In
mathematics
Mathematics is a field of study that discovers and organizes methods, Mathematical theory, theories and theorems that are developed and Mathematical proof, proved for the needs of empirical sciences and mathematics itself. There are many ar ...
, specifically
set theory
Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies Set (mathematics), sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory – as a branch of mathema ...
, the continuum hypothesis (abbreviated CH) is a hypothesis about the possible sizes of
infinite set
In set theory, an infinite set is a set that is not a finite set. Infinite sets may be countable or uncountable.
Properties
The set of natural numbers (whose existence is postulated by the axiom of infinity) is infinite. It is the only set ...
s. It states:
Or equivalently:
In
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory
In set theory, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, named after mathematicians Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, is an axiomatic system that was proposed in the early twentieth century in order to formulate a theory of sets free of paradoxes suc ...
with the
axiom of choice
In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from e ...
(ZFC), this is equivalent to the following equation in
aleph number
In mathematics, particularly in set theory, the aleph numbers are a sequence of numbers used to represent the cardinality (or size) of infinite sets. They were introduced by the mathematician Georg Cantor and are named after the symbol he used t ...
s:
, or even shorter with
beth number
In mathematics, particularly in set theory, the beth numbers are a certain sequence of infinite cardinal numbers (also known as transfinite numbers), conventionally written \beth_0, \beth_1, \beth_2, \beth_3, \dots, where \beth is the Hebrew lett ...
s:
.
The continuum hypothesis was advanced by
Georg Cantor
Georg Ferdinand Ludwig Philipp Cantor ( ; ; – 6 January 1918) was a mathematician who played a pivotal role in the creation of set theory, which has become a foundations of mathematics, fundamental theory in mathematics. Cantor establi ...
in 1878, and establishing its truth or falsehood is the first of
Hilbert's 23 problems presented in 1900. The answer to this problem is
independent of ZFC, so that either the continuum hypothesis or its negation can be added as an axiom to ZFC set theory, with the resulting theory being consistent if and only if ZFC is consistent. This independence was proved in 1963 by
Paul Cohen, complementing earlier work by
Kurt Gödel
Kurt Friedrich Gödel ( ; ; April 28, 1906 – January 14, 1978) was a logician, mathematician, and philosopher. Considered along with Aristotle and Gottlob Frege to be one of the most significant logicians in history, Gödel profoundly ...
in 1940.
The name of the hypothesis comes from the term ''
continuum'' for the real numbers.
History
Cantor believed the continuum hypothesis to be true and for many years tried in vain to prove it. It became the first on David Hilbert's
list of important open questions that was presented at the
International Congress of Mathematicians
The International Congress of Mathematicians (ICM) is the largest conference for the topic of mathematics. It meets once every four years, hosted by the International Mathematical Union (IMU).
The Fields Medals, the IMU Abacus Medal (known before ...
in the year 1900 in Paris.
Axiomatic set theory
Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies Set (mathematics), sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory – as a branch of mathema ...
was at that point not yet formulated.
Kurt Gödel
Kurt Friedrich Gödel ( ; ; April 28, 1906 – January 14, 1978) was a logician, mathematician, and philosopher. Considered along with Aristotle and Gottlob Frege to be one of the most significant logicians in history, Gödel profoundly ...
proved in 1940 that the negation of the continuum hypothesis, i.e., the existence of a set with intermediate cardinality, could not be proved in standard set theory. The second half of the independence of the continuum hypothesis – i.e., unprovability of the nonexistence of an intermediate-sized set – was proved in 1963 by
Paul Cohen.
Cardinality of infinite sets
Two sets are said to have the same ''
cardinality
The thumb is the first digit of the hand, next to the index finger. When a person is standing in the medical anatomical position (where the palm is facing to the front), the thumb is the outermost digit. The Medical Latin English noun for thum ...
'' or ''
cardinal number
In mathematics, a cardinal number, or cardinal for short, is what is commonly called the number of elements of a set. In the case of a finite set, its cardinal number, or cardinality is therefore a natural number. For dealing with the cas ...
'' if there exists a
bijection
In mathematics, a bijection, bijective function, or one-to-one correspondence is a function between two sets such that each element of the second set (the codomain) is the image of exactly one element of the first set (the domain). Equival ...
(a one-to-one correspondence) between them. Intuitively, for two sets
and
to have the same cardinality means that it is possible to "pair off" elements of
with elements of
in such a fashion that every element of
is paired off with exactly one element of
and vice versa. Hence, the set
has the same cardinality as
despite the sets themselves containing different elements.
With infinite sets such as the set of
integer
An integer is the number zero (0), a positive natural number (1, 2, 3, ...), or the negation of a positive natural number (−1, −2, −3, ...). The negations or additive inverses of the positive natural numbers are referred to as negative in ...
s or
rational number
In mathematics, a rational number is a number that can be expressed as the quotient or fraction of two integers, a numerator and a non-zero denominator . For example, is a rational number, as is every integer (for example,
The set of all ...
s, the existence of a bijection between two sets becomes more difficult to demonstrate. The rational numbers
seemingly form a counterexample to the continuum hypothesis: the integers form a proper subset of the rationals, which themselves form a proper subset of the reals, so intuitively, there are more rational numbers than integers and more real numbers than rational numbers. However, this intuitive analysis is flawed since it does not take into account the fact that all three sets are
infinite. Perhaps more importantly, it in fact conflates the concept of "size" of the set
with the order or topological structure placed on it. In fact, it turns out the rational numbers can actually be placed in one-to-one correspondence with the integers, and therefore the set of rational numbers is the same size (''cardinality'') as the set of integers: they are both
countable set
In mathematics, a set is countable if either it is finite or it can be made in one to one correspondence with the set of natural numbers. Equivalently, a set is ''countable'' if there exists an injective function from it into the natural numbe ...
s.
Cantor gave two proofs that the cardinality of the set of
integer
An integer is the number zero (0), a positive natural number (1, 2, 3, ...), or the negation of a positive natural number (−1, −2, −3, ...). The negations or additive inverses of the positive natural numbers are referred to as negative in ...
s is strictly smaller than that of the set of
real number
In mathematics, a real number is a number that can be used to measure a continuous one- dimensional quantity such as a duration or temperature. Here, ''continuous'' means that pairs of values can have arbitrarily small differences. Every re ...
s (see
Cantor's first uncountability proof and
Cantor's diagonal argument
Cantor's diagonal argument (among various similar namesthe diagonalisation argument, the diagonal slash argument, the anti-diagonal argument, the diagonal method, and Cantor's diagonalization proof) is a mathematical proof that there are infin ...
). His proofs, however, give no indication of the extent to which the cardinality of the integers is less than that of the real numbers. Cantor proposed the continuum hypothesis as a possible solution to this question.
In simple terms, the Continuum Hypothesis (CH) states that the set of real numbers has minimal possible cardinality which is greater than the cardinality of the set of integers. That is, every set
of real numbers can either be mapped one-to-one into the integers or the real numbers can be mapped one-to-one into
. Since the real numbers are
equinumerous with the
powerset
In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is po ...
of the integers, i.e.
, CH can be restated as follows:
Assuming the
axiom of choice
In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from e ...
, there is a unique smallest cardinal number
greater than
, and the continuum hypothesis is in turn equivalent to the equality
.
Independence from ZFC
The independence of the continuum hypothesis (CH) from
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory
In set theory, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, named after mathematicians Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, is an axiomatic system that was proposed in the early twentieth century in order to formulate a theory of sets free of paradoxes suc ...
(ZF) follows from combined work of
Kurt Gödel
Kurt Friedrich Gödel ( ; ; April 28, 1906 – January 14, 1978) was a logician, mathematician, and philosopher. Considered along with Aristotle and Gottlob Frege to be one of the most significant logicians in history, Gödel profoundly ...
and
Paul Cohen.
Gödel
showed that CH cannot be disproved from ZF, even if the
axiom of choice
In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from e ...
(AC) is adopted, i.e. from ZFC. Gödel's proof shows that both CH and AC hold in the
constructible universe
In mathematics, in set theory, the constructible universe (or Gödel's constructible universe), denoted by L, is a particular Class (set theory), class of Set (mathematics), sets that can be described entirely in terms of simpler sets. L is the un ...
, an
inner model of ZF set theory, assuming only the axioms of ZF. The existence of an inner model of ZF in which additional axioms hold shows that the additional axioms are (relatively)
consistent
In deductive logic, a consistent theory is one that does not lead to a logical contradiction. A theory T is consistent if there is no formula \varphi such that both \varphi and its negation \lnot\varphi are elements of the set of consequences ...
with ZF, provided ZF itself is consistent. The latter condition cannot be proved in ZF itself, due to
Gödel's incompleteness theorems
Gödel's incompleteness theorems are two theorems of mathematical logic that are concerned with the limits of in formal axiomatic theories. These results, published by Kurt Gödel in 1931, are important both in mathematical logic and in the phi ...
, but is widely believed to be true and can be proved in stronger set theories.
Cohen showed that CH cannot be proven from the ZFC axioms, completing the overall independence proof. To prove his result, Cohen developed the method of
forcing, which has become a standard tool in set theory. Essentially, this method begins with a model of ZF in which CH holds and constructs another model which contains more sets than the original in a way that CH does not hold in the new model. Cohen was awarded the
Fields Medal
The Fields Medal is a prize awarded to two, three, or four mathematicians under 40 years of age at the International Congress of Mathematicians, International Congress of the International Mathematical Union (IMU), a meeting that takes place e ...
in 1966 for his proof.
Cohen's independence proof shows that CH is independent of ZFC. Further research has shown that CH is independent of all known ''
large cardinal axioms'' in the context of ZFC. Moreover, it has been shown that the
cardinality of the continuum
In set theory, the cardinality of the continuum is the cardinality or "size" of the set of real numbers \mathbb R, sometimes called the continuum. It is an infinite cardinal number and is denoted by \bold\mathfrak c (lowercase Fraktur "c") or \ ...
can be any cardinal consistent with
Kőnig's theorem. A result of Solovay, proved shortly after Cohen's result on the independence of the continuum hypothesis, shows that in any model of ZFC, if
is a cardinal of uncountable
cofinality, then there is a forcing extension in which
. However, per Kőnig's theorem, it is not consistent to assume
is
or
or any cardinal with cofinality
.
The continuum hypothesis is closely related to
many statements in
analysis
Analysis (: analyses) is the process of breaking a complex topic or substance into smaller parts in order to gain a better understanding of it. The technique has been applied in the study of mathematics and logic since before Aristotle (38 ...
, point set
topology
Topology (from the Greek language, Greek words , and ) is the branch of mathematics concerned with the properties of a Mathematical object, geometric object that are preserved under Continuous function, continuous Deformation theory, deformat ...
and
measure theory
In mathematics, the concept of a measure is a generalization and formalization of geometrical measures (length, area, volume) and other common notions, such as magnitude (mathematics), magnitude, mass, and probability of events. These seemingl ...
. As a result of its independence, many substantial
conjecture
In mathematics, a conjecture is a conclusion or a proposition that is proffered on a tentative basis without proof. Some conjectures, such as the Riemann hypothesis or Fermat's conjecture (now a theorem, proven in 1995 by Andrew Wiles), ha ...
s in those fields have subsequently been shown to be independent as well.
The independence from ZFC means that proving or disproving the CH within ZFC is impossible. However, Gödel and Cohen's negative results are not universally accepted as disposing of all interest in the continuum hypothesis. The continuum hypothesis remains an active topic of research: see
Woodin and
Koellner for an overview of the current research status.
The continuum hypothesis and the
axiom of choice
In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from e ...
were among the first genuinely mathematical statements shown to be independent of ZF set theory. Although the existence of some statements independent of ZFC had already been known more than two decades prior: for example, assuming
good soundness properties and the consistency of ZFC,
Gödel's incompleteness theorems
Gödel's incompleteness theorems are two theorems of mathematical logic that are concerned with the limits of in formal axiomatic theories. These results, published by Kurt Gödel in 1931, are important both in mathematical logic and in the phi ...
published in 1931 establish that there is a formal statement Con(ZFC) (one for each appropriate
Gödel numbering scheme) expressing the consistency of ZFC, that is also independent of it. The latter independence result indeed holds for many theories.
Arguments ''for'' and ''against'' the continuum hypothesis
Gödel believed that CH is false, and that his proof that CH is consistent with ZFC only shows that the
Zermelo–Fraenkel axioms do not adequately characterize the universe of sets. Gödel was a
Platonist
Platonism is the philosophy of Plato and philosophical systems closely derived from it, though contemporary Platonists do not necessarily accept all doctrines of Plato. Platonism has had a profound effect on Western thought. At the most fundam ...
and therefore had no problems with asserting the truth and falsehood of statements independent of their provability. Cohen, though a
formalist, also tended towards rejecting CH.
Historically, mathematicians who favored a "rich" and "large"
universe
The universe is all of space and time and their contents. It comprises all of existence, any fundamental interaction, physical process and physical constant, and therefore all forms of matter and energy, and the structures they form, from s ...
of sets were against CH, while those favoring a "neat" and "controllable" universe favored CH. Parallel arguments were made for and against the
axiom of constructibility, which implies CH. More recently,
Matthew Foreman has pointed out that
ontological maximalism can actually be used to argue in favor of CH, because among models that have the same reals, models with "more" sets of reals have a better chance of satisfying CH.
Another viewpoint is that the conception of set is not specific enough to determine whether CH is true or false. This viewpoint was advanced as early as 1923 by
Skolem, even before Gödel's first incompleteness theorem. Skolem argued on the basis of what is now known as
Skolem's paradox, and it was later supported by the independence of CH from the axioms of ZFC since these axioms are enough to establish the elementary properties of sets and cardinalities. In order to argue against this viewpoint, it would be sufficient to demonstrate new axioms that are supported by intuition and resolve CH in one direction or another. Although the
axiom of constructibility does resolve CH, it is not generally considered to be intuitively true any more than CH is generally considered to be false.
At least two other axioms have been proposed that have implications for the continuum hypothesis, although these axioms have not currently found wide acceptance in the mathematical community. In 1986, Chris Freiling presented an argument against CH by showing that the negation of CH is equivalent to
Freiling's axiom of symmetry, a statement derived by arguing from particular intuitions about
probabilities
Probability is a branch of mathematics and statistics concerning Event (probability theory), events and numerical descriptions of how likely they are to occur. The probability of an event is a number between 0 and 1; the larger the probab ...
. Freiling believes this axiom is "intuitively clear" but others have disagreed.
A difficult argument against CH developed by
W. Hugh Woodin has attracted considerable attention since the year 2000.
Foreman does not reject Woodin's argument outright but urges caution. Woodin proposed a new hypothesis that he labeled the , or "Star axiom". The Star axiom would imply that
is
, thus falsifying CH. The Star axiom was bolstered by an independent May 2021 proof showing the Star axiom can be derived from a variation of
Martin's maximum. However, Woodin stated in the 2010s that he now instead believes CH to be true, based on his belief in his new "ultimate L" conjecture.
Solomon Feferman
Solomon Feferman (December 13, 1928July 26, 2016) was an American philosopher and mathematician who worked in mathematical logic. In addition to his prolific technical work in proof theory, computability theory, and set theory, he was known for h ...
argued that CH is not a definite mathematical problem. He proposed a theory of "definiteness" using a semi-intuitionistic subsystem of ZF that accepts
classical logic
Classical logic (or standard logic) or Frege–Russell logic is the intensively studied and most widely used class of deductive logic. Classical logic has had much influence on analytic philosophy.
Characteristics
Each logical system in this c ...
for bounded quantifiers but uses
intuitionistic logic
Intuitionistic logic, sometimes more generally called constructive logic, refers to systems of symbolic logic that differ from the systems used for classical logic by more closely mirroring the notion of constructive proof. In particular, systems ...
for unbounded ones, and suggested that a proposition
is mathematically "definite" if the semi-intuitionistic theory can prove
. He conjectured that CH is not definite according to this notion, and proposed that CH should, therefore, be considered not to have a truth value.
Peter Koellner wrote a critical commentary on Feferman's article.
Joel David Hamkins proposes a
multiverse approach to set theory and argues that "the continuum hypothesis is settled on the multiverse view by our extensive knowledge about how it behaves in the multiverse, and, as a result, it can no longer be settled in the manner formerly hoped for". In a related vein,
Saharon Shelah wrote that he does "not agree with the pure Platonic view that the interesting problems in set theory can be decided, that we just have to discover the additional axiom. My mental picture is that we have many possible set theories, all conforming to ZFC".
Generalized continuum hypothesis
The ''generalized continuum hypothesis'' (GCH) states that if an infinite set's cardinality lies between that of an infinite set and that of the
power set
In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is po ...
of , then it has the same cardinality as either or
. That is, for any
infinite cardinal
there is no cardinal
such that
. GCH is equivalent to:
(occasionally called ''Cantor's aleph hypothesis'').
The
beth number
In mathematics, particularly in set theory, the beth numbers are a certain sequence of infinite cardinal numbers (also known as transfinite numbers), conventionally written \beth_0, \beth_1, \beth_2, \beth_3, \dots, where \beth is the Hebrew lett ...
s provide an alternative notation for this condition:
for every ordinal
. The continuum hypothesis is the special case for the ordinal
. GCH was first suggested by
Philip Jourdain
Philip Edward Bertrand Jourdain (16 October 1879 – 1 October 1919) was a British mathematician, logician and follower of Bertrand Russell.
Background
He was born in Ashbourne in Derbyshire* one of a large family belonging to Emily Clay and ...
. For the early history of GCH, see Moore.
Like CH, GCH is also independent of ZFC, but
Sierpiński proved that ZF + GCH implies the
axiom of choice
In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from e ...
(AC) (and therefore the negation of the
axiom of determinacy
In mathematics, the axiom of determinacy (abbreviated as AD) is a possible axiom for set theory introduced by Jan Mycielski and Hugo Steinhaus in 1962. It refers to certain two-person topological games of length ω. AD states that every game o ...
, AD), so choice and GCH are not independent in ZF; there are no models of ZF in which GCH holds and AC fails. To prove this, Sierpiński showed GCH implies that every cardinality n is smaller than some
aleph number
In mathematics, particularly in set theory, the aleph numbers are a sequence of numbers used to represent the cardinality (or size) of infinite sets. They were introduced by the mathematician Georg Cantor and are named after the symbol he used t ...
, and thus can be ordered. This is done by showing that n is smaller than
which is smaller than its own
Hartogs number—this uses the equality
; for the full proof, see Gillman.
Kurt Gödel
Kurt Friedrich Gödel ( ; ; April 28, 1906 – January 14, 1978) was a logician, mathematician, and philosopher. Considered along with Aristotle and Gottlob Frege to be one of the most significant logicians in history, Gödel profoundly ...
showed that GCH is a consequence of ZF +
V=L (the axiom that every set is constructible relative to the ordinals), and is therefore consistent with ZFC. As GCH implies CH, Cohen's model in which CH fails is a model in which GCH fails, and thus GCH is not provable from ZFC. W. B. Easton used the method of forcing developed by Cohen to prove
Easton's theorem, which shows it is consistent with ZFC for arbitrarily large cardinals
to fail to satisfy
. Much later,
Foreman and
Woodin proved that (assuming the consistency of very large cardinals) it is consistent that
holds for every infinite cardinal
. Later Woodin extended this by showing the consistency of
for every Carmi Merimovich showed that, for each , it is consistent with ZFC that for each infinite cardinal , is the th successor of (assuming the consistency of some large cardinal axioms). On the other hand, László Patai proved that if is an ordinal and for each infinite cardinal , is the th successor of , then is finite.
For any infinite sets and , if there is an injection from to then there is an injection from subsets of to subsets of . Thus for any infinite cardinals and ,
. If and are finite, the stronger inequality
holds. GCH implies that this strict, stronger inequality holds for infinite cardinals as well as finite cardinals.
Implications of GCH for cardinal exponentiation
Although the generalized continuum hypothesis refers directly only to cardinal exponentiation with 2 as the base, one can deduce from it the values of cardinal exponentiation
in all cases. GCH implies that for ordinals and :
*
when ;
*
when and
, where cf is the
cofinality operation; and
*
when and
The first equality (when ) follows from:
while:
The third equality (when and
) follows from:
by
Kőnig's theorem, while:
See also
*
Absolute infinite
*
Beth number
In mathematics, particularly in set theory, the beth numbers are a certain sequence of infinite cardinal numbers (also known as transfinite numbers), conventionally written \beth_0, \beth_1, \beth_2, \beth_3, \dots, where \beth is the Hebrew lett ...
*
Cardinality
The thumb is the first digit of the hand, next to the index finger. When a person is standing in the medical anatomical position (where the palm is facing to the front), the thumb is the outermost digit. The Medical Latin English noun for thum ...
*
Ω-logic
*
Second continuum hypothesis
*
Wetzel's problem
References
*
Sources
*
Further reading
*
*
*
* Gödel, K.: ''What is Cantor's Continuum Problem?'', reprinted in Benacerraf and Putnam's collection ''Philosophy of Mathematics'', 2nd ed., Cambridge University Press, 1983. An outline of Gödel's arguments against CH.
* Martin, D. (1976). "Hilbert's first problem: the continuum hypothesis," in ''Mathematical Developments Arising from Hilbert's Problems,'' Proceedings of Symposia in Pure Mathematics XXVIII, F. Browder, editor. American Mathematical Society, 1976, pp. 81–92.
*
*
External links
*
{{DEFAULTSORT:Continuum Hypothesis
Forcing (mathematics)
Independence results
Basic concepts in infinite set theory
Hilbert's problems
Infinity
Hypotheses
Cardinal numbers