The
language of mathematics has a wide
vocabulary
A vocabulary (also known as a lexicon) is a set of words, typically the set in a language or the set known to an individual. The word ''vocabulary'' originated from the Latin , meaning "a word, name". It forms an essential component of languag ...
of specialist and technical terms. It also has a certain amount of
jargon
Jargon, or technical language, is the specialized terminology associated with a particular field or area of activity. Jargon is normally employed in a particular Context (language use), communicative context and may not be well understood outside ...
: commonly used phrases which are part of the culture of mathematics, rather than of the subject. Jargon often appears in lectures, and sometimes in print, as informal shorthand for
rigorous arguments or precise ideas. Much of this uses common English words, but with a specific non-obvious meaning when used in a mathematical sense.
Some phrases, like "in general", appear below in more than one section.
Philosophy of mathematics
;
abstract nonsense:A
tongue-in-cheek reference to
category theory
Category theory is a general theory of mathematical structures and their relations. It was introduced by Samuel Eilenberg and Saunders Mac Lane in the middle of the 20th century in their foundational work on algebraic topology. Category theory ...
, using which one can employ arguments that establish a (possibly concrete) result without reference to any specifics of the present problem. For that reason, it is also known as ''general abstract nonsense'' or ''generalized abstract nonsense''.
;
canonical:A reference to a standard or choice-free presentation of some
mathematical object (e.g., canonical map, canonical form, or canonical ordering). The same term can also be used more informally to refer to something "standard" or "classic". For example, one might say that
Euclid's proof is the "canonical proof" of
the infinitude of primes.
; deep:A result is called "deep" if its proof requires concepts and methods that are advanced beyond the concepts needed to formulate the result. For example, the
prime number theorem
In mathematics, the prime number theorem (PNT) describes the asymptotic analysis, asymptotic distribution of the prime numbers among the positive integers. It formalizes the intuitive idea that primes become less common as they become larger by p ...
— originally proved using techniques of
complex analysis
Complex analysis, traditionally known as the theory of functions of a complex variable, is the branch of mathematical analysis that investigates functions of complex numbers. It is helpful in many branches of mathematics, including algebraic ...
— was once thought to be a deep result until
elementary proof In mathematics, an elementary proof is a mathematical proof that only uses basic techniques. More specifically, the term is used in number theory to refer to proofs that make no use of complex analysis. Historically, it was once thought that certain ...
s were found. On the other hand, the fact that
π is irrational is usually known to be a deep result, because it requires a considerable development of
real analysis before the proof can be established — even though the claim itself can be stated in terms of simple
number theory
Number theory is a branch of pure mathematics devoted primarily to the study of the integers and arithmetic functions. Number theorists study prime numbers as well as the properties of mathematical objects constructed from integers (for example ...
and
geometry
Geometry (; ) is a branch of mathematics concerned with properties of space such as the distance, shape, size, and relative position of figures. Geometry is, along with arithmetic, one of the oldest branches of mathematics. A mathematician w ...
.
;
elegant:An aesthetic term referring to the ability of an idea to provide insight into mathematics, whether by unifying disparate fields, introducing a new perspective on a single field, or by providing a technique of proof which is either particularly simple, or which captures the intuition or imagination as to why the result it proves is true. In some occasions, the term "beautiful" can also be used to the same effect, though
Gian-Carlo Rota distinguished between ''elegance of presentation'' and ''beauty of concept'', saying that for example, some topics could be written about elegantly although the mathematical content is not beautiful, and some
theorems or proofs are beautiful but may be written about inelegantly.
;
elementary:A proof or a result is called "elementary" if it only involves basic concepts and methods in the field, and is to be contrasted with
deep results which require more development within or outside the field. The concept of "elementary proof" is used specifically in
number theory
Number theory is a branch of pure mathematics devoted primarily to the study of the integers and arithmetic functions. Number theorists study prime numbers as well as the properties of mathematical objects constructed from integers (for example ...
, where it usually refers to a proof that does not resort to methods from
complex analysis
Complex analysis, traditionally known as the theory of functions of a complex variable, is the branch of mathematical analysis that investigates functions of complex numbers. It is helpful in many branches of mathematics, including algebraic ...
.
;
folklore
Folklore is the body of expressive culture shared by a particular group of people, culture or subculture. This includes oral traditions such as Narrative, tales, myths, legends, proverbs, Poetry, poems, jokes, and other oral traditions. This also ...
:A result is called "folklore" if it is non-obvious and non-published, yet generally known to the specialists within a field. In many scenarios, it is unclear as to who first obtained the result, though if the result is significant, it may eventually find its way into the textbooks, whereupon it ceases to be folklore.
;
natural:Similar to "canonical" but more specific, and which makes reference to a description (almost exclusively in the context of
transformations) which holds independently of any choices. Though long used informally, this term has found a formal definition in category theory.
;
pathological:An object behaves pathologically (or, somewhat more broadly used, in a ''degenerated'' way) if it either fails to conform to the generic behavior of such objects, fails to satisfy certain context-dependent regularity properties, or simply disobeys
mathematical intuition. In many occasions, these can be and often are contradictory requirements, while in other occasions, the term is more deliberately used to refer to an object artificially constructed as a counterexample to these properties. A simple example is that from the definition of a
triangle
A triangle is a polygon with three corners and three sides, one of the basic shapes in geometry. The corners, also called ''vertices'', are zero-dimensional points while the sides connecting them, also called ''edges'', are one-dimension ...
having
angle
In Euclidean geometry, an angle can refer to a number of concepts relating to the intersection of two straight Line (geometry), lines at a Point (geometry), point. Formally, an angle is a figure lying in a Euclidean plane, plane formed by two R ...
s which sum to π radians, a single straight line conforms to this definition pathologically.
:Note for that latter quote that as the differentiable functions are
meagre in the space of continuous functions, as
Banach found out in 1931, differentiable functions are colloquially speaking a rare exception among the continuous ones. Thus it can hardly be defended any-more to call non-differentiable continuous functions pathological.
;
rigor (rigour):The act of establishing a mathematical result using indisputable logic, rather than informal descriptive argument. Rigor is a cornerstone quality of mathematics, and can play an important role in preventing mathematics from degenerating into fallacies.
;
well-behaved
In mathematics, when a mathematical phenomenon runs counter to some intuition, then the phenomenon is sometimes called pathological. On the other hand, if a phenomenon does not run counter to intuition, it is sometimes called well-behaved or n ...
:An object is well-behaved (in contrast with being ''
Pathological'') if it satisfies certain prevailing regularity properties, or if it conforms to mathematical intuition (even though intuition can often suggest opposite behaviors as well). In some occasions (e.g.,
analysis), the term "
smooth''"'' can also be used to the same effect.
Descriptive informalities
Although ultimately every mathematical argument must meet a high standard of precision, mathematicians use descriptive but informal statements to discuss recurring themes or concepts with unwieldy formal statements. Note that many of the terms are completely rigorous in context.
;
almost all
In mathematics, the term "almost all" means "all but a negligible quantity". More precisely, if X is a set (mathematics), set, "almost all elements of X" means "all elements of X but those in a negligible set, negligible subset of X". The meaning o ...
: A shorthand term for "all except for a
set of
measure zero
In mathematical analysis, a null set is a Lebesgue measurable set of real numbers that has Lebesgue measure, measure zero. This can be characterized as a set that can be Cover (topology), covered by a countable union of Interval (mathematics), ...
", when there is a
measure to speak of. For example, "almost all
real number
In mathematics, a real number is a number that can be used to measure a continuous one- dimensional quantity such as a duration or temperature. Here, ''continuous'' means that pairs of values can have arbitrarily small differences. Every re ...
s are
transcendental" because the
algebraic real numbers form a
countable
In mathematics, a Set (mathematics), set is countable if either it is finite set, finite or it can be made in one to one correspondence with the set of natural numbers. Equivalently, a set is ''countable'' if there exists an injective function fro ...
subset
In mathematics, a Set (mathematics), set ''A'' is a subset of a set ''B'' if all Element (mathematics), elements of ''A'' are also elements of ''B''; ''B'' is then a superset of ''A''. It is possible for ''A'' and ''B'' to be equal; if they a ...
of the real numbers with measure zero. One can also speak of "almost all"
integer
An integer is the number zero (0), a positive natural number (1, 2, 3, ...), or the negation of a positive natural number (−1, −2, −3, ...). The negations or additive inverses of the positive natural numbers are referred to as negative in ...
s having a property to mean "all except finitely many", despite the integers not admitting a measure for which this agrees with the previous usage. For example, "almost all prime numbers are
odd". There is a more complicated meaning for integers as well, discussed in the main article. Finally, this term is sometimes used synonymously with ''generic'', below.
;
arbitrarily large In mathematics, the phrases arbitrarily large, arbitrarily small and arbitrarily long are used in statements to make clear the fact that an object is large, small, or long with little limitation or restraint, respectively. The use of "arbitrarily" o ...
: Notions which arise mostly in the context of
limits, referring to the recurrence of a phenomenon as the limit is approached. A statement such as that predicate ''P'' is satisfied by arbitrarily large values, can be expressed in more formal notation by . See also ''frequently''. The statement that quantity ''f''(''x'') depending on ''x'' "can be made" arbitrarily large, corresponds to .
;
arbitrary: A shorthand for the
universal quantifier. An arbitrary choice is one which is made unrestrictedly, or alternatively, a statement holds of an arbitrary element of a set if it holds of any element of that set. Also much in general-language use among mathematicians: "Of course, this problem can be arbitrarily complicated".
;
eventually:In the context of limits, this is shorthand meaning ''for sufficiently large arguments''; the relevant argument(s) are implicit in the context. As an example, the function log(log(''x'')) ''eventually'' becomes larger than 100"; in this context, "eventually" means "for
sufficiently large
In the mathematical areas of number theory and analysis, an infinite sequence or a function is said to eventually have a certain property, if it does not have the said property across all its ordered instances, but will after some instances have ...
''x''."
;
factor through: A term in
category theory
Category theory is a general theory of mathematical structures and their relations. It was introduced by Samuel Eilenberg and Saunders Mac Lane in the middle of the 20th century in their foundational work on algebraic topology. Category theory ...
referring to composition of
morphisms. If for three
objects ''A'', ''B'', and ''C'' a map
can be written as a composition
with
and
, then ''f'' is said to ''factor through'' any (and all) of
,
, and
.
; finite: When said of the value of a variable assuming values from the non-negative
extended reals the meaning is usually "not infinite". For example, if the
variance
In probability theory and statistics, variance is the expected value of the squared deviation from the mean of a random variable. The standard deviation (SD) is obtained as the square root of the variance. Variance is a measure of dispersion ...
of a random variable is said to be finite, this implies it is a non-negative real number, possibly zero. In some contexts though, for example in "a small but finite amplitude", zero and infinitesimals are meant to be excluded. When said of the value of a variable assuming values from the extended natural numbers
the meaning is simply "not infinite". When said of a set or a mathematical whose main component is a set, it means that the
cardinality
The thumb is the first digit of the hand, next to the index finger. When a person is standing in the medical anatomical position (where the palm is facing to the front), the thumb is the outermost digit. The Medical Latin English noun for thum ...
of the set is less than
.
; frequently: In the context of limits, this is shorthand for ''
arbitrarily large In mathematics, the phrases arbitrarily large, arbitrarily small and arbitrarily long are used in statements to make clear the fact that an object is large, small, or long with little limitation or restraint, respectively. The use of "arbitrarily" o ...
arguments'' and its relatives; as with ''eventually'', the intended variant is implicit. As an example, the
sequence
In mathematics, a sequence is an enumerated collection of objects in which repetitions are allowed and order matters. Like a set, it contains members (also called ''elements'', or ''terms''). The number of elements (possibly infinite) is cal ...
is frequently in the
interval (1/2, 3/2), because there are arbitrarily large ''n'' for which the value of the sequence is in the interval.
; formal, formally: Qualifies anything that is sufficiently precise to be translated straightforwardly in a
formal system. For example. a
formal proof, a formal definition.
;
generic: This term has similar connotations as ''almost all'' but is used particularly for concepts outside the purview of
measure theory
In mathematics, the concept of a measure is a generalization and formalization of geometrical measures (length, area, volume) and other common notions, such as magnitude (mathematics), magnitude, mass, and probability of events. These seemingl ...
. A property holds "generically" on a set if the set satisfies some (context-dependent) notion of density, or perhaps if its
complement satisfies some (context-dependent) notion of smallness. For example, a property which holds on a
dense G
δ (
intersection of countably many
open set
In mathematics, an open set is a generalization of an Interval (mathematics)#Definitions_and_terminology, open interval in the real line.
In a metric space (a Set (mathematics), set with a metric (mathematics), distance defined between every two ...
s) is said to hold generically. In
algebraic geometry
Algebraic geometry is a branch of mathematics which uses abstract algebraic techniques, mainly from commutative algebra, to solve geometry, geometrical problems. Classically, it studies zero of a function, zeros of multivariate polynomials; th ...
, one says that a property of points on an
algebraic variety that holds on a dense
Zariski open set is true generically; however, it is usually not said that a property which holds merely on a dense set (which is not Zariski open) is generic in this situation.
; in general: In a descriptive context, this phrase introduces a simple characterization of a broad class of , with an eye towards identifying a unifying principle. This term introduces an "elegant" description which holds for "
arbitrary" objects. Exceptions to this description may be mentioned explicitly, as "
pathological" cases.
;
left-hand side, right-hand side (LHS, RHS): Most often, these refer simply to the left-hand or the right-hand side of an
equation
In mathematics, an equation is a mathematical formula that expresses the equality of two expressions, by connecting them with the equals sign . The word ''equation'' and its cognates in other languages may have subtly different meanings; for ...
; for example,
has
on the LHS and
on the RHS. Occasionally, these are used in the sense of
lvalue and rvalue: an RHS is primitive, and an LHS is derivative.
; nice: A mathematical is colloquially called ''nice'' or ''sufficiently nice'' if it satisfies hypotheses or properties, sometimes unspecified or even unknown, that are especially desirable in a given context. It is an informal antonym for
pathological. For example, one might conjecture that a
differential operator ought to satisfy a certain boundedness condition "for nice test functions," or one might state that some interesting
topological invariant should be computable "for nice
spaces ''X''."
;
: Anything that can be assigned to a
variable and for which
equality with another object can be considered. The term was coined when variables began to be used for
sets and
mathematical structures.
; onto: A function (which in mathematics is generally defined as mapping the elements of one set ''A'' to elements of another ''B'') is called "''A'' onto ''B''" (instead of "''A'' to ''B''" or "''A'' into ''B''") only if it is
surjective; it may even be said that "''f'' is onto" (i. e. surjective). Not translatable (without circumlocutions) to some languages other than English.
; proper: If, for some notion of substructure, are substructures of themselves (that is, the relationship is
reflexive), then the qualification ''proper'' requires the objects to be different. For example, a ''proper'' subset of a set ''S'' is a subset of ''S'' that is different from ''S'', and a ''proper''
divisor of a number ''n'' is a divisor of ''n'' that is different from ''n''. This
overloaded word is also non-jargon for a
proper morphism.
; regular : A function is called ''regular'' if it satisfies satisfactory continuity and differentiability properties, which are often context-dependent. These properties might include possessing a specified number of
derivative
In mathematics, the derivative is a fundamental tool that quantifies the sensitivity to change of a function's output with respect to its input. The derivative of a function of a single variable at a chosen input value, when it exists, is t ...
s, with the function and its derivatives exhibiting some ''nice'' property (see ''nice'' above), such as
Hölder continuity. Informally, this term is sometimes used synonymously with ''smooth'', below. These imprecise uses of the word ''regular'' are not to be confused with the notion of a
regular topological space, which is rigorously defined.
; resp.: (Respectively) A convention to shorten parallel expositions. "''A'' (resp. ''B'')
as some relationship to''X'' (resp. ''Y'')" means that ''A''
as some relationship to''X'' and also that ''B''
as (the same) relationship to''Y''. For example,
square
In geometry, a square is a regular polygon, regular quadrilateral. It has four straight sides of equal length and four equal angles. Squares are special cases of rectangles, which have four equal angles, and of rhombuses, which have four equal si ...
s (resp. triangles) have 4 sides (resp. 3 sides); or
compact (resp.
Lindelöf) spaces are ones where every open
cover has a finite (resp. countable) open subcover.
; sharp: Often, a mathematical theorem will establish constraints on the behavior of some ; for example, a function will be shown to have an
upper or lower bound. The constraint is ''sharp'' (sometimes ''optimal'') if it cannot be made more restrictive without failing in some cases. For example, for
arbitrary non-negative real numbers ''x'', the
exponential function ''e
x'', where
''e'' = 2.7182818..., gives an upper bound on the values of the
quadratic function ''x''
2. This is not sharp; the gap between the functions is everywhere at least 1. Among the exponential functions of the form α
''x'', setting α = ''e''
2/''e'' = 2.0870652... results in a sharp upper bound; the slightly smaller choice α = 2 fails to produce an upper bound, since then α
3 = 8 < 3
2. In applied fields the word "tight" is often used with the same meaning.
;
smooth: ''Smoothness'' is a concept which mathematics has endowed with many meanings, from simple differentiability to infinite differentiability to
analyticity, and still others which are more complicated. Each such usage attempts to invoke the physically intuitive notion of smoothness.
; strong, stronger: A theorem is said to be ''strong'' if it deduces restrictive results from general hypotheses. One celebrated example is
Donaldson's theorem, which puts tight restraints on what would otherwise appear to be a large class of manifolds. This (informal) usage reflects the opinion of the mathematical community: not only should such a theorem be strong in the descriptive sense (below) but it should also be definitive in its area. A theorem, result, or condition is further called ''stronger'' than another one if a proof of the second can be easily obtained from the first but not conversely. An example is the sequence of theorems:
Fermat's little theorem,
Euler's theorem,
Lagrange's theorem, each of which is stronger than the last; another is that a sharp upper bound (see ''sharp'' above) is a stronger result than a non-sharp one. Finally, the adjective ''strong'' or the adverb ''strongly'' may be added to a mathematical notion to indicate a related stronger notion; for example, a
strong antichain is an
antichain satisfying certain additional conditions, and likewise a
strongly regular graph is a
regular graph meeting stronger conditions. When used in this way, the stronger notion (such as "strong antichain") is a technical term with a precisely defined meaning; the nature of the extra conditions cannot be derived from the definition of the weaker notion (such as "antichain").
;
sufficiently large
In the mathematical areas of number theory and analysis, an infinite sequence or a function is said to eventually have a certain property, if it does not have the said property across all its ordered instances, but will after some instances have ...
, suitably small, sufficiently close: In the context of limits, these terms refer to some (unspecified, even unknown) point at which a phenomenon prevails as the limit is approached. A statement such as that predicate ''P'' holds for sufficiently large values, can be expressed in more formal notation by ∃''x'' : ∀''y'' ≥ ''x'' : ''P''(''y''). See also ''eventually''.
; upstairs, downstairs: A descriptive term referring to notation in which two are written one above the other; the upper one is ''upstairs'' and the lower, ''downstairs''. For example, in a
fiber bundle, the total space is often said to be ''upstairs'', with the base space ''downstairs''. In a
fraction
A fraction (from , "broken") represents a part of a whole or, more generally, any number of equal parts. When spoken in everyday English, a fraction describes how many parts of a certain size there are, for example, one-half, eight-fifths, thre ...
, the
numerator is occasionally referred to as ''upstairs'' and the
denominator ''downstairs'', as in "bringing a term upstairs".
;
up to, modulo, mod out by: An extension to mathematical discourse of the notions of
modular arithmetic
In mathematics, modular arithmetic is a system of arithmetic operations for integers, other than the usual ones from elementary arithmetic, where numbers "wrap around" when reaching a certain value, called the modulus. The modern approach to mo ...
. A statement is true ''up to'' a condition if the establishment of that condition is the only impediment to the truth of the statement. Also used when working with members of
equivalence classes, especially in
category theory
Category theory is a general theory of mathematical structures and their relations. It was introduced by Samuel Eilenberg and Saunders Mac Lane in the middle of the 20th century in their foundational work on algebraic topology. Category theory ...
, where the
equivalence relation is (categorical) isomorphism; for example, "The tensor product in a weak
monoidal category
In mathematics, a monoidal category (or tensor category) is a category (mathematics), category \mathbf C equipped with a bifunctor
:\otimes : \mathbf \times \mathbf \to \mathbf
that is associative up to a natural isomorphism, and an Object (cate ...
is associative and unital up to a
natural isomorphism."
; vanish: To assume the value 0. For example, "The function sin(''x'') vanishes for those values of ''x'' that are integer multiples of π." This can also apply to limits: see
Vanish at infinity In mathematics, a function is said to vanish at infinity if its values approach 0 as the input grows without bounds. There are two different ways to define this with one definition applying to functions defined on normed vector spaces and the othe ...
.
; weak, weaker: The converse of
strong.
; well-defined: Accurately and precisely described or specified. For example, sometimes a definition relies on a choice of some ; the result of the definition must then be independent of this choice.
Proof terminology
The formal language of
proof draws repeatedly from a small pool of ideas, many of which are invoked through various lexical shorthands in practice.
; aliter: An obsolescent term which is used to announce to the reader an alternative method, or proof of a result. In a proof, it therefore flags a piece of reasoning that is superfluous from a logical point of view, but has some other interest.
;
by way of contradiction (BWOC), or "for, if not, ...": The rhetorical prelude to a
proof by contradiction
In logic, proof by contradiction is a form of proof that establishes the truth or the validity of a proposition by showing that assuming the proposition to be false leads to a contradiction.
Although it is quite freely used in mathematical pr ...
, preceding the
negation
In logic, negation, also called the logical not or logical complement, is an operation (mathematics), operation that takes a Proposition (mathematics), proposition P to another proposition "not P", written \neg P, \mathord P, P^\prime or \over ...
of the statement to be proved.
;
if and only if
In logic and related fields such as mathematics and philosophy, "if and only if" (often shortened as "iff") is paraphrased by the biconditional, a logical connective between statements. The biconditional is true in two cases, where either bo ...
(iff): An abbreviation for
logical equivalence
In logic and mathematics, statements p and q are said to be logically equivalent if they have the same truth value in every model. The logical equivalence of p and q is sometimes expressed as p \equiv q, p :: q, \textsfpq, or p \iff q, depending ...
of statements.
; in general: In the context of proofs, this phrase is often seen in
induction arguments when passing from the base case to the induction step, and similarly, in the definition of sequences whose first few terms are exhibited as examples of the formula giving every term of the sequence.
;
necessary and sufficient: A minor variant on "if and only if"; "''A'' is ''necessary'' (''and sufficient'') for ''B''" means "''A'' if (only if) ''B''". For example, "For a
field ''K'' to be
algebraically closed it is necessary and sufficient that it have no finite
field extensions" means "''K'' is algebraically closed if and only if it has no finite extensions". Often used in lists, as in "The following conditions are necessary and sufficient for a field to be algebraically closed...".
; need to show (NTS), required to prove (RTP), wish to show, want to show (WTS): Proofs sometimes proceed by enumerating several conditions whose satisfaction will together imply the desired theorem; thus, one ''needs to show'' just these statements.
;
one and only one: A statement of the
existence and uniqueness of an ; the object exists, and furthermore, no other such object exists.
;
Q.E.D.
Q.E.D. or QED is an initialism of the List of Latin phrases (full), Latin phrase , meaning "that which was to be demonstrated". Literally, it states "what was to be shown". Traditionally, the abbreviation is placed at the end of Mathematical proof ...
: (''Quod erat demonstrandum''): A Latin abbreviation, meaning "which was to be demonstrated", historically placed at the end of proofs, but less common currently, having been supplanted by the
Halmos end-of-proof mark, a square sign ∎.
; sufficiently nice: A condition on in the scope of the discussion, to be specified later, that will guarantee that some stated property holds for them. When
working out a theorem, the use of this expression in the statement of the theorem indicates that the conditions involved may be not yet known to the speaker, and that the intent is to collect the conditions that will be found to be needed in order for the proof of the theorem to go through.
; the following are equivalent (TFAE): Often several equivalent conditions (especially for a definition, such as
normal subgroup
In abstract algebra, a normal subgroup (also known as an invariant subgroup or self-conjugate subgroup) is a subgroup that is invariant under conjugation by members of the group of which it is a part. In other words, a subgroup N of the group ...
) are equally useful in practice; one introduces a theorem stating an equivalence of more than two statements with TFAE.
;
transport of structure: It is often the case that two are shown to be equivalent in some way, and that one of them is endowed with additional structure. Using the equivalence, we may define such a structure on the second object as well, via ''transport of structure''. For example, any two
vector space
In mathematics and physics, a vector space (also called a linear space) is a set (mathematics), set whose elements, often called vector (mathematics and physics), ''vectors'', can be added together and multiplied ("scaled") by numbers called sc ...
s of the same
dimension
In physics and mathematics, the dimension of a mathematical space (or object) is informally defined as the minimum number of coordinates needed to specify any point within it. Thus, a line has a dimension of one (1D) because only one coo ...
are
isomorphic; if one of them is given an
inner product and if we fix a particular isomorphism, then we may define an inner product on the other space by ''factoring through'' the isomorphism.
;
without (any) loss of generality (WLOG, WOLOG, WALOG), we may assume (WMA): Sometimes a
proposition
A proposition is a statement that can be either true or false. It is a central concept in the philosophy of language, semantics, logic, and related fields. Propositions are the object s denoted by declarative sentences; for example, "The sky ...
can be more easily proved with additional assumptions on the objects it concerns. If the proposition as stated follows from this modified one with a simple and minimal explanation (for example, if the remaining special cases are identical but for notation), then the modified assumptions are introduced with this phrase and the altered proposition is proved.
Proof techniques
Mathematicians have several phrases to describe proofs or proof techniques. These are often used as hints for filling in tedious details.
; angle chasing: Used to describe a geometrical proof that involves finding relationships between the various angles in a diagram.
;
back-of-the-envelope calculation: An informal computation omitting much rigor without sacrificing correctness. Often this computation is "proof of concept" and treats only an accessible special case.
; brute force: Rather than finding underlying principles or patterns, this is a method where one would evaluate as many cases as needed to sufficiently prove or provide convincing evidence that the thing in question is true. Sometimes this involves evaluating every possible case (where it is also known as
proof by exhaustion).
; by example: A ''proof by example'' is an argument whereby a statement is not proved but instead illustrated by an example. If done well, the specific example would easily generalize to a general proof.
; by inspection: A rhetorical shortcut made by authors who invite the reader to verify, at a glance, the correctness of a proposed expression or deduction. If an expression can be evaluated by straightforward application of simple techniques and without recourse to extended calculation or general theory, then it can be evaluated ''by inspection''. It is also applied to solving equations; for example to find roots of a
quadratic equation
In mathematics, a quadratic equation () is an equation that can be rearranged in standard form as
ax^2 + bx + c = 0\,,
where the variable (mathematics), variable represents an unknown number, and , , and represent known numbers, where . (If and ...
by inspection is to 'notice' them, or mentally check them. 'By inspection' can play a kind of ''
gestalt'' role: the answer or solution simply clicks into place.
;
by intimidation: Style of proof where claims believed by the author to be easily verifiable are labelled as 'obvious' or 'trivial', which often results in the reader being confused.
; clearly, can be easily shown: A term which shortcuts around calculation the mathematician perceives to be tedious or routine, accessible to any member of the audience with the necessary expertise in the field;
Laplace used ''obvious'' (
French: ''évident'').
; complete intuition : commonly reserved for jokes (puns on
complete induction).
;
diagram chasing:
[Numerous examples can be found in , for example on p. 100.] Given a
commutative diagram of objects and morphisms between them, if one wishes to prove some property of the morphisms (such as
injectivity) which can be stated in terms of
elements, then the proof can proceed by tracing the path of elements of various objects around the diagram as successive morphisms are applied to it. That is, one ''chases'' elements around the diagram, or does a ''diagram chase''.
;
handwaving: A non-technique of proof mostly employed in lectures, where formal argument is not strictly necessary. It proceeds by omission of details or even significant ingredients, and is merely a plausibility argument.
; in general: In a context not requiring rigor, this phrase often appears as a labor-saving device when the technical details of a complete argument would outweigh the conceptual benefits. The author gives a proof in a simple enough case that the computations are reasonable, and then indicates that "in general" the proof is similar.
; index battle: For proofs involving objects with multiple indices which can be solved by going to the bottom (if anyone wishes to take up the effort). Similar to diagram chasing.
; morally true: Used to indicate that the speaker believes a statement ''should'' be true, given their mathematical experience, even though a proof has not yet been put forward. As a variation, the statement may in fact be false, but instead provide a slogan for or illustration of a correct principle.
Hasse's
local-global principle is a particularly influential example of this.
; obviously: See ''
clearly''.
; the proof is left as an exercise to the reader: Usually applied to a claim within a larger proof when the proof of that claim can be produced routinely by any member of the audience with the necessary expertise, but is not so simple as to be ''obvious''.
;
trivial: Similar to ''clearly''. A concept is trivial if it holds by definition, is an immediate
corollary to a known statement, or is a simple special case of a more general concept.
Miscellaneous
This section features terms used across different areas in
mathematics
Mathematics is a field of study that discovers and organizes methods, Mathematical theory, theories and theorems that are developed and Mathematical proof, proved for the needs of empirical sciences and mathematics itself. There are many ar ...
, or terms that do not typically appear in more specialized glossaries. For the terms used only in some specific areas of mathematics, see glossaries in
:Glossaries of mathematics.
B
C
D
F
I
M
P
S
See also
*
Glossary of areas of mathematics
*
List of mathematical constants
*
List of mathematical symbols
*
:Mathematical terminology
Notes
References
*.
* .
* (Part
Ian
II.
*.
*.
*.
*.
*.
* .
*.
*{{citation
, title = The Seventeen Provers of the World
, editor-last = Wiedijk
, editor-first = Freek
, year = 2006
, publisher = Birkhäuser
, isbn = 978-3-540-30704-4
, url-access = registration
, url = https://archive.org/details/seventeenprovers00free
.
Bibliography
*''
Encyclopedia of Mathematics''
Jargon
Wikipedia glossaries using description lists