HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
mathematics Mathematics is a field of study that discovers and organizes methods, Mathematical theory, theories and theorems that are developed and Mathematical proof, proved for the needs of empirical sciences and mathematics itself. There are many ar ...
, in
set theory Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies Set (mathematics), sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory – as a branch of mathema ...
, the constructible universe (or Gödel's constructible universe), denoted by L, is a particular
class Class, Classes, or The Class may refer to: Common uses not otherwise categorized * Class (biology), a taxonomic rank * Class (knowledge representation), a collection of individuals or objects * Class (philosophy), an analytical concept used d ...
of sets that can be described entirely in terms of simpler sets. L is the union of the constructible hierarchy L_\alpha. It was introduced by
Kurt Gödel Kurt Friedrich Gödel ( ; ; April 28, 1906 – January 14, 1978) was a logician, mathematician, and philosopher. Considered along with Aristotle and Gottlob Frege to be one of the most significant logicians in history, Gödel profoundly ...
in his 1938 paper "The Consistency of the Axiom of Choice and of the Generalized Continuum-Hypothesis". In this paper, he proved that the constructible universe is an
inner model In set theory, a branch of mathematical logic, an inner model for a theory ''T'' is a substructure of a model ''M'' of a set theory that is both a model for ''T'' and contains all the ordinals of ''M''. Definition Let ''L'' = ⟨∈� ...
of ZF set theory (that is, of
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory In set theory, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, named after mathematicians Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, is an axiomatic system that was proposed in the early twentieth century in order to formulate a theory of sets free of paradoxes suc ...
with the
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from e ...
excluded), and also that the axiom of choice and the
generalized continuum hypothesis In mathematics, specifically set theory, the continuum hypothesis (abbreviated CH) is a hypothesis about the possible sizes of infinite sets. It states: Or equivalently: In Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC), this ...
are true in the constructible universe. This shows that both propositions are
consistent In deductive logic, a consistent theory is one that does not lead to a logical contradiction. A theory T is consistent if there is no formula \varphi such that both \varphi and its negation \lnot\varphi are elements of the set of consequences ...
with the basic
axiom An axiom, postulate, or assumption is a statement that is taken to be true, to serve as a premise or starting point for further reasoning and arguments. The word comes from the Ancient Greek word (), meaning 'that which is thought worthy or ...
s of set theory, if ZF itself is consistent. Since many other theorems only hold in systems in which one or both of the propositions is true, their consistency is an important result.


What ''L'' is

L can be thought of as being built in "stages" resembling the construction of the
von Neumann universe In set theory and related branches of mathematics, the von Neumann universe, or von Neumann hierarchy of sets, denoted by ''V'', is the class of hereditary well-founded sets. This collection, which is formalized by Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory ( ...
, V. The stages are indexed by ordinals. In von Neumann's universe, at a
successor Successor may refer to: * An entity that comes after another (see Succession (disambiguation)) Film and TV * ''The Successor'' (1996 film), a film including Laura Girling * The Successor (2023 film), a French drama film * ''The Successor'' ( ...
stage, one takes V_ to be the set of ''all'' subsets of the previous stage, V_\alpha. By contrast, in Gödel's constructible universe L, one uses ''only'' those subsets of the previous stage that are: *definable by a
formula In science, a formula is a concise way of expressing information symbolically, as in a mathematical formula or a ''chemical formula''. The informal use of the term ''formula'' in science refers to the general construct of a relationship betwe ...
in the
formal language In logic, mathematics, computer science, and linguistics, a formal language is a set of strings whose symbols are taken from a set called "alphabet". The alphabet of a formal language consists of symbols that concatenate into strings (also c ...
of set theory, *with parameters from the previous stage and, *with the quantifiers interpreted to range over the previous stage. By limiting oneself to sets defined only in terms of what has already been constructed, one ensures that the resulting sets will be constructed in a way that is independent of the peculiarities of the surrounding model of set theory and contained in any such model. Define the Def operator: \operatorname(X) := \Bigl\. L is defined by
transfinite recursion Transfinite induction is an extension of mathematical induction to well-ordered sets, for example to sets of ordinal numbers or cardinal numbers. Its correctness is a theorem of ZFC. Induction by cases Let P(\alpha) be a property defined for a ...
as follows: * L_0 := \varnothing. * L_ := \operatorname(L_\alpha). * If \lambda is a
limit ordinal In set theory, a limit ordinal is an ordinal number that is neither zero nor a successor ordinal. Alternatively, an ordinal λ is a limit ordinal if there is an ordinal less than λ, and whenever β is an ordinal less than λ, then there exists a ...
, then L_ := \bigcup_ L_. Here \alpha<\lambda means \alpha precedes \lambda. * L := \bigcup_ L_. Here Ord denotes the
class Class, Classes, or The Class may refer to: Common uses not otherwise categorized * Class (biology), a taxonomic rank * Class (knowledge representation), a collection of individuals or objects * Class (philosophy), an analytical concept used d ...
of all ordinals. If z is an element of L_\alpha, then z=\\in\textrm(L_\alpha)=L_. So L_\alpha is a subset of L_, which is a subset of the
power set In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is po ...
of L_\alpha. Consequently, this is a tower of nested
transitive set In set theory, a branch of mathematics, a set A is called transitive if either of the following equivalent conditions holds: * whenever x \in A, and y \in x, then y \in A. * whenever x \in A, and x is not an urelement, then x is a subset of A. S ...
s. But L itself is a
proper class Proper may refer to: Mathematics * Proper map, in topology, a property of continuous function between topological spaces, if inverse images of compact subsets are compact * Proper morphism, in algebraic geometry, an analogue of a proper map f ...
. The elements of L are called "constructible" sets; and L itself is the "constructible universe". The "
axiom of constructibility The axiom of constructibility is a possible axiom for set theory in mathematics that asserts that every set is constructible. The axiom is usually written as ''V'' = ''L''. The axiom, first investigated by Kurt Gödel, is inconsistent with the pr ...
", aka "V = L", says that every set (of V) is constructible, i.e. in L.


Additional facts about the sets Lα

An equivalent definition for L_\alpha is: For any finite ordinal n, the sets L_n and V_n are the same (whether V equals L or not), and thus L_\omega = V_\omega: their elements are exactly the
hereditarily finite set In mathematics and set theory, hereditarily finite sets are defined as finite sets whose elements are all hereditarily finite sets. In other words, the set itself is finite, and all of its elements are finite sets, recursively all the way down to t ...
s. Equality beyond this point does not hold. Even in models of ZFC in which V equals L, L_ is a proper subset of V_, and thereafter L_ is a proper subset of the power set of L_\alpha for all \alpha>\omega. On the other hand, V = L does imply that V_\alpha equals L_\alpha if \alpha=\omega_\alpha, for example if \alpha is inaccessible. More generally, V = L implies H_\alpha = L_\alpha for all infinite cardinals \alpha. If \alpha is an infinite ordinal then there is a
bijection In mathematics, a bijection, bijective function, or one-to-one correspondence is a function between two sets such that each element of the second set (the codomain) is the image of exactly one element of the first set (the domain). Equival ...
between L_\alpha and \alpha, and the bijection is constructible. So these sets are
equinumerous In mathematics, two sets or classes ''A'' and ''B'' are equinumerous if there exists a one-to-one correspondence (or bijection) between them, that is, if there exists a function from ''A'' to ''B'' such that for every element ''y'' of ''B'', ...
in any model of set theory that includes them. As defined above, \textrm(X) is the set of subsets of X defined by \Delta_0 formulas (with respect to the
Levy hierarchy Levy, Lévy or Levies may refer to: People * Levy (surname), people with the surname Levy or Lévy * Levy Adcock (born 1988), American football player * Levy Barent Cohen (1747–1808), Dutch-born British financier and community worker * Levy ...
, i.e., formulas of set theory containing only
bounded quantifiers In the study of formal theories in mathematical logic, bounded quantifiers (a.k.a. restricted quantifiers) are often included in a formal language in addition to the standard quantifiers "∀" and "∃". Bounded quantifiers differ from "∀" and " ...
) that use as parameters only X and its elements. Another definition, due to Gödel, characterizes each L_ as the intersection of the power set of L_\alpha with the closure of L_\alpha\cup\ under a collection of nine explicit functions, similar to
Gödel operation In mathematical set theory Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies Set (mathematics), sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory ...
s. This definition makes no reference to definability. All arithmetical subsets of \omega and relations on \omega belong to L_ (because the arithmetic definition gives one in L_). Conversely, any subset of \omega belonging to L_ is arithmetical (because elements of L_\omega can be coded by natural numbers in such a way that \in is definable, i.e., arithmetic). On the other hand, L_ already contains certain non-arithmetical subsets of \omega, such as the set of (natural numbers coding) true arithmetical statements (this can be defined from L_ so it is in L_). All hyperarithmetical subsets of \omega and relations on \omega belong to L_ (where \omega_1^ stands for the
Church–Kleene ordinal In mathematics, particularly set theory, non-recursive ordinals are large countable ordinals greater than all the recursive ordinals, and therefore can not be expressed using recursive ordinal notations. The Church–Kleene ordinal and variant ...
), and conversely any subset of \omega that belongs to L_ is hyperarithmetical.


L is a standard inner model of ZFC

(L,\in) is a standard model, i.e. L is a transitive class and the interpretation uses the real element relationship, so it is
well-founded In mathematics, a binary relation is called well-founded (or wellfounded or foundational) on a set (mathematics), set or, more generally, a Class (set theory), class if every non-empty subset has a minimal element with respect to ; that is, t ...
. L is an inner model, i.e. it contains all the ordinal numbers of V and it has no "extra" sets beyond those in V. However L might be strictly a subclass of V. L is a model of ZFC, which means that it satisfies the following
axiom An axiom, postulate, or assumption is a statement that is taken to be true, to serve as a premise or starting point for further reasoning and arguments. The word comes from the Ancient Greek word (), meaning 'that which is thought worthy or ...
s: *
Axiom of regularity In mathematics, the axiom of regularity (also known as the axiom of foundation) is an axiom of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory that states that every Empty set, non-empty Set (mathematics), set ''A'' contains an element that is Disjoint sets, disjoin ...
: Every non-empty set x contains some element y such that x and y are disjoint sets. : (L,\in) is a substructure of (V,\in), which is well founded, so L is well founded. In particular, if y\in x\in L, then by the transitivity of L, y\in L. If we use this same y as in V, then it is still disjoint from x because we are using the same element relation and no new sets were added. *
Axiom of extensionality The axiom of extensionality, also called the axiom of extent, is an axiom used in many forms of axiomatic set theory, such as Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory. The axiom defines what a Set (mathematics), set is. Informally, the axiom means that the ...
: Two sets are the same if they have the same elements. : If x and y are in L and they have the same elements in L, then by L's transitivity, they have the same elements (in V). So they are equal (in V and thus in L). *
Axiom of empty set In axiomatic set theory, the axiom of empty set, also called the axiom of null set and the axiom of existence, is a statement that asserts the existence of a set with no elements. It is an axiom of Kripke–Platek set theory and the variant of g ...
: is a set. : \=L_0=\, which is in L_1. So \\in L. Since the element relation is the same and no new elements were added, this is the empty set of L. *
Axiom of pairing In axiomatic set theory and the branches of logic, mathematics, and computer science that use it, the axiom of pairing is one of the axioms of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory. It was introduced by as a special case of his axiom of elementary sets ...
: If x, y are sets, then \ is a set. : If x\in L and y\in L, then there is some ordinal \alpha such that x\in L_\alpha and y\in L_\alpha. Then \ = \ \in L_. Thus \\in L and it has the same meaning for L as for V. *
Axiom of union An axiom, postulate, or assumption is a statement (logic), statement that is taken to be truth, true, to serve as a premise or starting point for further reasoning and arguments. The word comes from the Ancient Greek word (), meaning 'that whi ...
: For any set x there is a set y whose elements are precisely the elements of the elements of x. : If x\in L_\alpha, then its elements are in L_\alpha and their elements are also in L_\alpha. So y is a subset of L_\alpha. Then y = \ \in L_. Thus y\in L. *
Axiom of infinity In axiomatic set theory and the branches of mathematics and philosophy that use it, the axiom of infinity is one of the axioms of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory. It guarantees the existence of at least one infinite set, namely a set containing ...
: There exists a set x such that \varnothing is in x and whenever y is in x, so is the union y\cup\. :
Transfinite induction Transfinite induction is an extension of mathematical induction to well-ordered sets, for example to sets of ordinal numbers or cardinal numbers. Its correctness is a theorem of ZFC. Induction by cases Let P(\alpha) be a property defined for a ...
can be used to show each ordinal \alpha is in L_. In particular, \omega \in L_ and thus \omega \in L. *
Axiom of separation In many popular versions of axiomatic set theory, the axiom schema of specification, also known as the axiom schema of separation (''Aussonderungsaxiom''), subset axiom, axiom of class construction, or axiom schema of restricted comprehension is ...
: Given any set S and any proposition P(x,z_1,\ldots,z_n), \ is a set. : By induction on subformulas of P, one can show that there is an \alpha such that L_\alpha contains S and z_1,\ldots,z_n and (P is true in L_\alpha if and only if P is true in L), the latter is called the "
reflection principle In set theory, a branch of mathematics, a reflection principle says that it is possible to find sets that, with respect to any given property, resemble the class of all sets. There are several different forms of the reflection principle depending ...
"). So \ = \ \in L_. Thus the subset is in L.P. Odifreddi, ''Classical Recursion Theory'', pp.427. Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics *
Axiom of replacement In set theory, the axiom schema of replacement is a schema of axioms in Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (ZF) that asserts that the image of any set under any definable mapping is also a set. It is necessary for the construction of certain infinite ...
: Given any set S and any mapping (formally defined as a proposition P(x,y) where P(x,y) and P(x,z) implies y = z), \ is a set. : Let Q(x,y) be the formula that relativizes P to L, i.e. all quantifiers in P are restricted to L. Q is a much more complex formula than Q, but it is still a finite formula, and since P was a mapping over L, Q must be a mapping over V; thus we can apply replacement in V to Q. So \ = \ is a set in V and a subclass of L. Again using the axiom of replacement in V, we can show that there must be an \alpha such that this set is a subset of L_\alpha \in L_. Then one can use the axiom of separation in L to finish showing that it is an element of L *
Axiom of power set In mathematics, the axiom of power set is one of the Zermelo–Fraenkel axioms of axiomatic set theory. It guarantees for every set x the existence of a set \mathcal(x), the power set of x, consisting precisely of the subsets of x. By the axio ...
: For any set x there exists a set y, such that the elements of y are precisely the subsets of x. : In general, some subsets of a set in L will not be in L So the whole power set of a set in L will usually not be in L. What we need here is to show that the intersection of the power set with L ''is'' in L. Use replacement in V to show that there is an α such that the intersection is a subset of L_\alpha. Then the intersection is \ \in L_. Thus the required set is in L. *
Axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from e ...
: Given a set x of mutually disjoint nonempty sets, there is a set y (a choice set for x) containing exactly one element from each member of x. : One can show that there is a definable well-ordering of , in particular based on ordering all sets in L by their definitions and by the rank they appear at. So one chooses the least element of each member of x to form y using the axioms of union and separation in L Notice that the proof that L is a model of ZFC only requires that V be a model of ZF, i.e. we do ''not'' assume that the axiom of choice holds in V.


L is absolute and minimal

If W is any standard model of ZF sharing the same ordinals as V, then the L defined in W is the same as the L defined in V. In particular, L_\alpha is the same in W and V, for any ordinal \alpha. And the same formulas and parameters in \mathrm(L_\alpha) produce the same constructible sets in L_. Furthermore, since L is a subclass of V and, similarly, L is a subclass of W, L is the smallest class containing all the ordinals that is an
inner model In set theory, a branch of mathematical logic, an inner model for a theory ''T'' is a substructure of a model ''M'' of a set theory that is both a model for ''T'' and contains all the ordinals of ''M''. Definition Let ''L'' = ⟨∈� ...
of ZF. Indeed, L is the intersection of all such classes. If there is a ''set'' W in V that is an inner model of ZF, and the ordinal \kappa is the set of ordinals that occur in W, then L_\kappa is the L of W. If there is a set that is a standard model of ZF, then the smallest such set is such a L_\kappa. This set is called the minimal model of ZFC. Using the downward
Löwenheim–Skolem theorem In mathematical logic, the Löwenheim–Skolem theorem is a theorem on the existence and cardinality of models, named after Leopold Löwenheim and Thoralf Skolem. The precise formulation is given below. It implies that if a countable first-order ...
, one can show that the minimal model (if it exists) is a countable set. Of course, any consistent theory must have a model, so even within the minimal model of set theory there are sets that are models of ZF (assuming ZF is consistent). However, those set models are non-standard. In particular, they do not use the normal element relation and they are not well founded. Because both "L constructed within L" and "V constructed within L" result in the real L, and both the L of L_\kappa and the V of L_\kappa are the real L_\kappa, we get that V=L is true in L and in any L_\kappa that is a model of ZF. However, V=L does not hold in any other standard model of ZF.


L and large cardinals

Since \mathrm\subset L\subseteq V, properties of ordinals that depend on the absence of a function or other structure (i.e. \Pi^_1 formulas) are preserved when going down from V to L. Hence
initial ordinal The von Neumann cardinal assignment is a cardinal assignment that uses ordinal numbers. For a well-orderable set ''U'', we define its cardinal number to be the smallest ordinal number equinumerous to ''U'', using the von Neumann definition of an ...
s of cardinals remain initial in L. Regular ordinals remain regular in L. Weak
limit cardinal In mathematics, limit cardinals are certain cardinal numbers. A cardinal number ''λ'' is a weak limit cardinal if ''λ'' is neither a successor cardinal nor zero. This means that one cannot "reach" ''λ'' from another cardinal by repeated success ...
s become strong limit cardinals in L because the
generalized continuum hypothesis In mathematics, specifically set theory, the continuum hypothesis (abbreviated CH) is a hypothesis about the possible sizes of infinite sets. It states: Or equivalently: In Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC), this ...
holds in L. Weakly
inaccessible cardinal In set theory, a cardinal number is a strongly inaccessible cardinal if it is uncountable, regular, and a strong limit cardinal. A cardinal is a weakly inaccessible cardinal if it is uncountable, regular, and a weak limit cardinal. Since abou ...
s become strongly inaccessible. Weakly
Mahlo cardinal In mathematics, a Mahlo cardinal is a certain kind of large cardinal number. Mahlo cardinals were first described by . As with all large cardinals, none of these varieties of Mahlo cardinals can be proven to exist by ZFC (assuming ZFC is consi ...
s become strongly Mahlo. And more generally, any
large cardinal In the mathematical field of set theory, a large cardinal property is a certain kind of property of transfinite cardinal numbers. Cardinals with such properties are, as the name suggests, generally very "large" (for example, bigger than the least ...
property weaker than 0 (see the list of large cardinal properties) will be retained in L. However, 0^\sharp is false in L even if true in V. So all the large cardinals whose existence implies 0^\sharp cease to have those large cardinal properties, but retain the properties weaker than 0^\sharp which they also possess. For example,
measurable cardinal In mathematics, a measurable cardinal is a certain kind of large cardinal number. In order to define the concept, one introduces a two-valued measure (mathematics), measure on a cardinal ''κ'', or more generally on any set. For a cardinal ''κ'', ...
s cease to be measurable but remain Mahlo in L. If 0^\sharp holds in V, then there is a closed unbounded class of ordinals that are order-
indiscernible In mathematical logic, indiscernibles are objects that cannot be distinguished by any property or relation defined by a formula. Usually only first-order formulas are considered. Examples If ''a'', ''b'', and ''c'' are distinct and is a set o ...
in L. While some of these are not even initial ordinals in V, they have all the large cardinal properties weaker than 0^\sharp in L. Furthermore, any strictly increasing class function from this class of order-
indiscernibles In mathematical logic, indiscernibles are objects that cannot be distinguished by any property or relation defined by a formula. Usually only first-order formulas are considered. Examples If ''a'', ''b'', and ''c'' are distinct and is a set of ...
to itself can be extended in a unique way to an
elementary embedding In model theory, a branch of mathematical logic, two structures ''M'' and ''N'' of the same signature ''σ'' are called elementarily equivalent if they satisfy the same first-order ''σ''-sentences. If ''N'' is a substructure of ''M'', one oft ...
of L into L. This gives L a nice structure of repeating segments.


L can be well-ordered

There are various ways of well-ordering L. Some of these involve the "fine structure" of L, which was first described by Ronald Bjorn Jensen in his 1972 paper entitled "The fine structure of the constructible hierarchy". Instead of explaining the fine structure, we will give an outline of how L could be well-ordered using only the definition given above. Suppose x and y are two different sets in L and we wish to determine whether x < y or x > y. If x first appears in L_ and y first appears in L_ and \beta is different from \alpha, then let if and only if \alpha<\beta. Henceforth, we suppose that \beta=\alpha. The stage L_=\mathrm(L_\alpha) uses formulas with parameters from L_\alpha to define the sets x and y. If one discounts (for the moment) the parameters, the formulas can be given a standard
Gödel numbering In mathematical logic, a Gödel numbering is a function that assigns to each symbol and well-formed formula of some formal language a unique natural number, called its Gödel number. Kurt Gödel developed the concept for the proof of his incom ...
by the natural numbers. If \Phi is the formula with the smallest Gödel number that can be used to define x, and \Psi is the formula with the smallest Gödel number that can be used to define y, and \Psi is different from \Phi, then let if and only if \Phi<\Psi in the Gödel numbering. Henceforth, we suppose that \Psi=\Phi. Suppose that \Phi uses n parameters from L_\alpha. Suppose z_1,\ldots,z_n is the sequence of parameters that can be used with \Phi to define x, and w_1,\ldots,w_n does the same for y. Then let x < y if and only if either z_n < w_n or (z_n = w_n and z_ < w_) or (z_n=w_n and z_=w_ and z_), etc. This is called the reverse
lexicographic ordering In mathematics, the lexicographic or lexicographical order (also known as lexical order, or dictionary order) is a generalization of the alphabetical order of the dictionaries to sequences of ordered symbols or, more generally, of elements of a ...
; if there are multiple sequences of parameters that define one of the sets, we choose the least one under this ordering. It being understood that each parameter's possible values are ordered according to the restriction of the ordering of L to L_\alpha, so this definition involves transfinite recursion on \alpha. The well-ordering of the values of single parameters is provided by the inductive hypothesis of the transfinite induction. The values of n-tuples of parameters are well-ordered by the product ordering. The formulas with parameters are well-ordered by the ordered sum (by Gödel numbers) of well-orderings. And L is well-ordered by the ordered sum (indexed by \alpha) of the orderings on L_. Notice that this well-ordering can be defined within L itself by a formula of set theory with no parameters, only the free-variables x and y. And this formula gives the same
truth value In logic and mathematics, a truth value, sometimes called a logical value, is a value indicating the relation of a proposition to truth, which in classical logic has only two possible values ('' true'' or '' false''). Truth values are used in ...
regardless of whether it is evaluated in L, V, or W (some other standard model of ZF with the same ordinals) and we will suppose that the formula is false if either x or y is not in L. It is well known that the axiom of choice is equivalent to the ability to well-order every set. Being able to well-order the proper class V (as we have done here with L) is equivalent to the
axiom of global choice In mathematics, specifically in class theories, the axiom of global choice is a stronger variant of the axiom of choice that applies to proper classes of sets as well as sets of sets. Informally it states that one can simultaneously choose an ele ...
, which is more powerful than the ordinary
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from e ...
because it also covers proper classes of non-empty sets.


has a reflection principle

Proving that the
axiom of separation In many popular versions of axiomatic set theory, the axiom schema of specification, also known as the axiom schema of separation (''Aussonderungsaxiom''), subset axiom, axiom of class construction, or axiom schema of restricted comprehension is ...
,
axiom of replacement In set theory, the axiom schema of replacement is a schema of axioms in Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (ZF) that asserts that the image of any set under any definable mapping is also a set. It is necessary for the construction of certain infinite ...
, and
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, abbreviated AC or AoC, is an axiom of set theory. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection of non-empty sets, it is possible to construct a new set by choosing one element from e ...
hold in L requires (at least as shown above) the use of a
reflection principle In set theory, a branch of mathematics, a reflection principle says that it is possible to find sets that, with respect to any given property, resemble the class of all sets. There are several different forms of the reflection principle depending ...
for L. Here we describe such a principle. By induction on n<\omega, we can use ZF in V to prove that for any ordinal \alpha, there is an ordinal \beta>\alpha such that for any sentence P(z_1,\ldots,z_k) with z_1,\ldots,z_k in L_\beta and containing fewer than n symbols (counting a constant symbol for an element of L_\beta as one symbol) we get that P(z_1,\ldots,z_k) holds in L_\beta if and only if it holds in L.


The generalized continuum hypothesis holds in L

Let S \in L_\alpha, and let T be any constructible subset of S. Then there is some \beta with T \in L_, so for some formula \Phi and some z_i drawn from L_\beta. By the downward
Löwenheim–Skolem theorem In mathematical logic, the Löwenheim–Skolem theorem is a theorem on the existence and cardinality of models, named after Leopold Löwenheim and Thoralf Skolem. The precise formulation is given below. It implies that if a countable first-order ...
and Mostowski collapse, there must be some transitive set K containing L_\alpha and some w_i, and having the same first-order theory as L_\beta with the w_i substituted for the z_i; and this K will have the same cardinal as L_\alpha. Since V = L is true in L_\beta, it is also true in , so K = L_\gamma for some \gamma having the same cardinal as \alpha. And T = \ = \ because L_\beta and L_\gamma have the same theory. So T is in fact in L_. So all the constructible subsets of an infinite set S have ranks with (at most) the same cardinal \kappa as the rank of S; it follows that if \delta is the initial ordinal for \kappa^+, then L \cap \mathcal(S) \subseteq L_\delta serves as the "power set" of S within L Thus this "power set" L \cap \mathcal(S) \in L_. And this in turn means that the "power set" of S has cardinal at most \vert\delta\vert. Assuming S itself has cardinal \kappa, the "power set" must then have cardinal exactly \kappa^+. But this is precisely the
generalized continuum hypothesis In mathematics, specifically set theory, the continuum hypothesis (abbreviated CH) is a hypothesis about the possible sizes of infinite sets. It states: Or equivalently: In Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC), this ...
relativized to L.


Constructible sets are definable from the ordinals

There is a formula of set theory that expresses the idea that X = L_\alpha. It has only free variables for X and \alpha. Using this we can expand the definition of each constructible set. If S \in L_, then S = \ for some formula \Phi and some z_1,\ldots,z_n in L_\alpha. This is equivalent to saying that: for all y, y \in S if and only if here exists X such that X=L_\alpha and y \in X and \Psi(X,y,z_1,\ldots,z_n)where \Psi(X,\ldots) is the result of restricting each quantifier in \Phi(\ldots) to X. Notice that each z_k \in L_ for some \beta<\alpha. Combine formulas for the z's with the formula for S and apply existential quantifiers over the z's outside and one gets a formula that defines the constructible set S using only the ordinals \alpha that appear in expressions like x = L_\alpha as parameters. Example: The set \ is constructible. It is the unique set s that satisfies the formula: \forall y (y \in s \iff (y \in L_ \land (\forall a (a \in y \iff a \in L_5 \land Ord (a)) \lor \forall b (b \in y \iff b \in L_ \land Ord (b))))) where Ord (a) is short for: \forall c \in a (\forall d \in c (d \in a \land \forall e \in d (e \in c))). Actually, even this complex formula has been simplified from what the instructions given in the first paragraph would yield. But the point remains, there is a formula of set theory that is true only for the desired constructible set S and that contains parameters only for ordinals.


Relative constructibility

Sometimes it is desirable to find a model of set theory that is narrow like L, but that includes or is influenced by a set that is not constructible. This gives rise to the concept of relative constructibility, of which there are two flavors, denoted by L(A) and L /math>. The class L(A) for a non-constructible set A is the intersection of all classes that are standard models of set theory and contain A and all the ordinals. L(A) is defined by
transfinite recursion Transfinite induction is an extension of mathematical induction to well-ordered sets, for example to sets of ordinal numbers or cardinal numbers. Its correctness is a theorem of ZFC. Induction by cases Let P(\alpha) be a property defined for a ...
as follows: *L_0(A) = the smallest transitive set containing A as an element, i.e. the
transitive closure In mathematics, the transitive closure of a homogeneous binary relation on a set (mathematics), set is the smallest Relation (mathematics), relation on that contains and is Transitive relation, transitive. For finite sets, "smallest" can be ...
of \. *L_(A) = \mathrm (L_\alpha(A)) *If \lambda is a limit ordinal, then L_(A) = \bigcup_ L_(A). *L(A) = \bigcup_ L_(A). If L(A) contains a well-ordering of the transitive closure of \, then this can be extended to a well-ordering of L(A). Otherwise, the axiom of choice will fail in L(A). A common example is L(\mathbb), the smallest model that contains all the real numbers, which is used extensively in modern
descriptive set theory In mathematical logic, descriptive set theory (DST) is the study of certain classes of "well-behaved" set (mathematics), subsets of the real line and other Polish spaces. As well as being one of the primary areas of research in set theory, it has a ...
. The class L /math> is the class of sets whose construction is influenced by A, where A may be a (presumably non-constructible) set or a proper class. The definition of this class uses \mathrm_A(X), which is the same as \mathrm(X) except instead of evaluating the truth of formulas \Phi in the model (X,\in), one uses the model (X,\in,A) where A is a unary predicate. The intended interpretation of A(y) is y \in A. Then the definition of L /math> is exactly that of L only with \mathrm replaced by \mathrm_A. L /math> is always a model of the axiom of choice. Even if A is a set, A is not necessarily itself a member of L /math>, although it always is if A is a set of ordinals. The sets in L(A) or L /math> are usually not actually constructible, and the properties of these models may be quite different from the properties of L itself.


See also

*
Axiom of constructibility The axiom of constructibility is a possible axiom for set theory in mathematics that asserts that every set is constructible. The axiom is usually written as ''V'' = ''L''. The axiom, first investigated by Kurt Gödel, is inconsistent with the pr ...
* Statements true in L *
Reflection principle In set theory, a branch of mathematics, a reflection principle says that it is possible to find sets that, with respect to any given property, resemble the class of all sets. There are several different forms of the reflection principle depending ...
*
Axiomatic set theory Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies Set (mathematics), sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory – as a branch of mathema ...
*
Transitive set In set theory, a branch of mathematics, a set A is called transitive if either of the following equivalent conditions holds: * whenever x \in A, and y \in x, then y \in A. * whenever x \in A, and x is not an urelement, then x is a subset of A. S ...
*
L(R) In set theory, L(R) (pronounced ''L of R'') is the smallest transitive class, transitive inner model of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, ZF containing all the ordinal number, ordinals and all the real number, reals. Construction L(R) can be constru ...
* Ordinal definable *
Condensation lemma In set theory, a branch of mathematics, the condensation lemma is a result about sets in the constructible universe. It states that if ''X'' is a transitive set and is an elementary submodel of some level of the constructible hierarchy Lα, th ...


Notes


References

* * * * * * {{DEFAULTSORT:Constructible Universe Works by Kurt Gödel