Ultrafilter On A Set
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In the
mathematical Mathematics is a field of study that discovers and organizes methods, Mathematical theory, theories and theorems that are developed and Mathematical proof, proved for the needs of empirical sciences and mathematics itself. There are many ar ...
field of
set theory Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies Set (mathematics), sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory – as a branch of mathema ...
, an ultrafilter on a
set Set, The Set, SET or SETS may refer to: Science, technology, and mathematics Mathematics *Set (mathematics), a collection of elements *Category of sets, the category whose objects and morphisms are sets and total functions, respectively Electro ...
X is a ''maximal filter'' on the set X. In other words, it is a collection of subsets of X that satisfies the definition of a filter on X and that is maximal with respect to inclusion, in the sense that there does not exist a strictly larger collection of subsets of X that is also a filter. (In the above, by definition a filter on a set does not contain the empty set.) Equivalently, an ultrafilter on the set X can also be characterized as a filter on X with the property that for every
subset In mathematics, a Set (mathematics), set ''A'' is a subset of a set ''B'' if all Element (mathematics), elements of ''A'' are also elements of ''B''; ''B'' is then a superset of ''A''. It is possible for ''A'' and ''B'' to be equal; if they a ...
A of X either A or its complement X\setminus A belongs to the ultrafilter. Ultrafilters on sets are an important special instance of ultrafilters on partially ordered sets, where the
partially ordered set In mathematics, especially order theory, a partial order on a Set (mathematics), set is an arrangement such that, for certain pairs of elements, one precedes the other. The word ''partial'' is used to indicate that not every pair of elements need ...
consists of the
power set In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is po ...
\wp(X) and the partial order is
subset inclusion In mathematics, a set ''A'' is a subset of a set ''B'' if all elements of ''A'' are also elements of ''B''; ''B'' is then a superset of ''A''. It is possible for ''A'' and ''B'' to be equal; if they are unequal, then ''A'' is a proper subset ...
\,\subseteq. This article deals specifically with ultrafilters on a set and does not cover the more general notion. There are two types of ultrafilter on a set. A principal ultrafilter on X is the collection of all subsets of X that contain a fixed element x \in X. The ultrafilters that are not principal are the free ultrafilters. The existence of free ultrafilters on any infinite set is implied by the
ultrafilter lemma In the mathematical field of set theory, an ultrafilter on a set X is a ''maximal filter'' on the set X. In other words, it is a collection of subsets of X that satisfies the definition of a filter on X and that is maximal with respect to incl ...
, which can be proven in ZFC. On the other hand, there exists models of ZF where every ultrafilter on a set is principal. Ultrafilters have many applications in set theory,
model theory In mathematical logic, model theory is the study of the relationship between theory (mathematical logic), formal theories (a collection of Sentence (mathematical logic), sentences in a formal language expressing statements about a Structure (mat ...
, and
topology Topology (from the Greek language, Greek words , and ) is the branch of mathematics concerned with the properties of a Mathematical object, geometric object that are preserved under Continuous function, continuous Deformation theory, deformat ...
. Usually, only free ultrafilters lead to non-trivial constructions. For example, an
ultraproduct The ultraproduct is a mathematical construction that appears mainly in abstract algebra and mathematical logic, in particular in model theory and set theory. An ultraproduct is a quotient of the direct product of a family of structures. All fact ...
modulo a principal ultrafilter is always isomorphic to one of the factors, while an ultraproduct modulo a free ultrafilter usually has a more complex structure.


Definitions

Given an arbitrary set X, an ultrafilter on X is a non-empty
family Family (from ) is a Social group, group of people related either by consanguinity (by recognized birth) or Affinity (law), affinity (by marriage or other relationship). It forms the basis for social order. Ideally, families offer predictabili ...
U of subsets of X such that: # or : The empty set is not an element of U. #: If A \in U and if B \subseteq X is any superset of A (that is, if A \subseteq B \subseteq X) then B \in U. #: If A and B are elements of U then so is their
intersection In mathematics, the intersection of two or more objects is another object consisting of everything that is contained in all of the objects simultaneously. For example, in Euclidean geometry, when two lines in a plane are not parallel, their ...
A \cap B. #If A \subseteq X then either A or its complement X \setminus A is an element of U.Properties 1 and 3 imply that A and X \setminus A cannot be elements of U. Properties (1), (2), and (3) are the defining properties of a Some authors do not include non-degeneracy (which is property (1) above) in their definition of "filter". However, the definition of "ultrafilter" (and also of "prefilter" and "filter subbase") always includes non-degeneracy as a defining condition. This article requires that all filters be proper although a filter might be described as "proper" for emphasis. A filter base is a non-empty family of sets that has the
finite intersection property In general topology, a branch of mathematics, a non-empty family A of subsets of a set X is said to have the finite intersection property (FIP) if the intersection over any finite subcollection of A is non-empty. It has the strong finite intersect ...
(i.e. all finite intersections are non-empty). Equivalently, a filter subbase is a non-empty family of sets that is contained in (proper) filter. The smallest (relative to \subseteq) filter containing a given filter subbase is said to be generated by the filter subbase. The upward closure in X of a family of sets P is the set :P^ := \. A or is a non-empty and proper (i.e. \varnothing \not\in P) family of sets P that is downward directed, which means that if B, C \in P then there exists some A \in P such that A \subseteq B \cap C. Equivalently, a prefilter is any family of sets P whose upward closure P^ is a filter, in which case this filter is called the filter generated by P and P is said to be a filter base P^. The dual in X of a family of sets P is the set X \setminus P := \. For example, the dual of the
power set In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is po ...
\wp(X) is itself: X \setminus \wp(X) = \wp(X). A family of sets is a proper filter on X if and only if its dual is a proper ideal on X ("" means not equal to the power set).


Generalization to ultra prefilters

A family U \neq \varnothing of subsets of X is called if \varnothing \not\in U and any of the following equivalent conditions are satisfied:
  1. For every set S \subseteq X there exists some set B \in U such that B \subseteq S or B \subseteq X \setminus S (or equivalently, such that B \cap S equals B or \varnothing).
  2. For every set S \subseteq B there exists some set B \in U such that B \cap S equals B or \varnothing. * Here, B is defined to be the union of all sets in U. * This characterization of "U is ultra" does not depend on the set X, so mentioning the set X is optional when using the term "ultra."
  3. For set S (not necessarily even a subset of X) there exists some set B \in U such that B \cap S equals B or \varnothing. * If U satisfies this condition then so does superset V \supseteq U. In particular, a set V is ultra if and only if \varnothing \not\in V and V contains as a subset some ultra family of sets.
A filter subbase that is ultra is necessarily a prefilter.Suppose \mathcal is filter subbase that is ultra. Let C, D \in \mathcal and define S = C \cap D. Because \mathcal is ultra, there exists some B \in \mathcal such that B \cap S equals B or \varnothing. The finite intersection property implies that B \cap S \neq \varnothing so necessarily B \cap S = B, which is equivalent to B \subseteq C \cap D. \blacksquare The ultra property can now be used to define both ultrafilters and ultra prefilters: :An is a prefilter that is ultra. Equivalently, it is a filter subbase that is ultra. :An on X is a (proper) filter on X that is ultra. Equivalently, it is any filter on X that is generated by an ultra prefilter. Ultra prefilters as maximal prefilters To characterize ultra prefilters in terms of "maximality," the following relation is needed. :Given two families of sets M and N, the family M is said to be coarser than N, and N is finer than and subordinate to M, written M \leq N or , if for every C \in M, there is some F \in N such that F \subseteq C. The families M and N are called equivalent if M \leq N and N \leq M. The families M and N are comparable if one of these sets is finer than the other. The subordination relationship, i.e. \,\geq,\, is a
preorder In mathematics, especially in order theory, a preorder or quasiorder is a binary relation that is reflexive relation, reflexive and Transitive relation, transitive. The name is meant to suggest that preorders are ''almost'' partial orders, ...
so the above definition of "equivalent" does form an
equivalence relation In mathematics, an equivalence relation is a binary relation that is reflexive, symmetric, and transitive. The equipollence relation between line segments in geometry is a common example of an equivalence relation. A simpler example is equ ...
. If M \subseteq N then M \leq N but the converse does not hold in general. However, if N is upward closed, such as a filter, then M \leq N if and only if M \subseteq N. Every prefilter is equivalent to the filter that it generates. This shows that it is possible for filters to be equivalent to sets that are not filters. If two families of sets M and N are equivalent then either both M and N are ultra (resp. prefilters, filter subbases) or otherwise neither one of them is ultra (resp. a prefilter, a filter subbase). In particular, if a filter subbase is not also a prefilter, then it is equivalent to the filter or prefilter that it generates. If M and N are both filters on X then M and N are equivalent if and only if M = N. If a proper filter (resp. ultrafilter) is equivalent to a family of sets M then M is necessarily a prefilter (resp. ultra prefilter). Using the following characterization, it is possible to define prefilters (resp. ultra prefilters) using only the concept of filters (resp. ultrafilters) and subordination: :An arbitrary family of sets is a prefilter if and only it is equivalent to a (proper) filter. :An arbitrary family of sets is an ultra prefilter if and only it is equivalent to an ultrafilter. :A on X is a prefilter U \subseteq \wp(X) that satisfies any of the following equivalent conditions:
  1. U is ultra.
  2. U is maximal on \operatorname(X) with respect to \,\leq, meaning that if P \in \operatorname(X) satisfies U \leq P then P \leq U.
  3. There is no prefilter properly subordinate to U.
  4. If a (proper) filter F on X satisfies U \leq F then F \leq U.
  5. The filter on X generated by U is ultra.


Characterizations

There are no ultrafilters on the
empty set In mathematics, the empty set or void set is the unique Set (mathematics), set having no Element (mathematics), elements; its size or cardinality (count of elements in a set) is 0, zero. Some axiomatic set theories ensure that the empty set exi ...
, so it is henceforth assumed that X is nonempty. A filter base U on X is an ultrafilter on X if and only if any of the following equivalent conditions hold:
  1. for any S \subseteq X, either S \in U or X \setminus S \in U.
  2. U is a maximal filter subbase on X, meaning that if F is any filter subbase on X then U \subseteq F implies U = F.
A (proper) filter U on X is an ultrafilter on X if and only if any of the following equivalent conditions hold:
  1. U is ultra;
  2. U is generated by an ultra prefilter;
  3. For any subset S \subseteq X, S \in U or X \setminus S \in U. * So an ultrafilter U decides for every S \subseteq X whether S is "large" (i.e. S \in U) or "small" (i.e. X \setminus S \in U).
  4. For each subset A \subseteq X, either A is in U or (X \setminus A) is.
  5. U \cup (X \setminus U) = \wp(X). This condition can be restated as: \wp(X) is partitioned by U and its dual X \setminus U. * The sets P and X \setminus P are disjoint for all prefilters P on X.
  6. \wp(X) \setminus U = \left\ is an ideal on X.
  7. For any finite family S_1, \ldots, S_n of subsets of X (where n \geq 1), if S_1 \cup \cdots \cup S_n \in U then S_i \in U for some index i. * In words, a "large" set cannot be a finite union of sets none of which is large.
  8. For any R, S \subseteq X, if R \cup S = X then R \in U or S \in U.
  9. For any R, S \subseteq X, if R \cup S \in U then R \in U or S \in U (a filter with this property is called a ).
  10. For any R, S \subseteq X, if R \cup S \in U and R \cap S = \varnothing then R \in U or S \in U.
  11. U is a maximal filter; that is, if F is a filter on X such that U \subseteq F then U = F. Equivalently, U is a maximal filter if there is no filter F on X that contains U as a
    proper subset In mathematics, a set ''A'' is a subset of a set ''B'' if all elements of ''A'' are also elements of ''B''; ''B'' is then a superset of ''A''. It is possible for ''A'' and ''B'' to be equal; if they are unequal, then ''A'' is a proper subset ...
    (that is, no filter is strictly finer than U).


Grills and filter-grills

If \mathcal \subseteq \wp(X) then its is the family \mathcal^ := \ where \mathcal^ may be written if X is clear from context. If \mathcal is a filter then \mathcal^ is the set of positive sets with respect to \mathcal and is usually written as \mathcal^. For example, \varnothing^ = \wp(X) and if \varnothing \in \mathcal then \mathcal^ = \varnothing. If \mathcal \subseteq \mathcal then \mathcal^ \subseteq \mathcal^ and moreover, if \mathcal is a filter subbase then \mathcal \subseteq \mathcal^. The grill \mathcal^ is upward closed in X if and only if \varnothing \not\in \mathcal, which will henceforth be assumed. Moreover, \mathcal^ = \mathcal^ so that \mathcal is upward closed in X if and only if \mathcal^ = \mathcal. The grill of a filter on X is called a For any \varnothing \neq \mathcal \subseteq \wp(X), \mathcal is a filter-grill on X if and only if (1) \mathcal is upward closed in X and (2) for all sets R and S, if R \cup S \in \mathcal then R \in \mathcal or S \in \mathcal. The grill operation \mathcal \mapsto \mathcal^ induces a bijection :^ ~:~ \operatorname(X) \to \operatorname(X) whose inverse is also given by \mathcal \mapsto \mathcal^. If \mathcal \in \operatorname(X) then \mathcal is a filter-grill on X if and only if \mathcal = \mathcal^, or equivalently, if and only if \mathcal is an ultrafilter on X. That is, a filter on X is a filter-grill if and only if it is ultra. For any non-empty \mathcal \subseteq \wp(X), \mathcal is both a filter on X and a filter-grill on X if and only if (1) \varnothing \not\in \mathcal and (2) for all R, S \subseteq X, the following equivalences hold: :R \cup S \in \mathcal if and only if R, S \in \mathcal if and only if R \cap S \in \mathcal.


Free or principal

If P is any non-empty family of sets then the Kernel of P is the intersection of all sets in P: \operatorname P := \bigcap_ B. A non-empty family of sets P is called: * if \operatorname P = \varnothing and otherwise (that is, if \operatorname P \neq \varnothing). * if \operatorname P \in P. * if \operatorname P \in P and \operatorname P is a singleton set; in this case, if \operatorname P = \ then P is said to be principal at x. If a family of sets P is fixed then P is ultra if and only if some element of P is a singleton set, in which case P will necessarily be a prefilter. Every principal prefilter is fixed, so a principal prefilter P is ultra if and only if \operatorname P is a singleton set. A singleton set is ultra if and only if its sole element is also a singleton set. The next theorem shows that every ultrafilter falls into one of two categories: either it is free or else it is a principal filter generated by a single point. Every filter on X that is principal at a single point is an ultrafilter, and if in addition X is finite, then there are no ultrafilters on X other than these. In particular, if a set X has finite cardinality n < \infty, then there are exactly n ultrafilters on X and those are the ultrafilters generated by each singleton subset of X. Consequently, free ultrafilters can only exist on an infinite set.


Examples, properties, and sufficient conditions

If X is an infinite set then there are as many ultrafilters over X as there are families of subsets of X; explicitly, if X has infinite cardinality \kappa then the set of ultrafilters over X has the same cardinality as \wp(\wp(X)); that cardinality being 2^. If U and S are families of sets such that U is ultra, \varnothing \not\in S, and U \leq S, then S is necessarily ultra. A filter subbase U that is not a prefilter cannot be ultra; but it is nevertheless still possible for the prefilter and filter generated by U to be ultra. Suppose U \subseteq \wp(X) is ultra and Y is a set. The trace U\vert_Y := \ is ultra if and only if it does not contain the empty set. Furthermore, at least one of the sets U\vert_Y \setminus \ and U\vert_ \setminus \ will be ultra (this result extends to any finite partition of X). If F_1, \ldots, F_n are filters on X, U is an ultrafilter on X, and F_1 \cap \cdots \cap F_n \leq U, then there is some F_i that satisfies F_i \leq U. This result is not necessarily true for an infinite family of filters. The image under a map f : X \to Y of an ultra set U \subseteq \wp(X) is again ultra and if U is an ultra prefilter then so is f(U). The property of being ultra is preserved under bijections. However, the preimage of an ultrafilter is not necessarily ultra, not even if the map is surjective. For example, if X has more than one point and if the range of f : X \to Y consists of a single point \ then \ is an ultra prefilter on Y but its preimage is not ultra. Alternatively, if U is a principal filter generated by a point in Y \setminus f(X) then the preimage of U contains the empty set and so is not ultra. The elementary filter induced by an infinite sequence, all of whose points are distinct, is an ultrafilter. If n = 2, then U_n denotes the set consisting all subsets of X having cardinality n, and if X contains at least 2 n - 1 (=3) distinct points, then U_n is ultra but it is not contained in any prefilter. This example generalizes to any integer n > 1 and also to n = 1 if X contains more than one element. Ultra sets that are not also prefilters are rarely used. For every S \subseteq X \times X and every a \in X, let S\big\vert_ := \. If \mathcal is an ultrafilter on X then the set of all S \subseteq X \times X such that \left\ \in \mathcal is an ultrafilter on X \times X.


Monad structure

The
functor In mathematics, specifically category theory, a functor is a Map (mathematics), mapping between Category (mathematics), categories. Functors were first considered in algebraic topology, where algebraic objects (such as the fundamental group) ar ...
associating to any set X the set of U(X) of all ultrafilters on X forms a
monad Monad may refer to: Philosophy * Monad (philosophy), a term meaning "unit" **Monism, the concept of "one essence" in the metaphysical and theological theory ** Monad (Gnosticism), the most primal aspect of God in Gnosticism * ''Great Monad'', an ...
called the . The unit map X \to U(X) sends any element x \in X to the principal ultrafilter given by x. This
ultrafilter monad In the mathematical field of set theory, an ultrafilter on a set X is a ''maximal filter'' on the set X. In other words, it is a collection of subsets of X that satisfies the definition of a filter on X and that is maximal with respect to incl ...
is the
codensity monad In mathematics, especially in category theory, the codensity monad is a fundamental construction associating a monad to a wide class of functors. Definition The codensity monad of a functor G: D \to C is defined to be the right Kan extension ...
of the inclusion of the category of finite sets into the category of all sets, which gives a conceptual explanation of this monad. Similarly, the ultraproduct monad is the codensity monad of the inclusion of the category of finite families of sets into the category of all families of set. So in this sense,
ultraproduct The ultraproduct is a mathematical construction that appears mainly in abstract algebra and mathematical logic, in particular in model theory and set theory. An ultraproduct is a quotient of the direct product of a family of structures. All fact ...
s are categorically inevitable.


The ultrafilter lemma

The ultrafilter lemma was first proved by
Alfred Tarski Alfred Tarski (; ; born Alfred Teitelbaum;School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews ''School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews''. January 14, 1901 – October 26, 1983) was a Polish-American logician ...
in 1930. The ultrafilter lemma is equivalent to each of the following statements: # For every prefilter on a set X, there exists a maximal prefilter on X subordinate to it. # Every proper filter subbase on a set X is contained in some ultrafilter on X. A consequence of the ultrafilter lemma is that every filter is equal to the intersection of all ultrafilters containing it.Let \mathcal be a filter on X that is not an ultrafilter. If S \subseteq X is such that S \not\in \mathcal then \ \cup \mathcal has the finite intersection property (because if F \in \mathcal then F \cap (X \setminus S) = \varnothing if and only if F \subseteq S) so that by the ultrafilter lemma, there exists some ultrafilter \mathcal_S on X such that \ \cup \mathcal \subseteq \mathcal_S (so in particular S \not\in \mathcal_S). It follows that \mathcal = \bigcap_ \mathcal_S. \blacksquare The following results can be proven using the ultrafilter lemma. A free ultrafilter exists on a set X if and only if X is infinite. Every proper filter is equal to the intersection of all ultrafilters containing it. Since there are filters that are not ultra, this shows that the intersection of a family of ultrafilters need not be ultra. A family of sets \mathbb \neq \varnothing can be extended to a free ultrafilter if and only if the intersection of any finite family of elements of \mathbb is infinite.


Relationships to other statements under ZF

Throughout this section, ZF refers to
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory In set theory, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, named after mathematicians Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, is an axiomatic system that was proposed in the early twentieth century in order to formulate a theory of sets free of paradoxes suc ...
and ZFC refers to ZF with the
Axiom of Choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from e ...
(AC). The ultrafilter lemma is independent of ZF. That is, there exist
models A model is an informative representation of an object, person, or system. The term originally denoted the plans of a building in late 16th-century English, and derived via French and Italian ultimately from Latin , . Models can be divided int ...
in which the axioms of ZF hold but the ultrafilter lemma does not. There also exist models of ZF in which every ultrafilter is necessarily principal. Every filter that contains a singleton set is necessarily an ultrafilter and given x \in X, the definition of the discrete ultrafilter \ does not require more than ZF. If X is finite then every ultrafilter is a discrete filter at a point; consequently, free ultrafilters can only exist on infinite sets. In particular, if X is finite then the ultrafilter lemma can be proven from the axioms ZF. The existence of free ultrafilter on infinite sets can be proven if the axiom of choice is assumed. More generally, the ultrafilter lemma can be proven by using the
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from e ...
, which in brief states that any
Cartesian product In mathematics, specifically set theory, the Cartesian product of two sets and , denoted , is the set of all ordered pairs where is an element of and is an element of . In terms of set-builder notation, that is A\times B = \. A table c ...
of non-empty sets is non-empty. Under ZF, the axiom of choice is, in particular,
equivalent Equivalence or Equivalent may refer to: Arts and entertainment *Album-equivalent unit, a measurement unit in the music industry *Equivalence class (music) *'' Equivalent VIII'', or ''The Bricks'', a minimalist sculpture by Carl Andre *'' Equiva ...
to (a)
Zorn's lemma Zorn's lemma, also known as the Kuratowski–Zorn lemma, is a proposition of set theory. It states that a partially ordered set containing upper bounds for every chain (that is, every totally ordered subset) necessarily contains at least on ...
, (b)
Tychonoff's theorem In mathematics, Tychonoff's theorem states that the product of any collection of compact topological spaces is compact with respect to the product topology. The theorem is named after Andrey Nikolayevich Tikhonov (whose surname sometimes is tra ...
, (c) the weak form of the vector basis theorem (which states that every vector space has a basis), (d) the strong form of the vector basis theorem, and other statements. However, the ultrafilter lemma is strictly weaker than the axiom of choice. While free ultrafilters can be proven to exist, it is possible to construct an explicit example of a free ultrafilter (using only ZF and the ultrafilter lemma); that is, free ultrafilters are intangible.
Alfred Tarski Alfred Tarski (; ; born Alfred Teitelbaum;School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews ''School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews''. January 14, 1901 – October 26, 1983) was a Polish-American logician ...
proved that under ZFC, the cardinality of the set of all free ultrafilters on an infinite set X is equal to the cardinality of \wp(\wp(X)), where \wp(X) denotes the power set of X. Other authors attribute this discovery to Bedřich Pospíšil (following a combinatorial argument from Fichtenholz, and Kantorovitch, improved by Hausdorff). Under ZF, the
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from e ...
can be used to prove both the ultrafilter lemma and the
Krein–Milman theorem In the mathematical theory of functional analysis, the Krein–Milman theorem is a proposition about compact convex sets in locally convex topological vector spaces (TVSs). This theorem generalizes to infinite-dimensional spaces and to arbitra ...
; conversely, under ZF, the ultrafilter lemma together with the Krein–Milman theorem can prove the axiom of choice.


Statements that cannot be deduced

The ultrafilter lemma is a relatively weak axiom. For example, each of the statements in the following list can be deduced from ZF together with the ultrafilter lemma:
  1. A countable union of
    countable set In mathematics, a set is countable if either it is finite or it can be made in one to one correspondence with the set of natural numbers. Equivalently, a set is ''countable'' if there exists an injective function from it into the natural numbe ...
    s is a countable set.
  2. The
    axiom of countable choice The axiom of countable choice or axiom of denumerable choice, denoted ACω, is an axiom of set theory that states that every countable collection of non-empty sets must have a choice function. That is, given a function A with domain \mathbb ( ...
    (ACC).
  3. The
    axiom of dependent choice In mathematics Mathematics is a field of study that discovers and organizes methods, Mathematical theory, theories and theorems that are developed and Mathematical proof, proved for the needs of empirical sciences and mathematics itself. T ...
    (ADC).


Equivalent statements

Under ZF, the ultrafilter lemma is equivalent to each of the following statements:
  1. The
    Boolean prime ideal theorem In mathematics, the Boolean prime ideal theorem states that Ideal (order theory), ideals in a Boolean algebra (structure), Boolean algebra can be extended to Ideal (order theory)#Prime ideals , prime ideals. A variation of this statement for Filte ...
    (BPIT).
  2. Stone's representation theorem for Boolean algebras In mathematics, Stone's representation theorem for Boolean algebras states that every Boolean algebra is isomorphic to a certain field of sets. The theorem is fundamental to the deeper understanding of Boolean algebra that emerged in the first ha ...
    .
  3. Any product of
    Boolean space In mathematics, Stone's representation theorem for Boolean algebras states that every Boolean algebra is isomorphic to a certain field of sets. The theorem is fundamental to the deeper understanding of Boolean algebra that emerged in the first hal ...
    s is a Boolean space.
  4. Boolean Prime Ideal Existence Theorem: Every nondegenerate
    Boolean algebra In mathematics and mathematical logic, Boolean algebra is a branch of algebra. It differs from elementary algebra in two ways. First, the values of the variable (mathematics), variables are the truth values ''true'' and ''false'', usually denot ...
    has a prime ideal.
  5. Tychonoff's theorem In mathematics, Tychonoff's theorem states that the product of any collection of compact topological spaces is compact with respect to the product topology. The theorem is named after Andrey Nikolayevich Tikhonov (whose surname sometimes is tra ...
    for
    Hausdorff space In topology and related branches of mathematics, a Hausdorff space ( , ), T2 space or separated space, is a topological space where distinct points have disjoint neighbourhoods. Of the many separation axioms that can be imposed on a topologi ...
    s: Any product of
    compact Compact as used in politics may refer broadly to a pact or treaty; in more specific cases it may refer to: * Interstate compact, a type of agreement used by U.S. states * Blood compact, an ancient ritual of the Philippines * Compact government, a t ...
    Hausdorff space In topology and related branches of mathematics, a Hausdorff space ( , ), T2 space or separated space, is a topological space where distinct points have disjoint neighbourhoods. Of the many separation axioms that can be imposed on a topologi ...
    s is compact.
  6. If \ is endowed with the
    discrete topology In topology, a discrete space is a particularly simple example of a topological space or similar structure, one in which the points form a , meaning they are '' isolated'' from each other in a certain sense. The discrete topology is the finest to ...
    then for any set I, the
    product space In topology and related areas of mathematics, a product space is the Cartesian product of a family of topological spaces equipped with a natural topology called the product topology. This topology differs from another, perhaps more natural-seemi ...
    \^I is
    compact Compact as used in politics may refer broadly to a pact or treaty; in more specific cases it may refer to: * Interstate compact, a type of agreement used by U.S. states * Blood compact, an ancient ritual of the Philippines * Compact government, a t ...
    .
  7. Each of the following versions of the Banach-Alaoglu theorem is equivalent to the ultrafilter lemma:
    1. Any equicontinuous set of scalar-valued maps on a
      topological vector space In mathematics, a topological vector space (also called a linear topological space and commonly abbreviated TVS or t.v.s.) is one of the basic structures investigated in functional analysis. A topological vector space is a vector space that is als ...
      (TVS) is relatively compact in the
      weak-* topology In mathematics, weak topology is an alternative term for certain initial topologies, often on topological vector spaces or spaces of linear operators, for instance on a Hilbert space. The term is most commonly used for the initial topology of a ...
      (that is, it is contained in some weak-* compact set).
    2. The polar of any neighborhood of the origin in a TVS X is a weak-* compact subset of its
      continuous dual space In mathematics, any vector space ''V'' has a corresponding dual vector space (or just dual space for short) consisting of all linear forms on ''V,'' together with the vector space structure of pointwise addition and scalar multiplication by const ...
      .
    3. The closed unit ball in the
      continuous dual space In mathematics, any vector space ''V'' has a corresponding dual vector space (or just dual space for short) consisting of all linear forms on ''V,'' together with the vector space structure of pointwise addition and scalar multiplication by const ...
      of any
      normed space The Ateliers et Chantiers de France (ACF, Workshops and Shipyards of France) was a major shipyard that was established in Dunkirk, France, in 1898. The shipyard boomed in the period before World War I (1914–18), but struggled in the inter-war p ...
      is weak-* compact. * If the normed space is separable then the ultrafilter lemma is sufficient but not necessary to prove this statement.
  8. A topological space X is compact if every ultrafilter on X converges to some limit.
  9. A topological space X is compact if every ultrafilter on X converges to some limit. * The addition of the words "and only if" is the only difference between this statement and the one immediately above it.
  10. The
    Alexander subbase theorem In topology, a subbase (or subbasis, prebase, prebasis) for the Topology (structure), topology of a topological space is a subcollection B of \tau that generates \tau, in the sense that \tau is the smallest topology containing B as open sets. A ...
    .
  11. The Ultranet lemma: Every net has a universal subnet. * By definition, a net in X is called an or an if for every subset S \subseteq X, the net is eventually in S or in X \setminus S.
  12. A topological space X is compact if and only if every ultranet on X converges to some limit. * If the words "and only if" are removed then the resulting statement remains equivalent to the ultrafilter lemma.
  13. A
    convergence space In mathematics, a convergence space, also called a generalized convergence, is a set together with a relation called a that satisfies certain properties relating elements of ''X'' with the Family of sets, family of Filter (set theory), filters on ...
    X is compact if every ultrafilter on X converges.
  14. A
    uniform space In the mathematical field of topology, a uniform space is a topological space, set with additional mathematical structure, structure that is used to define ''uniform property, uniform properties'', such as complete space, completeness, uniform con ...
    is compact if it is
    complete Complete may refer to: Logic * Completeness (logic) * Completeness of a theory, the property of a theory that every formula in the theory's language or its negation is provable Mathematics * The completeness of the real numbers, which implies t ...
    and
    totally bounded In topology and related branches of mathematics, total-boundedness is a generalization of compactness for circumstances in which a set is not necessarily closed. A totally bounded set can be covered by finitely many subsets of every fixed “si ...
    .
  15. The Stone–Čech compactification Theorem.
  16. Each of the following versions of the
    compactness theorem In mathematical logic, the compactness theorem states that a set of first-order sentences has a model if and only if every finite subset of it has a model. This theorem is an important tool in model theory, as it provides a useful (but generall ...
    is equivalent to the ultrafilter lemma:
    1. If \Sigma is a set of first-order
      sentences The ''Sentences'' (. ) is a compendium of Christian theology written by Peter Lombard around 1150. It was the most important religious textbook of the Middle Ages. Background The sentence genre emerged from works like Prosper of Aquitaine's ...
      such that every finite subset of \Sigma has a
      model A model is an informative representation of an object, person, or system. The term originally denoted the plans of a building in late 16th-century English, and derived via French and Italian ultimately from Latin , . Models can be divided in ...
      , then \Sigma has a model.
    2. If \Sigma is a set of zero-order sentences such that every finite subset of \Sigma has a model, then \Sigma has a model.
  17. The
    completeness theorem Complete may refer to: Logic * Completeness (logic) * Completeness of a theory, the property of a theory that every formula in the theory's language or its negation is provable Mathematics * The completeness of the real numbers, which implies ...
    : If \Sigma is a set of zero-order sentences that is syntactically consistent, then it has a model (that is, it is semantically consistent).


Weaker statements

Any statement that can be deduced from the ultrafilter lemma (together with ZF) is said to be than the ultrafilter lemma. A weaker statement is said to be if under ZF, it is not equivalent to the ultrafilter lemma. Under ZF, the ultrafilter lemma implies each of the following statements:
  1. The Axiom of Choice for Finite sets (ACF): Given I \neq \varnothing and a family \left(X_i\right)_ of non-empty sets, their product X_i is not empty.
  2. A
    countable In mathematics, a Set (mathematics), set is countable if either it is finite set, finite or it can be made in one to one correspondence with the set of natural numbers. Equivalently, a set is ''countable'' if there exists an injective function fro ...
    union of finite sets is a countable set. * However, ZF with the ultrafilter lemma is too weak to prove that a countable union of sets is a countable set.
  3. The
    Hahn–Banach theorem In functional analysis, the Hahn–Banach theorem is a central result that allows the extension of bounded linear functionals defined on a vector subspace of some vector space to the whole space. The theorem also shows that there are sufficient ...
    . * In ZF, the Hahn–Banach theorem is strictly weaker than the ultrafilter lemma.
  4. The
    Banach–Tarski paradox The Banach–Tarski paradox is a theorem in set-theoretic geometry, which states the following: Given a solid ball in three-dimensional space, there exists a decomposition of the ball into a finite number of disjoint subsets, which can then ...
    . * In fact, under ZF, the Banach–Tarski paradox can be deduced from the
    Hahn–Banach theorem In functional analysis, the Hahn–Banach theorem is a central result that allows the extension of bounded linear functionals defined on a vector subspace of some vector space to the whole space. The theorem also shows that there are sufficient ...
    , which is strictly weaker than the Ultrafilter Lemma.
  5. Every set can be
    linearly ordered In mathematics, a total order or linear order is a partial order in which any two elements are comparable. That is, a total order is a binary relation \leq on some set X, which satisfies the following for all a, b and c in X: # a \leq a ( re ...
    .
  6. Every field has a unique
    algebraic closure In mathematics, particularly abstract algebra, an algebraic closure of a field ''K'' is an algebraic extension of ''K'' that is algebraically closed. It is one of many closures in mathematics. Using Zorn's lemmaMcCarthy (1991) p.21Kaplansky ...
    .
  7. Non-trivial
    ultraproducts The ultraproduct is a mathematics, mathematical construction that appears mainly in abstract algebra and mathematical logic, in particular in model theory and set theory. An ultraproduct is a quotient of the direct product of a family of Structure ...
    exist.
  8. The weak ultrafilter theorem: A free ultrafilter exists on \N. * Under ZF, the weak ultrafilter theorem does not imply the ultrafilter lemma; that is, it is strictly weaker than the ultrafilter lemma.
  9. There exists a free ultrafilter on every infinite set; * This statement is actually strictly weaker than the ultrafilter lemma. * ZF alone does not even imply that there exists a non-principal ultrafilter on set.


Completeness

The completeness of an ultrafilter U on a powerset is the smallest
cardinal Cardinal or The Cardinal most commonly refers to * Cardinalidae, a family of North and South American birds **''Cardinalis'', genus of three species in the family Cardinalidae ***Northern cardinal, ''Cardinalis cardinalis'', the common cardinal of ...
κ such that there are κ elements of U whose intersection is not in U. The definition of an ultrafilter implies that the completeness of any powerset ultrafilter is at least \aleph_0. An ultrafilter whose completeness is than \aleph_0—that is, the intersection of any countable collection of elements of U is still in U—is called countably complete or σ-complete. The completeness of a countably complete nonprincipal ultrafilter on a powerset is always a
measurable cardinal In mathematics, a measurable cardinal is a certain kind of large cardinal number. In order to define the concept, one introduces a two-valued measure (mathematics), measure on a cardinal ''κ'', or more generally on any set. For a cardinal ''κ'', ...
.


The (named after Mary Ellen Rudin and

Howard Jerome Keisler Howard Jerome Keisler (born 3 December 1936) is an American mathematician, currently professor emeritus at University of Wisconsin–Madison. His research has included model theory and non-standard analysis. His Ph.D. advisor was Alfred Tarski a ...
) is a
preorder In mathematics, especially in order theory, a preorder or quasiorder is a binary relation that is reflexive relation, reflexive and Transitive relation, transitive. The name is meant to suggest that preorders are ''almost'' partial orders, ...
on the class of powerset ultrafilters defined as follows: if U is an ultrafilter on \wp(X), and V an ultrafilter on \wp(Y), then V \leq _ U if there exists a function f : X \to Y such that :C \in V if and only if f^ \in U for every subset C \subseteq Y. Ultrafilters U and V are called , denoted , if there exist sets A \in U and B \in V and a
bijection In mathematics, a bijection, bijective function, or one-to-one correspondence is a function between two sets such that each element of the second set (the codomain) is the image of exactly one element of the first set (the domain). Equival ...
f : A \to B that satisfies the condition above. (If X and Y have the same cardinality, the definition can be simplified by fixing A = X, B = Y.) It is known that ≡RK is the kernel of ≤RK, i.e., that if and only if U \leq _ V and V \leq _ U.


Ultrafilters on ℘(ω)

There are several special properties that an ultrafilter on \wp(\omega), where \omega extends the natural numbers, may possess, which prove useful in various areas of set theory and topology. * A non-principal ultrafilter U is called a P-point (or ) if for every partition \left\ of \omega such that for all n < \omega, C_n \not\in U, there exists some A \in U such that A \cap C_n is a finite set for each n. * A non-principal ultrafilter U is called Ramsey (or selective) if for every partition \left\ of \omega such that for all n < \omega, C_n \not\in U, there exists some A \in U such that A \cap C_n is a
singleton set In mathematics, a singleton (also known as a unit set or one-point set) is a set with exactly one element. For example, the set \ is a singleton whose single element is 0. Properties Within the framework of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, the a ...
for each n. It is a trivial observation that all Ramsey ultrafilters are P-points.
Walter Rudin Walter Rudin (May 2, 1921 – May 20, 2010) was an Austrian- American mathematician and professor of mathematics at the University of Wisconsin–Madison. In addition to his contributions to complex and harmonic analysis, Rudin was known for hi ...
proved that the
continuum hypothesis In mathematics, specifically set theory, the continuum hypothesis (abbreviated CH) is a hypothesis about the possible sizes of infinite sets. It states: Or equivalently: In Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC), this ...
implies the existence of Ramsey ultrafilters. In fact, many hypotheses imply the existence of Ramsey ultrafilters, including
Martin's axiom In the mathematical field of set theory, Martin's axiom, introduced by Donald A. Martin and Robert M. Solovay, is a statement that is independent of the usual axioms of ZFC set theory. It is implied by the continuum hypothesis, but it is consi ...
.
Saharon Shelah Saharon Shelah (; , ; born July 3, 1945) is an Israeli mathematician. He is a professor of mathematics at the Hebrew University of Jerusalem and Rutgers University in New Jersey. Biography Shelah was born in Jerusalem on July 3, 1945. He is th ...
later showed that it is consistent that there are no P-point ultrafilters. Therefore, the existence of these types of ultrafilters is
independent Independent or Independents may refer to: Arts, entertainment, and media Artist groups * Independents (artist group), a group of modernist painters based in Pennsylvania, United States * Independentes (English: Independents), a Portuguese artist ...
of ZFC. P-points are called as such because they are topological P-points in the usual topology of the space of non-principal ultrafilters. The name Ramsey comes from
Ramsey's theorem In combinatorics, Ramsey's theorem, in one of its graph-theoretic forms, states that one will find monochromatic cliques in any edge labelling (with colours) of a sufficiently large complete graph. To demonstrate the theorem for two colours (sa ...
. To see why, one can prove that an ultrafilter is Ramsey if and only if for every 2-coloring of
omega Omega (, ; uppercase Ω, lowercase ω; Ancient Greek ὦ, later ὦ μέγα, Modern Greek ωμέγα) is the twenty-fourth and last letter in the Greek alphabet. In the Greek numerals, Greek numeric system/isopsephy (gematria), it has a value ...
2 there exists an element of the ultrafilter that has a homogeneous color. An ultrafilter on \wp(\omega) is Ramsey if and only if it is minimal in the Rudin–Keisler ordering of non-principal powerset ultrafilters.


See also

* * * * * * *


Notes

Proofs


References


Bibliography

* * * * * * * * * * *


Further reading

* * * {{Mathematical logic Families of sets Nonstandard analysis Order theory