The conditions
Let be a formal theory of arithmetic with a formalized provability predicate , which is expressed as a formula of with one free number variable. For each formula in the theory, let be the Gödel number of . The Hilbert–Bernays provability conditions are: # If proves a sentence then proves . # For every sentence , proves # proves that and imply Note that is predicate of numbers, and it is a provability predicate in the sense that the intended interpretation of is that there exists a number that codes for a proof of . Formally what is required of is the above three conditions. In the more concise notation ofUse in proving Gödel's incompleteness theorems
The Hilbert–Bernays provability conditions, combined with theProving Godel's first incompleteness theorem
For the first theorem only the first and third conditions are needed. The condition that is ω-consistent is generalized by the condition that if for every formula , if proves , then proves . Note that this indeed holds for an -consistent because means that there is a number coding for the proof of , and if is -consistent then going through all natural numbers one can actually find such a particular number , and then one can use to construct an actual proof of in . Suppose T could have proven . We then would have the following theorems in : # # (by construction of and theorem 1) # (by condition no. 1 and theorem 1) Thus proves both and . But if is consistent, this is impossible, and we are forced to conclude that does not prove . Now let us suppose could have proven . We then would have the following theorems in : # # (by construction of and theorem 1) # (by ω-consistency) Thus proves both and . But if is consistent, this is impossible, and we are forced to conclude that does not prove . To conclude, can prove neither nor .Using Rosser's trick
Using Rosser's trick, one needs not assume that is -consistent. However, one would need to show that the first and third provability conditions holds for , Rosser's provability predicate, rather than for the naive provability predicate Prov. This follows from the fact that for every formula , holds if and only if holds. An additional condition used is that proves that implies . This condition holds for every that includes logic and very basic arithmetics (as elaborated in Rosser's trick#The Rosser sentence). Using Rosser's trick, is defined using Rosser's provability predicate, instead of the naive provability predicate. The first part of the proof remains unchanged, except that the provability predicate is replaced with Rosser's provability predicate there, too. The second part of the proof no longer uses ω-consistency, and is changed to the following: Suppose could have proven . We then would have the following theorems in : # # (by construction of and theorem 1) # (by theorem 2 and the additional condition following the definition of Rosser's provability predicate) # (by condition no. 1 and theorem 1) Thus proves both and . But if is consistent, this is impossible, and we are forced to conclude that does not prove .The second theorem
We assume that proves its own consistency, i.e. that: :. For every formula : : (by negation elimination) It is possible to show by using condition no. 1 on the latter theorem, followed by repeated use of condition no. 3, that: : And using proving its own consistency it follows that: : We now use this to show that is not consistent: # (following proving its own consistency, with ) # (by construction of ) # (by condition no. 1 and theorem 2) # (by condition no. 3 and theorem 3) # (by theorems 1 and 4) # (by condition no. 2) # (by theorems 5 and 6) # (by construction of ) # (by theorems 7 and 8) # (by condition 1 and theorem 9) Thus proves both and , hence is inconsistent.References
* Smith, Peter (2007). ''An introduction to Gödel's incompleteness theorems''. Cambridge University Press. {{DEFAULTSORT:Hilbert-Bernays provability conditions Mathematical logic Provability logic