HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
mathematical economics Mathematical economics is the application of Mathematics, mathematical methods to represent theories and analyze problems in economics. Often, these Applied mathematics#Economics, applied methods are beyond simple geometry, and may include diff ...
, the Arrow–Debreu model is a theoretical
general equilibrium In economics, general equilibrium theory attempts to explain the behavior of supply, demand, and prices in a whole economy with several or many interacting markets, by seeking to prove that the interaction of demand and supply will result in an ov ...
model. It posits that under certain economic assumptions (
convex preferences In economics, convex preferences are an individual's ordering of various outcomes, typically with regard to the amounts of various goods consumed, with the property that, roughly speaking, "averages are better than the extremes". This implies that ...
,
perfect competition In economics, specifically general equilibrium theory, a perfect market, also known as an atomistic market, is defined by several idealizing conditions, collectively called perfect competition, or atomistic competition. In Economic model, theoret ...
, and demand independence), there must be a set of prices such that aggregate supplies will equal
aggregate demand In economics, aggregate demand (AD) or domestic final demand (DFD) is the total demand for final goods and services in an economy at a given time. It is often called effective demand, though at other times this term is distinguished. This is the ...
s for every commodity in the economy. The model is central to the theory of general (economic) equilibrium, and it is used as a general reference for other microeconomic models. It was proposed by
Kenneth Arrow Kenneth Joseph Arrow (August 23, 1921 – February 21, 2017) was an American economist, mathematician and political theorist. He received the John Bates Clark Medal in 1957, and the Nobel Memorial Prize in Economic Sciences in 1972, along with ...
,
Gérard Debreu Gérard Debreu (; 4 July 1921 – 31 December 2004) was a French-born economist and mathematician. Best known as a professor of economics at the University of California, Berkeley, where he began work in 1962, he won the 1983 Nobel Memorial Prize ...
in 1954, and Lionel W. McKenzie independently in 1954, with later improvements in 1959. The A-D model is one of the most general models of competitive economy and is a crucial part of
general equilibrium theory In economics, general equilibrium theory attempts to explain the behavior of supply, demand, and prices in a whole economy with several or many interacting markets, by seeking to prove that the interaction of demand and supply will result in an ov ...
, as it can be used to prove the existence of
general equilibrium In economics, general equilibrium theory attempts to explain the behavior of supply, demand, and prices in a whole economy with several or many interacting markets, by seeking to prove that the interaction of demand and supply will result in an ov ...
(or
Walrasian equilibrium Competitive equilibrium (also called: Walrasian equilibrium) is a concept of economic equilibrium, introduced by Kenneth Arrow and Gérard Debreu in 1951, appropriate for the analysis of commodity markets with flexible prices and many traders, and ...
) of an economy. In general, there may be many equilibria. Arrow (1972) and Debreu (1983) were separately awarded the
Nobel Prize in Economics The Nobel Memorial Prize in Economic Sciences, officially the Sveriges Riksbank Prize in Economic Sciences in Memory of Alfred Nobel (), commonly referred to as the Nobel Prize in Economics(), is an award in the field of economic sciences adminis ...
for their development of the model. McKenzie, however, did not receive the award.


Formal statement

This section follows the presentation in, which is based on.


Intuitive description of the Arrow–Debreu model

The Arrow–Debreu model models an economy as a combination of three kinds of agents: the households, the producers, and the market. The households and producers transact with the market but not with each other directly. The households possess endowments (bundles of commodities they begin with), one may think of as "inheritance." For mathematical clarity, all households must sell all their endowment to the market at the beginning. If they wish to retain some of the endowments, they would have to repurchase them from the market later. The endowments may be working hours, land use, tons of corn, etc. The households possess proportional ownerships of producers, which can be thought of as
joint-stock companies A joint-stock company (JSC) is a business entity in which shares of the company's stock can be bought and sold by shareholders. Each shareholder owns company stock in proportion, evidenced by their shares (certificates of ownership). Shareholder ...
. The profit made by producer j is divided among the households in proportion to how much stock each household holds for the producer j. Ownership is imposed initially, and the households may not sell, buy, create, or discard them. The households receive a budget, income from selling endowments, and
dividend A dividend is a distribution of profits by a corporation to its shareholders, after which the stock exchange decreases the price of the stock by the dividend to remove volatility. The market has no control over the stock price on open on the ex ...
from producer profits. The households possess preferences over bundles of commodities, which, under the assumptions given, makes them utility maximizers. The households choose the consumption plan with the highest utility they can afford using their budget. The producers can transform bundles of commodities into other bundles of commodities. The producers have no separate utility functions. Instead, they are all purely profit maximizers. The market is only capable of "choosing" a market price vector, which is a list of prices for each commodity, which every producer and household takes (there is no bargaining behavior—every producer and household is a
price taker In economics, market power refers to the ability of a firm to influence the price at which it sells a product or service by manipulating either the supply or demand of the product or service to increase economic profit. In other words, market powe ...
). The market has no utility or profit. Instead, the market aims to choose a market price vector such that, even though each household and producer is maximizing their utility and profit, their consumption and production plans "harmonize." That is, " the market clears". In other words, the market is playing the role of a " Walrasian auctioneer."


Notation setup

In general, we write indices of agents as superscripts and vector coordinate indices as subscripts.


useful notations for real vectors

* x \succeq y if \forall n, x_n \geq y_n * \R^N_+ is the set of x such that x \succeq 0 * \R_^N is the set of x such that x \succ 0 * \Delta_N = \left\ is the N-simplex. We often call it the price simplex since we sometimes scale the price vector to lie on it.


market

* The commodities are indexed as n\in 1:N. Here N is the number of commodities in the economy. It is a finite number. * The price vector p = (p_1, ..., p_N) \in \R_^N is a vector of length N, with each coordinate being the price of a commodity. The prices may be zero or positive.


households

* The households are indexed as i\in I. * Each household begins with an endowment of commodities r^i\in \R^N_+. * Each household begins with a tuple of ownerships of the producers \alpha^ \geq 0. The ownerships satisfy \sum_ \alpha^ = 1 \quad \forall j\in J . * The budget that the household receives is the sum of its income from selling endowments at the market price, plus profits from its ownership of producers:M^i(p) = \langle p, r^i\rangle + \sum_\alpha^\Pi^j(p)(M stands for ''money'') * Each household has a Consumption Possibility Set CPS^i\subset \R_+^N. * Each household has a preference relation \succeq^i over CPS^i. * With assumptions on \succeq^i (given in the next section), each preference relation is representable by a utility function u^i: CPS^i \to
, 1 The comma is a punctuation mark that appears in several variants in different languages. Some typefaces render it as a small line, slightly curved or straight, but inclined from the vertical; others give it the appearance of a miniature fille ...
/math> by the Debreu theorems. Thus instead of maximizing preference, we can equivalently state that the household is maximizing its utility. * A consumption plan is a vector in CPS^i, written as x^i. * U_+^i(x^i) is the set of consumption plans at least as preferable as x^i. * The budget set is the set of consumption plans that it can afford:B^i(p) = \. * For each price vector p, the household has a demand vector for commodities, as D^i(p)\in \R_+^N. This function is defined as the solution to a constraint maximization problem. It depends on both the economy and the initial distribution.D^i(p) := \arg\max_ u^i(x^i)It may not be well-defined for all p \in \R^N_. However, we will use enough assumptions to be well-defined at equilibrium price vectors.


producers

* The producers are indexed as j\in J. * Each producer has a Production Possibility Set PPS^j. Note that the supply vector may have both positive and negative coordinates. For example, (-1, 1, 0) indicates a production plan that uses up 1 unit of commodity 1 to produce 1 unit of commodity 2. * A production plan is a vector in PPS^j, written as y^j. * For each price vector p, the producer has a supply vector for commodities, as S^j(p)\in \R^N. This function will be defined as the solution to a constraint maximization problem. It depends on both the economy and the initial distribution.S^j(p) := \arg\max_ \langle p, y^j\rangleIt may not be well-defined for all p \in \R^N_. However, we will use enough assumptions to be well-defined at equilibrium price vectors. * The profit is \Pi^j(p) := \langle p, S^j(p)\rangle = \max_ \langle p, y^j\rangle


aggregates

* aggregate consumption possibility set CPS = \sum_CPS^i. * aggregate production possibility set PPS = \sum_PPS^j. * aggregate endowment r = \sum_i r^i * aggregate demand D(p) := \sum_i D^i(p) * aggregate supply S(p) := \sum_j S^j(p) * excess demand Z(p) = D(p) - S(p) - r


the whole economy

* An economy is a tuple (N, I, J, CPS^i, \succeq^i, PPS^j). It is a tuple specifying the commodities, consumer preferences, consumption possibility sets, and producers' production possibility sets. * An economy with initial distribution is an economy, along with an initial distribution tuple (r^i, \alpha^)_ for the economy. * A state of the economy is a tuple of price, consumption plans, and production plans for each household and producer: ((p_n)_, (x^i)_, (y^j)_). * A state is feasible iff each x^i \in CPS^i, each y^j\in PPS^j, and \sum_x^i \preceq \sum_y^j + r. * The feasible production possibilities set, given endowment r, is PPS_r := \. * Given an economy with distribution, the state corresponding to a price vector p is (p, (D^i(p))_, (S^j(p))_). * Given an economy with distribution, a price vector p is an equilibrium price vector for the economy with initial distribution, iffZ(p)_n \begin \leq 0 \text p_n = 0 \\ = 0 \text p_n > 0 \endThat is, if a commodity is not free, then supply exactly equals demand, and if a commodity is free, then supply is equal or greater than demand (we allow free commodity to be oversupplied). * A state is an equilibrium state iff it is the state corresponding to an equilibrium price vector.


Assumptions


Imposing an artificial restriction

The functions D^i(p), S^j(p) are not necessarily well-defined for all price vectors p. For example, if producer 1 is capable of transforming t units of commodity 1 into \sqrt units of commodity 2, and we have p_1 / p_2 < 1, then the producer can create plans with infinite profit, thus \Pi^j(p) = +\infty, and S^j(p) is undefined. Consequently, we define "restricted market" to be the same market, except there is a universal upper bound C, such that every producer is required to use a production plan \, y^j\, \leq C. Each household is required to use a consumption plan \, x^i\, \leq C. Denote the corresponding quantities on the restricted market with a tilde. So, for example, \tilde Z(p) is the excess demand function on the restricted market. C is chosen to be "large enough" for the economy so that the restriction is not in effect under equilibrium conditions (see next section). In detail, C is chosen to be large enough such that: * For any consumption plan x such that x \succeq 0, \, x\, = C, the plan is so "extravagant" that even if all the producers coordinate, they would still fall short of meeting the demand. * For any list of production plans for the economy (y^j\in PPS^j)_, if \sum_ y^j + r \succeq 0, then \, y^j\, < Cfor each j\in J. In other words, for any attainable production plan under the given endowment r, each producer's individual production plan must lie strictly within the restriction. Each requirement is satisfiable. * Define the set of attainable aggregate production plans to be PPS_r = \left\, then under the assumptions for the producers given above (especially the "no arbitrarily large free lunch" assumption), PPS_r is bounded for any r \succeq 0 (proof omitted). Thus the first requirement is satisfiable. * Define the set of attainable individual production plans to be PPS_r^j := \then under the assumptions for the producers given above (especially the "no arbitrarily large transformations" assumption), PPS_r^j is bounded for any j\in J, r \succeq 0 (proof omitted). Thus the second requirement is satisfiable. The two requirements together imply that the restriction is not a real restriction when the production plans and consumption plans are " interior" to the restriction. * At any price vector p, if \, \tilde S^j(p)\, < C, then S^j(p) exists and is equal to \tilde S^j(p) . In other words, if the production plan of a restricted producer is interior to the artificial restriction, then the unrestricted producer would choose the same production plan. This is proved by exploiting the second requirement on C. * If all S^j(p) = \tilde S^j(p), then the restricted and unrestricted households have the same budget. Now, if we also have \, \tilde D^i(p)\, < C, then D^i(p) exists and is equal to \tilde D^i(p) . In other words, if the consumption plan of a restricted household is interior to the artificial restriction, then the unrestricted household would choose the same consumption plan. This is proved by exploiting the first requirement on C. These two propositions imply that equilibria for the restricted market are equilibria for the unrestricted market:


existence of general equilibrium

As the last piece of the construction, we define Walras's law: * The unrestricted market satisfies Walras's law at p iff all S^j(p), D^i(p) are defined, and \langle p, Z(p)\rangle = 0, that is, \sum_ \langle p,S^j(p)\rangle + \langle p, r\rangle = \sum_ \langle p, D^i(p)\rangle * The restricted market satisfies Walras's law at p iff \langle p, \tilde Z(p)\rangle = 0. Walras's law can be interpreted on both sides: * On the side of the households, it is said that the aggregate household expenditure is equal to aggregate profit and aggregate income from selling endowments. In other words, every household spends its entire budget. * On the side of the producers, it is saying that the aggregate profit plus the aggregate cost equals the aggregate revenue. Note that the above proof does not give an iterative algorithm for finding any equilibrium, as there is no guarantee that the function f is a contraction. This is unsurprising, as there is no guarantee (without further assumptions) that any market equilibrium is a stable equilibrium.


The role of convexity

In 1954, McKenzie and the pair
Arrow An arrow is a fin-stabilized projectile launched by a bow. A typical arrow usually consists of a long, stiff, straight shaft with a weighty (and usually sharp and pointed) arrowhead attached to the front end, multiple fin-like stabilizers c ...
and Debreu independently proved the existence of general equilibria by invoking the
Kakutani fixed-point theorem In mathematical analysis, the Kakutani fixed-point theorem is a fixed-point theorem for set-valued functions. It provides sufficient conditions for a set-valued function defined on a convex, compact subset of a Euclidean space to have a fixed poi ...
on the fixed points of a
continuous Continuity or continuous may refer to: Mathematics * Continuity (mathematics), the opposing concept to discreteness; common examples include ** Continuous probability distribution or random variable in probability and statistics ** Continuous ...
function Function or functionality may refer to: Computing * Function key, a type of key on computer keyboards * Function model, a structured representation of processes in a system * Function object or functor or functionoid, a concept of object-orie ...
from a
compact Compact as used in politics may refer broadly to a pact or treaty; in more specific cases it may refer to: * Interstate compact, a type of agreement used by U.S. states * Blood compact, an ancient ritual of the Philippines * Compact government, a t ...
, convex set into itself. In the Arrow–Debreu approach, convexity is essential, because such fixed-point theorems are inapplicable to non-convex sets. For example, the rotation of the
unit circle In mathematics, a unit circle is a circle of unit radius—that is, a radius of 1. Frequently, especially in trigonometry, the unit circle is the circle of radius 1 centered at the origin (0, 0) in the Cartesian coordinate system in the Eucli ...
by 90 degrees lacks fixed points, although this rotation is a continuous transformation of a compact set into itself; although compact, the unit circle is non-convex. In contrast, the same rotation applied to the convex hull of the unit circle leaves the point ''(0,0)'' fixed. Notice that the Kakutani theorem does not assert that there exists exactly one fixed point. Reflecting the unit disk across the y-axis leaves a vertical segment fixed, so that this reflection has an infinite number of fixed points.


Non-convexity in large economies

The assumption of convexity precluded many applications, which were discussed in the ''
Journal of Political Economy The ''Journal of Political Economy'' is a monthly peer-reviewed academic journal published by the University of Chicago Press. Established by James Laurence Laughlin in 1892, it covers both theoretical and empirical economics. In the past, the ...
'' from 1959 to 1961 by Francis M. Bator, M. J. Farrell, Tjalling Koopmans, and Thomas J. Rothenberg.. proved the existence of economic equilibria when some consumer preferences need not be
convex Convex or convexity may refer to: Science and technology * Convex lens, in optics Mathematics * Convex set, containing the whole line segment that joins points ** Convex polygon, a polygon which encloses a convex set of points ** Convex polytop ...
. In his paper, Starr proved that a "convexified" economy has general equilibria that are closely approximated by "quasi-equilbria" of the original economy; Starr's proof used the Shapley–Folkman theorem.


Uzawa equivalence theorem

( Uzawa, 1962) showed that the existence of general equilibrium in an economy characterized by a continuous excess demand function fulfilling Walras's Law is equivalent to Brouwer fixed-Point theorem. Thus, the use of Brouwer's fixed-point theorem is essential for showing that the equilibrium exists in general.


Fundamental theorems of welfare economics There are two fundamental theorems of welfare economics. The first states that in economic equilibrium, a set of complete markets, with complete information, and in perfect competition, will be Pareto optimal (in the sense that no further exchange ...

In welfare economics, one possible concern is finding a Pareto-optimal plan for the economy. Intuitively, one can consider the problem of welfare economics to be the problem faced by a master planner for the whole economy: given starting endowment r for the entire society, the planner must pick a feasible master plan of production and consumption plans ((x^i)_, (y^j)_). The master planner has a wide freedom in choosing the master plan, but any reasonable planner should agree that, if someone's utility can be increased, while everyone else's is not decreased, then it is a better plan. That is, the Pareto ordering should be followed. Define the Pareto ordering on the set of all plans ((x^i)_, (y^j)_) by ((x^i)_, (y^j)_) \succeq((x'^i)_, (y'^j)_) iff x^i \succeq^i x'^i for all i\in I. Then, we say that a plan is Pareto-efficient with respect to a starting endowment r, iff it is feasible, and there does not exist another feasible plan that is strictly better in Pareto ordering. In general, there are a whole continuum of Pareto-efficient plans for each starting endowment r. With the set up, we have two fundamental theorems of welfare economics: Proof idea: any Pareto-optimal consumption plan is separated by a hyperplane from the set of attainable consumption plans. The slope of the hyperplane would be the equilibrium prices. Verify that under such prices, each producer and household would find the given state optimal. Verify that Walras's law holds, and so the expenditures match income plus profit, and so it is possible to provide each household with exactly the necessary budget.


convexity vs strict convexity

The assumptions of strict convexity can be relaxed to convexity. This modification changes supply and demand functions from point-valued functions into set-valued functions (or "correspondences"), and the application of Brouwer's fixed-point theorem into Kakutani's fixed-point theorem. This modification is similar to the generalization of the
minimax theorem In the mathematical area of game theory and of convex optimization, a minimax theorem is a theorem that claims that : \max_ \min_ f(x,y) = \min_ \max_f(x,y) under certain conditions on the sets X and Y and on the function f. It is always true that ...
to the existence of
Nash equilibria In game theory, the Nash equilibrium is the most commonly used solution concept for non-cooperative games. A Nash equilibrium is a situation where no player could gain by changing their own strategy (holding all other players' strategies fixed) ...
. The two fundamental theorems of welfare economics holds without modification.


equilibrium vs "quasi-equilibrium"

The definition of market equilibrium assumes that every household performs utility maximization, subject to budget constraints. That is, \begin \max_ u^i(x^i) \\ \langle p, x^i\rangle \leq M^i(p) \endThe dual problem would be cost minimization subject to utility constraints. That is,\begin u^i(x^i) \geq u^i_0\\ \min_ \langle p, x^i\rangle \endfor some real number u^i_0. The
duality gap In optimization problems in applied mathematics, the duality gap is the difference between the primal and dual solutions. If d^* is the optimal dual value and p^* is the optimal primal value then the duality gap is equal to p^* - d^*. This value ...
between the two problems is nonnegative, and may be positive. Consequently, some authors study the dual problem and the properties of its "quasi-equilibrium" (or "compensated equilibrium"). Every equilibrium is a quasi-equilibrium, but the converse is not necessarily true.


Extensions


Accounting for strategic bargaining

In the model, all producers and households are " price takers", meaning that they transact with the market using the price vector p. In particular, behaviors such as cartel, monopoly, consumer coalition, etc are not modelled. Edgeworth's limit theorem shows that under certain stronger assumptions, the households can do no better than price-take at the limit of an infinitely large economy.


Setup

In detail, we continue with the economic model on the households and producers, but we consider a different method to design production and distribution of commodities than the market economy. It may be interpreted as a model of a "socialist" economy. * There is no money, market, or private ownership of producers. * Since we have abolished private ownership, money, and the profit motive, there is no point in distinguishing one producer from the next. Consequently, instead of each producer planning individually y^j \in PPS^j, it is as if the whole society has one great producer producing y\in PPS. * Households still have the same preferences and endowments, but they no longer have budgets. * Producers do not produce to maximize profit, since there is no profit. All households come together to make a state ((x_i)_, y)—a production and consumption plan for the whole economy—with the following constraints:x^i \in CPS^i, y \in PPS, y\succeq \sum_i (x^i- r^i) * Any nonempty subset of households may eliminate all other households, while retaining control of the producers. This economy is thus a cooperative game with each household being a player, and we have the following concepts from cooperative game theory: * A blocking coalition is a nonempty subset of households, such that there exists a strictly Pareto-better plan even if they eliminate all other households. * A state is a core state iff there are no blocking coalitions. * The core of an economy is the set of core states. Since we assumed that any nonempty subset of households may eliminate all other households, while retaining control of the producers, the only states that can be executed are the core states. A state that is not a core state would immediately be objected by a coalition of households. We need one more assumption on PPS, that it is a cone, that is, k \cdot PPS \subset PPS for any k \geq 0. This assumption rules out two ways for the economy to become trivial. * The curse of free lunch: In this model, the whole PPS is available to any nonempty coalition, even a coalition of one. Consequently, if nobody has any endowment, and yet PPS contains some "free lunch" y\succ 0, then (assuming preferences are monotonic) every household would like to take all of y for itself, and consequently there exists *no* core state. Intuitively, the picture of the world is a committee of selfish people, vetoing any plan that doesn't give the entire free lunch to itself. * The limit to growth: Consider a society with 2 commodities. One is "labor" and another is "food". Households have only labor as endowment, but they only consume food. The PPS looks like a ramp with a flat top. So, putting in 0-1 thousand hours of labor produces 0-1 thousand kg of food, linearly, but any more labor produces no food. Now suppose each household is endowed with 1 thousand hours of labor. It's clear that every household would immediately block every other household, since it's always better for one to use the entire PPS for itself.


Main results (Debreu and Scarf, 1963)

In Debreu and Scarf's paper, they defined a particular way to approach an infinitely large economy, by "replicating households". That is, for any positive integer K, define an economy where there are K households that have exactly the same consumption possibility set and preference as household i. Let x^ stand for the consumption plan of the k-th replicate of household i. Define a plan to be equitable iff x^ \sim^i x^ for any i\in I and k, k'\in K. In general, a state would be quite complex, treating each replicate differently. However, core states are significantly simpler: they are equitable, treating every replicate equally. Consequently, when studying core states, it is sufficient to consider one consumption plan for each type of households. Now, define C_K to be the set of all core states for the economy with K replicates per household. It is clear that C_1 \supset C_2 \supset \cdots, so we may define the limit set of core states C := \cap_^\infty C_K. We have seen that C contains the set of market equilibria for the original economy. The converse is true under minor additional assumption: The assumption that PPS is a polygonal cone, or every CPS^i has nonempty interior, is necessary to avoid the technical issue of "quasi-equilibrium". Without the assumption, we can only prove that C is contained in the set of quasi-equilibria.


Accounting for nonconvexity

The assumption that production possibility sets are convex is a strong constraint, as it implies that there is no economy of scale. Similarly, we may consider nonconvex consumption possibility sets and nonconvex preferences. In such cases, the supply and demand functions S^j(p), D^i(p) may be discontinuous with respect to price vector, thus a general equilibrium may not exist. However, we may "convexify" the economy, find an equilibrium for it, then by the Shapley–Folkman–Starr theorem, it is an approximate equilibrium for the original economy. In detail, given any economy satisfying all the assumptions given, except convexity of PPS^j, CPS^i and \succeq^i, we define the "convexified economy" to be the same economy, except that * PPS'^j = \mathrm(PPS^j) * CPS'^i = \mathrm(CPS^i) * x \succeq'^i y iff \forall z \in CPS^i, y \in \mathrm(U_+^i(z)) \implies x \in \mathrm(U_+^i(z)) . where \mathrm denotes the
convex hull In geometry, the convex hull, convex envelope or convex closure of a shape is the smallest convex set that contains it. The convex hull may be defined either as the intersection of all convex sets containing a given subset of a Euclidean space, ...
. With this, any general equilibrium for the convexified economy is also an approximate equilibrium for the original economy. That is, if p^* is an equilibrium price vector for the convexified economy, then\begin d(D'(p^*) - S'(p^*), D(p^*) - S(p^*)) &\leq N\sqrt \\ d(r, D(p^*) - S(p^*)) &\leq N\sqrt \endwhere d(\cdot, \cdot) is the Euclidean distance, and L is any upper bound on the inner radii of all PPS^j, CPS^i (see page on Shapley–Folkman–Starr theorem for the definition of inner radii). The convexified economy may not satisfy the assumptions. For example, the set \\cup \ is closed, but its convex hull is not closed. Imposing the further assumption that the convexified economy also satisfies the assumptions, we find that the original economy always has an approximate equilibrium.


Accounting for time, space, and uncertainty

The commodities in the Arrow–Debreu model are entirely abstract. Thus, although it is typically represented as a static market, it can be used to model time, space, and uncertainty by splitting one commodity into several, each contingent on a certain time, place, and state of the world. For example, "apples" can be divided into "apples in New York in September if oranges are available" and "apples in Chicago in June if oranges are not available". Given some base commodities, the Arrow–Debreu complete market is a market where there is a separate commodity for every future time, for every place of delivery, for every state of the world under consideration, for every base commodity. In
financial economics Financial economics is the branch of economics characterized by a "concentration on monetary activities", in which "money of one type or another is likely to appear on ''both sides'' of a trade".William F. Sharpe"Financial Economics", in Its co ...
the term "Arrow–Debreu" most commonly refers to an Arrow–Debreu security. A canonical Arrow–Debreu security is a security that pays one unit of numeraire if a particular state of the world is reached and zero otherwise (the price of such a security being a so-called "
state price In financial economics, a state-price security, also called an Arrow–Debreu security (from its origins in the Arrow–Debreu model), a pure security, or a primitive security is a contract that agrees to pay one unit of a numeraire (a currency or ...
"). As such, any derivatives contract whose settlement value is a function on an underlying whose value is uncertain at contract date can be decomposed as linear combination of Arrow–Debreu securities. Since the work of Breeden and Lizenberger in 1978, a large number of researchers have used options to extract Arrow–Debreu prices for a variety of applications in
financial economics Financial economics is the branch of economics characterized by a "concentration on monetary activities", in which "money of one type or another is likely to appear on ''both sides'' of a trade".William F. Sharpe"Financial Economics", in Its co ...
.


Accounting for the existence of money

Typically, economists consider the functions of money to be as a unit of account, store of value, medium of exchange, and standard of deferred payment. This is however incompatible with the Arrow–Debreu complete market described above. In the complete market, there is only a one-time transaction at the market "at the beginning of time". After that, households and producers merely execute their planned productions, consumptions, and deliveries of commodities until the end of time. Consequently, there is no use for storage of value or medium of exchange. This applies not just to the Arrow–Debreu complete market, but also to models (such as those with markets of contingent commodities and Arrow insurance contracts) that differ in form, but are mathematically equivalent to it.


Computing general equilibria

Scarf (1967) was the first algorithm that computes the general equilibrium. See Scarf (2018) and Kubler (2012) for reviews.


Number of equilibria

Certain economies at certain endowment vectors may have infinitely equilibrium price vectors. However, "generically", an economy has only finitely many equilibrium price vectors. Here, "generically" means "on all points, except a closed set of Lebesgue measure zero", as in
Sard's theorem In mathematics, Sard's theorem, also known as Sard's lemma or the Morse–Sard theorem, is a result in mathematical analysis that asserts that the set of critical values (that is, the image of the set of critical points) of a smooth function ' ...
. There are many such genericity theorems. One example is the following:(Starr 2011) Section 26.3


See also

*
Model (economics) An economic model is a theoretical construct representing economic processes by a set of variables and a set of logical and/or quantitative relationships between them. The economic model is a simplified, often mathematical, framework designed ...
*
Incomplete markets In economics, incomplete markets are markets in which there does not exist an Arrow–Debreu security for every possible state of nature. In contrast with complete markets, this shortage of securities will likely restrict individuals from transferr ...
* Arrow-Debreu exchange market - a simpler market model, in which there are only households (who can be both buyers and sellers), but no producers. *
Fisher market Fisher market is an economic model attributed to Irving Fisher. It has the following ingredients: * A set of m divisible products with pre-specified supplies (usually normalized such that the supply of each good is 1). * A set of n buyers. * For eac ...
- an even simpler market model, in which there are only buyers; the total quantity of each product is given, and each buyer comes only with a monetary budget. * List of asset pricing articles *


References


Further reading

* * * *


External links


Notes on the Arrow–Debreu–McKenzie Model of an Economy
Prof. Kim C. Border
California Institute of Technology The California Institute of Technology (branded as Caltech) is a private research university in Pasadena, California, United States. The university is responsible for many modern scientific advancements and is among a small group of institutes ...

"The Fundamental Theorem" of Financepart II
Prof.
Mark Rubinstein Mark Edward Rubinstein (June 8, 1944 – May 9, 2019) was a leading financial economics, financial economist and financial engineering, financial engineer. He was Paul Stephens Professor of Applied Investment Analysis at the Haas School of Busine ...
,
Haas School of Business The Walter A. Haas School of Business (branded as Berkeley Haas) is the business school of the University of California, Berkeley, a Public university, public research university in Berkeley, California. It was the first business school at a pub ...
{{DEFAULTSORT:Arrow-Debreu model General equilibrium theory Financial models 1954 in economic history