidharma-samuccaya The Abhidharma-samuccaya (Sanskrit; ; English: "Compendium of Abhidharma") is a Buddhist text composed by Asaṅga. The ''Abhidharma-samuccaya'' is a systematic account of Abhidharma. According to J. W. de Jong it is also "one of the most impor ...
'', outlines these four reasons (''yukti'') that one may use to inquire about the nature of things. According to Cristian Coseru these are: #The principle of dependence (apeksāyukti), which takes into account the fact that conditioned things necessarily arise in dependence upon conditions: it is a principle of reason, for instance, that sprouts depend on seeds. #The principle of causal efficacy (kāryakāranayukti), which accounts for the difference between things in terms of the different causal conditions for their apprehension: it is a principle of reason, thus, that, in dependence upon form, a faculty of vision, and visual awareness, one has visual rather than, say, auditory or tactile experiences. #The realization of evidence from experience (sāksātkriyāsādhanayukti). We realize the presence of water from moisture and of fire from smoke. #The principle of natural reasoning, or the principle of reality (dharmatāyukti), which concerns the phenomenal character of things as perceived (for instance, the wetness and fluidity of water). According to Coseru "what we have here are examples of natural reasoning or of reasoning from experience, rather than attempts to use deliberative modes of reasoning for the purpose of justifying a given thesis or arguing for its conditions of satisfaction."


Nyaya influences

The
Nyāya Sūtras The ''Nyāya Sūtras'' is an ancient Indian Sanskrit text composed by , and the foundational text of the Nyaya school of Hindu philosophy. The date when the text was composed, and the biography of its author is unknown, but variously estim ...
of Gotama (6th century BC – 2nd century CE) is the founding text of the Nyaya school. The text systematically lays out logical rules for argumentation in the form of a five-step schema and also sets forth a theory of epistemology. According to Jonardon Ganeri, the Nyaya sutra brought about a transformation in Indian thinking about logic. First, it began a shift away from interest in argumentation and debate towards the formal properties of sound
inference Inferences are steps in logical reasoning, moving from premises to logical consequences; etymologically, the word '' infer'' means to "carry forward". Inference is theoretically traditionally divided into deduction and induction, a distinct ...
. Secondly, the Nyaya sutra led a shift to rule-governed forms of logical thinking.


Nyāya and Buddhist Epistemology

The influence of
Nyāya Nyāya (Sanskrit: न्यायः, IAST: nyāyaḥ), literally meaning "justice", "rules", "method" or "judgment", is one of the six orthodox ( Āstika) schools of Hindu philosophy. Nyāya's most significant contributions to Indian philosoph ...
on Buddhist epistemology is profound, especially in the development of the four major pramāṇa (valid means of knowledge). Below is a breakdown of how Buddhist thinkers integrated and adapted Nyāya concepts in their philosophical systems:


Nyāya and Buddhist Logic

Another significant area of influence was in the domain of logic. Nyāya's formal system of
inference Inferences are steps in logical reasoning, moving from premises to logical consequences; etymologically, the word '' infer'' means to "carry forward". Inference is theoretically traditionally divided into deduction and induction, a distinct ...
(anumāna) directly impacted Buddhist logic, especially in the works of scholars like Dharmakīrti. Nyāya's focus on hetu (reasoning or cause) and the structure of valid arguments was adopted and modified by Buddhists in their development of logical proofs ( pramāṇa) to support doctrines like
impermanence Impermanence, also known as the philosophical problem of change, is a philosophical concept addressed in a variety of religions and philosophies. In Eastern philosophy it is notable for its role in the Buddhism, Buddhist three marks of existe ...
and non-self. In the Pramāṇavārttika, Dharmakīrti reinterpreted Nyāya’s logical tools to fit within Buddhist metaphysical views. For example, Nyāya’s approach to
inference Inferences are steps in logical reasoning, moving from premises to logical consequences; etymologically, the word '' infer'' means to "carry forward". Inference is theoretically traditionally divided into deduction and induction, a distinct ...
was used to argue against essentialist doctrines by showing that all phenomena are dependent on causes and conditions (dependent origination), rather than existing inherently ( svabhāva). In
Mādhyamika Madhyamaka ("middle way" or "centrism"; ; ; Tibetan: དབུ་མ་པ་ ; ''dbu ma pa''), otherwise known as Śūnyavāda ("the emptiness doctrine") and Niḥsvabhāvavāda ("the no ''svabhāva'' doctrine"), refers to a tradition of Bu ...
philosophy,
Nāgārjuna Nāgārjuna (Sanskrit: नागार्जुन, ''Nāgārjuna''; ) was an Indian monk and Mahāyāna Buddhist philosopher of the Madhyamaka (Centrism, Middle Way) school. He is widely considered one of the most important Buddhist philosoph ...
and Śāntideva also employed logic and dialectical reasoning, heavily influenced by Nyāya, to argue against Nyāya’s own concept of an unchanging self.


Nyāya and Buddhist Debate Practices

The formal practice of debate (''yukti'') in Buddhist scholasticism, especially within monastic institutions, reflects the influence of Nyāya. The rigorous techniques of formal reasoning and logical debate in Nyāya were adopted by Buddhists to engage in systematic argumentation, not only with other philosophical schools but also within their own traditions. Buddhist monastic institutions, particularly in India, followed a debate structure built on
Nyāya Nyāya (Sanskrit: न्यायः, IAST: nyāyaḥ), literally meaning "justice", "rules", "method" or "judgment", is one of the six orthodox ( Āstika) schools of Hindu philosophy. Nyāya's most significant contributions to Indian philosoph ...
’s epistemological principles, emphasizing the importance of valid reasoning and evidence in defending doctrinal views. These debates often centered around the ''validity of pramāṇas'' and the nature of reality (
impermanence Impermanence, also known as the philosophical problem of change, is a philosophical concept addressed in a variety of religions and philosophies. In Eastern philosophy it is notable for its role in the Buddhism, Buddhist three marks of existe ...
and non-self versus permanence and self). In Tibet and East Asia, these debates became central to the scholastic tradition and helped refine Buddhist thought over centuries.


Nyāya Influence in Later Buddhist Traditions

The impact of Nyāya was not confined to early Indian Buddhist thinkers but continued to shape later Buddhist traditions. For example,
Tibetan Buddhism Tibetan Buddhism is a form of Buddhism practiced in Tibet, Bhutan and Mongolia. It also has a sizable number of adherents in the areas surrounding the Himalayas, including the Indian regions of Ladakh, Gorkhaland Territorial Administration, D ...
developed sophisticated methods of debate and logic that were heavily influenced by Indian Nyāya. In the
Gelug file:DalaiLama0054 tiny.jpg, 240px, 14th Dalai Lama, The 14th Dalai Lama (center), the most influential figure of the contemporary Gelug tradition, at the 2003 Kalachakra ceremony, Bodh Gaya, Bodhgaya (India) The Gelug (, also Geluk; 'virtuous' ...
school, the ''Pramāṇa'' texts of Dharmakīrti became a central part of the curriculum, alongside Nyāya texts. In addition,
Zen Buddhism Zen (; from Chinese: '' Chán''; in Korean: ''Sŏn'', and Vietnamese: ''Thiền'') is a Mahayana Buddhist tradition that developed in China during the Tang dynasty by blending Indian Mahayana Buddhism, particularly Yogacara and Madhyamaka ph ...
and
Chan Buddhism Chan (; of ), from Sanskrit '' dhyāna'' (meaning " meditation" or "meditative state"), is a Chinese school of Mahāyāna Buddhism. It developed in China from the 6th century CE onwards, becoming especially popular during the Tang and Song ...
also exhibited traces of logical techniques influenced by the early scholastics of India, where rational discourse was used to sharpen the practitioner's understanding of
emptiness Emptiness as a human condition is a sense of generalized boredom, social alienation, nihilism, and apathy. Feelings of emptiness often accompany dysthymia, depression (mood), depression, loneliness, anhedonia, wiktionary:despair, despair, or o ...
(''śūnyatā'') and
impermanence Impermanence, also known as the philosophical problem of change, is a philosophical concept addressed in a variety of religions and philosophies. In Eastern philosophy it is notable for its role in the Buddhism, Buddhist three marks of existe ...
.


Further Developments and Synthesis

In addition to Dharmakīrti and
Nāgārjuna Nāgārjuna (Sanskrit: नागार्जुन, ''Nāgārjuna''; ) was an Indian monk and Mahāyāna Buddhist philosopher of the Madhyamaka (Centrism, Middle Way) school. He is widely considered one of the most important Buddhist philosoph ...
, Buddhist thinkers like
Vasubandhu Vasubandhu (; Tibetan: དབྱིག་གཉེན་ ; floruit, fl. 4th to 5th century CE) was an influential Indian bhikkhu, Buddhist monk and scholar. He was a philosopher who wrote commentary on the Abhidharma, from the perspectives of th ...
and Śāntideva also utilized Nyāya-derived logic in their writings.
Vasubandhu Vasubandhu (; Tibetan: དབྱིག་གཉེན་ ; floruit, fl. 4th to 5th century CE) was an influential Indian bhikkhu, Buddhist monk and scholar. He was a philosopher who wrote commentary on the Abhidharma, from the perspectives of th ...
's work in the
Abhidharma The Abhidharma are a collection of Buddhist texts dating from the 3rd century BCE onwards, which contain detailed scholastic presentations of doctrinal material appearing in the canonical Buddhist scriptures and commentaries. It also refers t ...
tradition integrated Nyāya’s
inference Inferences are steps in logical reasoning, moving from premises to logical consequences; etymologically, the word '' infer'' means to "carry forward". Inference is theoretically traditionally divided into deduction and induction, a distinct ...
and
perception Perception () is the organization, identification, and interpretation of sensory information in order to represent and understand the presented information or environment. All perception involves signals that go through the nervous syste ...
frameworks to argue for
emptiness Emptiness as a human condition is a sense of generalized boredom, social alienation, nihilism, and apathy. Feelings of emptiness often accompany dysthymia, depression (mood), depression, loneliness, anhedonia, wiktionary:despair, despair, or o ...
and the illusion of permanence in all things. Moreover,
Tibetan Buddhist Tibetan Buddhism is a form of Buddhism practiced in Tibet, Bhutan and Mongolia. It also has a sizable number of adherents in the areas surrounding the Himalayas, including the Indian regions of Ladakh, Darjeeling, Sikkim, and Arunachal Prades ...
scholars like Chandrakirti and Jamyang Zhépa further developed these ideas, showing that the dialogue between Nyāya and Buddhism was not a one-way flow but rather an ongoing intellectual exchange that continued across centuries and geographical regions. B.K. Matilal outlines the five steps or limbs of the Nyaya method of reasoning as follows: #There is fire on the hill. hesis#For there is smoke.
eason Eason is a surname of English and Scottish origin. In the case of English, it may be a variant of Eastham (disambiguation), Eastham or Easton (surname), Easton; in the case of Scottish, it is a variant of Esson (disambiguation), Esson. A variant of ...
#(Wherever there is smoke, there is fire), as in the kitchen. xample#This is such a case (smoke on the hill). #Therefore, it is so, i.e., there is fire on the hill. Later Buddhist thinkers like Vasubandhu would see several of these steps as redundant and would affirm that only the first two or three were necessary. The Naiyayikas (the Nyaya scholars) also accepted four valid means (''pramaṇa'') of obtaining valid knowledge (''pramana'') - perception (''pratyakṣa''), inference (''anumāna''), comparison ('' upamāna'') and word/testimony of reliable sources (''śabda''). The systematic discussions of the Nyaya school influenced the Medieval Buddhist philosophers who developed their own theories of inferential reasoning and epistemic warrant (pramana). The Nyaya became one of the main opponents of the Buddhists.


Vaiśeṣika Influences

While the direct influence of the
Vaiśeṣika Vaisheshika (IAST: Vaiśeṣika; ; ) is one of the six schools of Hindu philosophy from ancient India. In its early stages, Vaiśeṣika was an independent philosophy with its own metaphysics, epistemology, logic, ethics, and soteriology. Over t ...
school on
Buddhism Buddhism, also known as Buddhadharma and Dharmavinaya, is an Indian religion and List of philosophies, philosophical tradition based on Pre-sectarian Buddhism, teachings attributed to the Buddha, a wandering teacher who lived in the 6th or ...
was limited compared to that of the
Nyāya Nyāya (Sanskrit: न्यायः, IAST: nyāyaḥ), literally meaning "justice", "rules", "method" or "judgment", is one of the six orthodox ( Āstika) schools of Hindu philosophy. Nyāya's most significant contributions to Indian philosoph ...
school, certain concepts from Vaiśeṣika philosophy did inform or prompt responses within Buddhist thought, particularly in the context of
Atomism Atomism () is a natural philosophy proposing that the physical universe is composed of fundamental indivisible components known as atoms. References to the concept of atomism and its Atom, atoms appeared in both Ancient Greek philosophy, ancien ...
, metaphysics, and conceptual classification. The influence was often indirect, occurring through shared intellectual debates and through the later fusion of Nyāya and Vaiśeṣika into a combined tradition.


Historical Context

The Vaiśeṣika school, traditionally attributed to the sage
Kaṇāda Kaṇāda (, ), also known as Ulūka, Kashyapa, Kaṇabhaksha, Kaṇabhuj was an ancient Indian natural scientist and philosopher who founded the Vaisheshika school of Indian philosophy that also represents the earliest Indian physics. Es ...
, emerged around the 2nd century BCE and developed a detailed realist metaphysical system centered on the analysis of substances, qualities, motion, and universals.Potter, Karl H. (ed.), ''Encyclopedia of Indian Philosophies, Vol. II: Indian Metaphysics and Epistemology: The Tradition of Nyāya-Vaiśeṣika up to Gaṅgeśa'', Princeton University Press, 1977, pp. 18–22. While Buddhist traditions primarily emphasized ethical practice, meditation, and liberation from suffering, by the time of the
Abhidharma The Abhidharma are a collection of Buddhist texts dating from the 3rd century BCE onwards, which contain detailed scholastic presentations of doctrinal material appearing in the canonical Buddhist scriptures and commentaries. It also refers t ...
scholastic period, Buddhist scholars began to systematize their own metaphysical and epistemological positions, sometimes in response to or dialogue with non-Buddhist systems like Vaiśeṣika.Dhammajoti, K.L., ''Sarvāstivāda Abhidharma'', Centre of Buddhist Studies, University of Hong Kong, 2007, pp. 127–131.


Atomism and Ontological Categories

Vaiśeṣika philosophy is considered one of the earliest proponents of atomism in Indian thought.Chakrabarti, Arindam, ''The Nyāya-Vaiśeṣika Theory of Universals: A Linguistic Analysis'', Springer, 1992, pp. 45–49. According to this view, all material objects are composed of indivisible, eternal atoms (''paramāṇu'') of four elements:
earth Earth is the third planet from the Sun and the only astronomical object known to Planetary habitability, harbor life. This is enabled by Earth being an ocean world, the only one in the Solar System sustaining liquid surface water. Almost all ...
,
water Water is an inorganic compound with the chemical formula . It is a transparent, tasteless, odorless, and Color of water, nearly colorless chemical substance. It is the main constituent of Earth's hydrosphere and the fluids of all known liv ...
,
fire Fire is the rapid oxidation of a fuel in the exothermic chemical process of combustion, releasing heat, light, and various reaction Product (chemistry), products. Flames, the most visible portion of the fire, are produced in the combustion re ...
, and
air An atmosphere () is a layer of gases that envelop an astronomical object, held in place by the gravity of the object. A planet retains an atmosphere when the gravity is great and the temperature of the atmosphere is low. A stellar atmosph ...
. These atoms combine through conjunction (''saṃyoga'') and inherence (''Samavāya'') to form complex, perceivable objects. Buddhist schools, particularly the Sarvāstivāda and later Theravāda Abhidhamma and
Yogācāra Yogachara (, IAST: ') is an influential tradition of Buddhist philosophy and psychology emphasizing the study of cognition, perception, and consciousness through the interior lens of meditation, as well as philosophical reasoning (hetuvidyā). ...
traditions, developed their own theories of atomism and constituent elements ('' dharmas''). These Buddhist atoms, however, were fundamentally momentary and non-substantial, existing only in a single instant before giving rise to a successor. While structurally similar in positing basic building blocks of reality, Buddhist atomism served a different function: not to establish a permanent material substratum, but to support doctrines of impermanence (''
anitya Impermanence, also known as the philosophical problem of change, is a philosophical concept addressed in a variety of religions and philosophies. In Eastern philosophy it is notable for its role in the Buddhist three marks of existence. It ...
'') and
dependent origination A dependant (US spelling: dependent) is a person who relies on another as a primary source of income and usually assistance with activities of daily living. A common-law spouse who is financially supported by their partner may also be included ...
. Some scholars suggest that the development of Buddhist atomism may have been in part a philosophical response to the atomistic realism of Vaiśeṣika, offering a counter-theory that maintained empirical rigor without conceding to metaphysical permanence.


Epistemology and Debate Culture

Vaiśeṣika epistemology, though not as developed as Nyāya’s, accepted
perception Perception () is the organization, identification, and interpretation of sensory information in order to represent and understand the presented information or environment. All perception involves signals that go through the nervous syste ...
(''Pratyakṣa'') and
inference Inferences are steps in logical reasoning, moving from premises to logical consequences; etymologically, the word '' infer'' means to "carry forward". Inference is theoretically traditionally divided into deduction and induction, a distinct ...
('' anumāna'') as valid means of knowledge ('' Pramāṇa''). Over time, Vaiśeṣika and Nyāya merged into a unified system, often referred to as the ''Nyāya-Vaiśeṣika'' school, particularly from the post- Uddyotakara period (c. 5th century CE onward). This synthesis brought Vaiśeṣika metaphysics into the sphere of logical and epistemological debate. Buddhist logicians, especially
Dignāga Dignāga (also known as ''Diṅnāga'', ) was an Indian Buddhist philosopher and logician. He is credited as one of the Buddhism, Buddhist founders of Indian logic (''hetu vidyā'') and Buddhist atomism, atomism. Dignāga's work laid the grou ...
and Dharmakīrti, engaged deeply with Nyāya-Vaiśeṣika thinkers, critiquing their views on perception, inference, and universals. While these critiques were often aimed at Nyāya formulations, many of the underlying metaphysical positions—such as the reality of substances or inherence—were drawn from Vaiśeṣika doctrines. This interaction spurred Buddhist thinkers to clarify and refine their own positions on cognition, objecthood, and conceptual construction (''vikalpa''). For example, Dharmakīrti’s theory of Apoha (exclusion) as the basis of conceptual cognition can be read as a direct challenge to both Vaiśeṣika's realist universals ('' Sāmānya'') and their role in perception.


Shared Frameworks and Divergences

There are also conceptual parallels that may reflect shared cultural and intellectual frameworks rather than direct influence. For instance, both Vaiśeṣika and Buddhist Abhidharma employ classificatory taxonomies to understand reality. Vaiśeṣika lists six or seven categories of being (''
Padārtha is a Sanskrit word for "categories" in Vaisheshika and Nyaya schools of Indian philosophy. Abhidharma texts similarly analyze reality into lists of mental and physical phenomena (''dharmas''), though from a phenomenological rather than ontological standpoint. However, the purpose and metaphysical commitments of these taxonomies diverge significantly. Vaiśeṣika aims at a stable ontology of the external world, whereas Buddhist taxonomy serves soteriological aims by analyzing experience into impermanent, non-self constituents.


Conclusion

While Vaiśeṣika did not exert a dominant or sustained influence on Buddhist philosophy, its presence in the broader philosophical landscape of classical India prompted Buddhist responses—especially in areas of atomism, realism, and classification. These responses were often critical and reformulative, leading to uniquely Buddhist formulations of key metaphysical and epistemological concepts. Through its integration with Nyāya, Vaiśeṣika indirectly contributed to shaping Buddhist logic and theory of knowledge during the scholastic and classical periods of Indian philosophy.


Mahayana Buddhist philosophy


Nagarjuna's Madhyamaka

Nagarjuna Nāgārjuna (Sanskrit: नागार्जुन, ''Nāgārjuna''; ) was an Indian monk and Mahayana, Mahāyāna Buddhist Philosophy, philosopher of the Madhyamaka (Centrism, Middle Way) school. He is widely considered one of the most importa ...
(c. 150 – c. 250 CE), one of the most influential Buddhist thinkers, defended the theory of the emptiness ('' shunyata'') of
phenomena A phenomenon ( phenomena), sometimes spelled phaenomenon, is an observable Event (philosophy), event. The term came into its modern Philosophy, philosophical usage through Immanuel Kant, who contrasted it with the noumenon, which ''cannot'' be ...
and attacked theories that posited an essence or true existence ('' svabhava'') to phenomena in his magnum opus ''The Fundamental Verses on the Middle Way''. He used the Buddhist catuṣkoṭi ("four corners" or "four positions") to construct
reductio ad absurdum In logic, (Latin for "reduction to absurdity"), also known as (Latin for "argument to absurdity") or ''apagogical argument'', is the form of argument that attempts to establish a claim by showing that the opposite scenario would lead to absur ...
arguments against numerous theories which posited essences to certain phenomena, such as causality and movement. In Nagarjuna's works and those of his followers, the four positions on a particular thesis are negated or ruled out () as exemplified by the first verse of Nagarjuna's Middle way verses which focuses on a critique of causation:
Entities of any kind are not ever found anywhere produced from themselves, from another, from both hemselves and another and also from no cause.
Nagarjuna also famously relied upon refutation based argumentation (''vitanda'') drawing out the consequences (''prasaṅga'') and presuppositions of his opponents' own theories and showing them to be self refuting. Because the ''vaitandika'' only seeks to disprove his opponents arguments without putting forward a thesis of his own, the Hindu Nyaya school philosophers such as Vatsyayana saw it as unfair and also irrational (because if you argue against P, you must have a thesis, mainly not-P). According to Matilal, Nagarjuna's position of not putting forth any implied thesis through his refutations would be rational if seen as a form of
illocutionary act The concept of illocutionary acts was introduced into linguistics by the philosopher J. L. Austin in his investigation of the various aspects of speech acts. In his framework, ''locution'' is what was said and meant, ''illocution'' is what was do ...
. Nagarjuna's reductions and the structure of the catuṣkoṭi became very influential in the Buddhist
Madhyamaka Madhyamaka ("middle way" or "centrism"; ; ; Tibetic languages, Tibetan: དབུ་མ་པ་ ; ''dbu ma pa''), otherwise known as Śūnyavāda ("the Śūnyatā, emptiness doctrine") and Niḥsvabhāvavāda ("the no Svabhava, ''svabhāva'' d ...
school of philosophy which sees itself as a continuation of Nagarjuna's thought. Nagarjuna also discusses the four modes of knowing of the Nyaya school, but he is unwilling to accept that such epistemic means bring us ultimate knowledge. Nagarjuna's epistemic stance continues to be debated among modern scholars, his skepticism of the ability of reason and language to capture the nature of reality and his view of reality as being empty of true existence have led some to see him as a skeptic, mystic, nihilist or agnostic, while others interpret him as a Wittgensteinian analyst, an anti-realist, or deconstructionist. Nagarjuna is also said to be the author of the ''Upāyaśṛdaya'' one of the first Buddhist texts on proper reasoning and argumentation. He also developed the Buddhist theory of two truths, defending ultimate truth as the truth of emptiness.


Vasubandhu

Vasubandhu Vasubandhu (; Tibetan: དབྱིག་གཉེན་ ; floruit, fl. 4th to 5th century CE) was an influential Indian bhikkhu, Buddhist monk and scholar. He was a philosopher who wrote commentary on the Abhidharma, from the perspectives of th ...
was one of the first Buddhist thinkers to write various works on sound reasoning and debate, including the ''Vādavidhi'' (Methods of Debate), and the ''Vādavidhāna'' (Rules of Debate). Vasubandhu was influenced by the system of the Nyaya school. Vasubandhu introduced the concept of 'logical pervasion' ('' vyapti''). He also introduced the trairūpya (triple inferential sign). The trairūpya is a logical argument that contains three constituents which a logical ‘sign’ or ‘mark’ (''linga'') must fulfill to be 'valid source of knowledge' (
pramana ''Pramana'' (; IAST: Pramāṇa) literally means " proof" and "means of knowledge".
): #It should be present in the case or object under consideration, the ‘subject-locus' (''pakṣa'') #It should be present in a ‘similar case’ or a homologue (''sapakṣa'') #It should not be present in any ‘dissimilar case’ or heterologue (''vipakṣa'')


Pramāṇavāda


Dignāga

Dignāga Dignāga (also known as ''Diṅnāga'', ) was an Indian Buddhist philosopher and logician. He is credited as one of the Buddhism, Buddhist founders of Indian logic (''hetu vidyā'') and Buddhist atomism, atomism. Dignāga's work laid the grou ...
(c. 480 – 540 CE) is the founder of an eponymous tradition of Buddhist logic and epistemology which was widely influential in Indian philosophy due to the introduction of unique epistemological questions. According to B.K. Matilal, Dignāga "was perhaps the most creative logician in medieval (400-1100) India." Dignāga's tradition of Buddhist logic is sometimes called the "School of Dignāga" or "The School of Dinnāga and Dharmakīrti". In Tibetan, it is often called “those who follow reasoning” (Tibetan: ''rigs pa rjes su ‘brang ba''); in modern literature, it is sometimes known by the
Sanskrit Sanskrit (; stem form ; nominal singular , ,) is a classical language belonging to the Indo-Aryan languages, Indo-Aryan branch of the Indo-European languages. It arose in northwest South Asia after its predecessor languages had Trans-cultural ...
"pramāṇavāda", often translated as "the epistemological school" or "the logico-epistemological school." Dignāga defended the validity of only two pramāṇas (instruments of knowledge), perception and inference, in his magnum opus, the '' Pramāṇa-samuccaya.'' His theory does not "make a radical distinction between epistemology and the psychological processes of cognition." As noted by Cristian Coseru, Dignāga's theory of knowledge is strongly grounded in perception "as an epistemic modality for establishing a cognitive event as knowledge". Since perception is information that is acquired through the senses, it is not susceptible to error. However, there is susceptibility to error in processes of interpretation, including mental construction and inferential thinking. Dignāga also wrote on language and meaning. His " apoha" (exclusion) theory of meaning was widely influential. For Dignāga, a word can express its own meaning only by repudiating other meanings. The word 'cow' gives its own meaning only by the exclusion of all those things which are other than cow.


Dharmakīrti

Following Dignāga, Dharmakīrti (c. 7th century), contributed significantly to the development and application of Buddhist pramana theory. Dharmakīrti's '' Pramāṇavārttika'', remains in
Tibet Tibet (; ''Böd''; ), or Greater Tibet, is a region in the western part of East Asia, covering much of the Tibetan Plateau and spanning about . It is the homeland of the Tibetan people. Also resident on the plateau are other ethnic groups s ...
as a central text on pramana and was widely commented on by various Indian and Tibetan scholars. Dharmakīrti's theory of epistemology differed from Dignāga's by introducing the idea that for something to be a valid cognition it must "confirm causal efficacy" (''arthakriyāsthiti'') which "consists in his cognition’scompliance with he object’s capacity toperform a function" (''Pramāṇavārttika'' 2.1ac). He was also one of the primary theorists of Buddhist atomism, according to which the only items considered to exist or be ultimately real are momentary particulars (''svalakṣaṇa'') including material atoms and momentary states of consciousness (dharmas). Everything else is considered to be only conventional (''saṃvṛtisat'') and thus he has been seen as a nominalist, like Dignāga. Vincent Eltschinger has argued that Buddhist epistemology, especially Dharmakīrti's, was an apologetic response to attacks by hostile Hindu opponents and thus was seen by Buddhists as "that which, by defeating the outsiders, removes the obstacles to the path towards liberation." Coseru meanwhile simply notes the inseparability of epistemic concerns from spiritual praxis for Buddhist epistemologists such as Dharmakīrti:
It is this praxis that leads a representative thinker such as Dharmakīrti to claim that the Buddha, whose view he and his successors claim to propound, is a true embodiment of the sources of knowledge. Thus, far from seeing a tension between empirical scrutiny and the exercise of reason, the Buddhist epistemological enterprise positions itself not merely as a dialogical disputational method for avoiding unwarranted beliefs, but as a practice aimed at achieving concrete, pragmatic ends. As Dharmakīrti reminds his fellow Buddhists, the successful accomplishment of any human goal is wholly dependent on having correct knowledge.


Later figures of the tradition

The Buddhist philosophers who are part of this pramāṇavāda tradition include numerous other figures who followed Dignāga and Dharmakīrti. They developed their theories further, commented on their works and defended their theories against Hindu and Buddhist opponents. Fyodor Stcherbatsky divided the followers and commentators on Dharmakirti into three main groups: * The philological school of commentators, these figures (such as Devendrabuddhi and Śākyabuddhi) focused on "exactly rendering the direct meaning of the commented text without losing oneself in its deeper implications". They all commented on the ''Pramāṇavārttika.'' * The Kashmiri school of philosophy, which sought to "disclose the deep philosophic contents of the system of Dignāga and Dharmakīrti, regarding it as a critical system of logic and epistemology." Its founding figure was Dharmottara (8th century), a philosopher from Kashmir who wrote some independent works and also a commentary on Dharmakīrti's ''Nyāyabindu'' and on his ''Pramanaviniscaya.'' * The religious school of commentators, who sought to "disclose the profound meaning of Dharmakirti's works and to reveal their concealed ultimate tendency." Unlike the Kashmiri school, which saw Dharmakīrti's work as primarily focused on epistemology and reasoning, the "religious" school used Dharmakīrti in order to develop and comment on the entirety of the metaphysics of Mahayana Buddhism. The founder of this school was the layman Prajñakaragupta (740–800 C.E.), an important and original thinker who introduced various new perspectives into the Pramāṇavāda tradition, such as backwards causation. He is the author of the large commentary, the ''Pramāṇavārttikālaṅkāra'' ("Ornament of the ''Pramāṇavārttikā"''). Some of the other figures of the epistemological school include: * Īśvarasena, a disciple of Dignāga, and teacher of Dharmakīrti * Śaṅkarasvāmin, wrote an introduction to Dignāga's logic * Jinendrabuddhi (7th or 8th century), a commentator on Dignāga's ''Pramanasamuccaya'' *Bāhuleya, a commentator on Dignāga's ''Nyāyamukha'' *Śubhakara (650–750), was particularly noteworthy because he composed a work which aimed at proving the objective reality of external things and thus attempted to disprove ''Vijñānavāda'' (the doctrine of consciousness, idealism) * Śākyabuddhi (ca. 700 C.E.), wrote a commentary on Dharmakīrti's ''Pramāṇavārttika'' *Chandragomin, purported author of the *''Nyāyasiddhyāloka'' *Anandavardhana, wrote a sub commentary to Dharmottara's ''Pramana-viniscaya commentary.'' * Vinītadeva (8th century), wrote a commentary on Dharmakīrti's ''Nyāyabindu'' * Śāntabhadra, wrote a commentary on Dharmakīrti's ''Nyāyabindu'' *Jinamitra, wrote a commentary on Dharmakīrti's ''Nyāyabindu'' * Devendrabuddhi (7th century), wrote various commentaries, including one on Dharmakīrti's ''Pramāṇavārttika'' * Karṇakagomin, wrote a commentary on Dharmakīrti's ''Pramāṇavārttika'' * Manorathanandin, wrote a commentary on Dharmakīrti's ''Pramāṇavārttika'' *Śakyamati, wrote a commentary on Dharmakīrti's ''Pramāṇavārttika'' *Arcaṭa, wrote a commentary on Dharmakīrti's ''Hetubindu'' *Jina, a follower of Prajñakaragupta *Ravigupta, a follower of Prajñakaragupta *Yamari, a follower of Prajñakaragupta * Śubhagupta (720–780), was a
Vaibhāṣika Sarvāstivāda-Vaibhāṣika () or simply Vaibhāṣika () is an ancient Buddhist tradition of Abhidharma (scholastic Buddhist philosophy), which was very influential in north India, especially Kashmir.Westerhoff 2018, pp. 60–61. In various tex ...
writer on pramana who wrote a proof of the external world *
Śaṅkaranandana Śaṅkaranandana (fl. c. 9th or 10th century), (Tibetan: ''Bde byed dga’ ba)'' was a Mahayana Buddhist philosopher, and a brahmin lay devotee (upāsaka) active in Kashmir in the Buddhist logico-epistemology, epistemological (''pramana'') traditi ...
(10th century), a prolific author of at least 17 texts, known as "the second Dharmakīrti." * Jñanasrimitra (975–1025), a "gate-scholar" at Vikramashila who wrote several original works *Paṇḍita Aśoka (980–1040) *Jñanasribhadra (1000–1100), wrote a commentary on the ''Pramāṇaviniścaya'' (Dharmakīrti) *Jayanta (1020–1080), author of the ''Pramāṇavārttikālaṅkāraṭīkā,'' a commentary on Prajñakaragupta's text. * Jitāri or Jetāri (940–1000), teacher of Atisha and author of numerous pramana texts. *Durvekamiśra (970–1030), a disciple of Jitāri * Ratnakīrti (11th century), a student of Jñanasrimitra * Mokṣākaragupta (11th–12th centuries), author of the ''Tarkabhāṣā'' *Vidyākaraśānti (1100–1200), author of the ''Tarkasopāna'' * Śākyaśrībhadra, a Kashmiri pandita who was the teacher of the Tibetan Sakya Pandita


Influence and reception

Dignāga also influenced non-Buddhist Sanskrit thinkers. According to Lawrence J. McCrea, and Parimal G. Patil, Dignāga set in motion an "epistemic turn" in Indian philosophy: The Hindu philosophers, especially those of the Nyāya, Vaiseshika and
Vedanta ''Vedanta'' (; , ), also known as ''Uttara Mīmāṃsā'', is one of the six orthodox (Āstika and nāstika, ''āstika'') traditions of Hindu philosophy and textual exegesis. The word ''Vedanta'' means 'conclusion of the Vedas', and encompa ...
schools, were in constant debate with the Buddhist epistemologists, developing arguments to defend their realist position against the
nominalism In metaphysics, nominalism is the view that universals and abstract objects do not actually exist other than being merely names or labels. There are two main versions of nominalism. One denies the existence of universals—that which can be inst ...
of the Buddhists. Nyāya-Vaiseshika thinkers such as Uddyotakara and Prashastapada critiqued the views of Dignaga as they developed their own philosophy. Vācaspati Miśra's ''Nyāya-vārtika-tātparya-tikā'' is almost entirely focused on outlining and defeating the arguments of the Buddhist epistemologists.
Prabhākara Prabhakara ( IAST: ''Prabhākara'') active c. 6th century was an Indian philosopher-grammarian in the Mīmāṃsā tradition of Kerala. Probable date Hariswamin's commentary on Shatapatha Brahmana which dates to 638 CE discusses the doctri ...
(active c. 6th century) meanwhile, may have been influenced by Buddhist reasoning to move away from some of the realistic views of older
Mīmāṃsā ''Mīmāṁsā'' (Sanskrit: मीमांसा; IAST: Mīmāṃsā) is a Sanskrit word that means "reflection" or "critical investigation" and thus refers to a tradition of contemplation which reflected on the meanings of certain Vedic tex ...
thought. The Vedanta scholar Śrīharṣa who attacked the realism of Nyāya may have been influenced by the Buddhists as well. Even the "New Reason" ('' Navya Nyāya'') scholar Gaṅgeśa Upādhyāya shows an influence from the Buddhist epistemological school, in his arrangement of his ''Tattvacintāmaṇi.''


Svātantrika Mādhyamika


Bhāvaviveka

Bhāvaviveka (c. 500 – c. 578) appears to be the first Buddhist logician to employ the "formal
syllogism A syllogism (, ''syllogismos'', 'conclusion, inference') is a kind of logical argument that applies deductive reasoning to arrive at a conclusion based on two propositions that are asserted or assumed to be true. In its earliest form (defin ...
" (Wylie: ''sbyor ba'i tshig''; Sanskrit: ''prayoga-vākya'') in expounding the Mādhyamaka view, which he employed to considerable effect in his commentary to
Nagarjuna Nāgārjuna (Sanskrit: नागार्जुन, ''Nāgārjuna''; ) was an Indian monk and Mahayana, Mahāyāna Buddhist Philosophy, philosopher of the Madhyamaka (Centrism, Middle Way) school. He is widely considered one of the most importa ...
's ''
Mūlamadhyamakakārikā The ''Mūlamadhyamakakārikā'' (), abbreviated as ''MMK'', is the foundational text of the Madhyamaka school of Mahāyāna Buddhist philosophy. It was composed by the Indian philosopher Nāgārjuna (around roughly 150 CE).Siderits and Katsura ...
'' entitled the ''Prajñāpradīpa''. To develop his arguments for emptiness, Bhāvaviveka drew on the work of Dignāga which put forth a new way of presenting logical arguments. Bhāvaviveka was later criticized by Chandrakirti (540-600) for his use of these positive logical arguments. For Chandrakirti, a true Mādhyamika only uses ''
reductio ad absurdum In logic, (Latin for "reduction to absurdity"), also known as (Latin for "argument to absurdity") or ''apagogical argument'', is the form of argument that attempts to establish a claim by showing that the opposite scenario would lead to absur ...
'' arguments and does not put forth positive arguments. Chandrakirti saw in the logico-epistemic tradition a commitment to a foundationalist epistemology and essentialist ontology. For Chandrakirti, a Mādhyamika's job should be to just deconstruct concepts which presuppose an essence.


Yogācāra-svātantrika Mādhyamika

In spite of Chandrakirti's critique, later Buddhist philosophers continued to explain Madhyamaka philosophy through the use of formal syllogisms as well as adopting the conceptual schemas of the Dignaga-Dharmakirti school along with those of the closely related
Yogacara Yogachara (, IAST: ') is an influential tradition of Buddhist philosophy and psychology emphasizing the study of cognition, perception, and consciousness through the interior lens of meditation, as well as philosophical reasoning (hetuvidyā). ...
school). These figures include Jñanagarbha (700–760),
Śāntarakṣita (Sanskrit: शान्तरक्षित; , 725–788),stanford.eduŚāntarakṣita (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)/ref> whose name translates into English as "protected by the One who is at peace" was an important and influential In ...
(725–788), Kamalaśīla, Haribhadra and Ratnākaraśānti (c.1000). Another thinker who worked on both pramana and Madhyamaka was the Kashmiri pandita Parahitabhadra. This tendency within Madhyamaka is termed ''Svātantrika'', while Chandrakirti's stance is termed ''Prasangika''. The Svatantrika-Prasaṅgika distinction is a central topic of debate in Tibetan Buddhist philosophy. In Tibetan Buddhism, those who follow this method and also make use of Yogācāra doctrines are called Yogācāra-Svātantrika Mādhyamika (Tibetan: Rnal ’byor spyod pa’i dbu ma rang rgyud pa). Probably the most influential figure in this tradition is Śāntarakṣita. According to James Blumenthal
Śāntarakṣita attempted to integrate the anti-essentialism of Nāgārjuna with the logico-epistemological thought of Dignāga (''ca.'' 6th c.) and Dharmakīrti (''ca.'' 7th c.) along with facets of Yogācāra/Cittamātra thought into one internally consistent, yet fundamentally Madhyamaka system.
This synthesis is one of the last major developments in Indian Buddhist thought, and has been influential on Tibetan Buddhist philosophy.


In the Tibetan tradition

Tom Tillemans, in discussing the Tibetan translation and assimilation of the logico-epistemological tradition, identifies two currents and transmission streams: The first is the tradition of the Kadampa scholar Ngok Lodzawa Loden Shayrap (1059–1109) and Chapa Chögyi Sengge (1109–69) and their disciples, mainly located at Sangpu Neutok. Chapa's ''Tshad ma’i bsdus pa'' (English: "Summaries of Epistemology and Logic") became the groundwork for the "Collected Topics" (Tibetan: ; Wylie: bsdus grwa) literature, which in large part furnished the Gelugpa-based logical architecture and epistemology. These two scholars (whose works are now lost) strengthened the influence of
Dharmakirti Dharmakīrti (fl. ;), was an influential Indian Buddhist philosopher who worked at Nālandā.Tom Tillemans (2011)Dharmakirti Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy He was one of the key scholars of epistemology ( pramāṇa) in Buddhist philo ...
in Tibetan Buddhist scholarship. There is also another tradition of interpretation founded by Sakya Pandita (1182–1251), who wrote the ''Tshad-ma rigs-gter'' (English: "Treasury of Logic on Valid Cognition"). Sakya pandita secured the place of Dharmakirti's ''Pramanavarttika'' as the foundational text on epistemology in Tibet. Later thinkers of the
Gelug file:DalaiLama0054 tiny.jpg, 240px, 14th Dalai Lama, The 14th Dalai Lama (center), the most influential figure of the contemporary Gelug tradition, at the 2003 Kalachakra ceremony, Bodh Gaya, Bodhgaya (India) The Gelug (, also Geluk; 'virtuous' ...
school such as Gyeltsap and Kaydrup attempted a synthesis of the two traditions, with varying results. This is because the views of Chapa were mostly that of
Philosophical realism Philosophical realismusually not treated as a position of its own but as a stance towards other subject mattersis the view that a certain kind of thing (ranging widely from abstract objects like numbers to moral statements to the physical world ...
, while Sakya pandita was an anti-realist.


Lexicon

* Argument: Vada, rtsod pa * Basis of cognition: Alambana * Characteristic: laksana, mtshan nid * Condition: pratyaya, rkyen * Causal function, purpose: arthakriyā * Debate: Vivada * Demonstrandum: sadhya, bsgrub par bya ba * Demonstrator: sadhaka, grub byed * Dialectician: tartika, rtog ge ba * Dialectics: tarka, rtog ge * Direct perception: pratyaksa, mngon sum * Event: dharma, chos * Event-associate: dharmin, chos can * Exclusion: Apoha, sel ba (Anya-apoha: gzhan sel ba) * Exemplification: drstanta, dpe * Inference: anumana, rjes su dpag pa **Inference for oneself, reasoning: svārthānumāna **Inference for others, demonstration: parārthānumāna * Interference: vyavakirana, 'dres pa * Invariable concomitance: avinabhava, med na mi 'byun ba * Judgment: prajnanana, shes-rab * Justification: hetu, gtan-tshigs * Means of valid cognition:
pramana ''Pramana'' (; IAST: Pramāṇa) literally means " proof" and "means of knowledge".
, tshad ma * Means of evidence: linga, rtags * Particular: svalakṣaṇa * Pervading/pervasion/logical pervasion: vyapti, khyab pa * Perception, Sensation: pratyaksa * Universal, General attribute: Samanyalaksana


See also

*
Logical connective In logic, a logical connective (also called a logical operator, sentential connective, or sentential operator) is a logical constant. Connectives can be used to connect logical formulas. For instance in the syntax of propositional logic, the ...
* Catuṣkoṭi * Tetralemma *
Dharmakirti Dharmakīrti (fl. ;), was an influential Indian Buddhist philosopher who worked at Nālandā.Tom Tillemans (2011)Dharmakirti Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy He was one of the key scholars of epistemology ( pramāṇa) in Buddhist philo ...
* Kathavatthu *
Nyaya Nyāya (Sanskrit: न्यायः, IAST: nyāyaḥ), literally meaning "justice", "rules", "method" or "judgment", is one of the six orthodox (Āstika) schools of Hindu philosophy. Nyāya's most significant contributions to Indian philosophy ...
* Apoha


References


Further reading

* * * * * * * * * (2 vols.) * * *


External links


Vidhabhusana, Satis Chandra (1907). History of the Mediaeval School of Indian Logic. Calcutta University.

Tobden, Tashi (Ed.in Chief); Sadhukhan, Sanjit Kumar (compiler); Dokham, Rigzin Ngodub (compiler) (1994). ''Bulletin of Tibetology: Special Volume on the History of Buddhist Logic.'' New Series, no.3. Gangtok, Sikkim: Sikkim Research Institute of Tibetology


with an annotated bibliography {{Authority control Buddhist logic Nyaya Nāstika Religious debates