HOME
The Info List - Theodicy


--- Advertisement ---



Theodicy
Theodicy
(/θiːˈɒdɪsi/), in its most common form, is an attempt to answer the question of why a good God
God
permits the manifestation of evil. Some theodicies also address the evidential problem of evil by attempting "to make the existence of an all-knowing, all-powerful and all-good or omnibenevolent God
God
consistent with the existence of evil or suffering in the world."[1] Unlike a defense, which tries to demonstrate that God's existence is logically possible in the light of evil, a theodicy attempts to provide a framework wherein God's existence is also plausible.[2] The German mathematician and philosopher Gottfried Leibniz
Gottfried Leibniz
coined the term "theodicy" in 1710 in his work Théodicée, though various responses to the problem of evil had been previously proposed. The British philosopher John Hick traced the history of moral theodicy in his 1966 work, Evil
Evil
and the God
God
of Love, identifying three major traditions:

the Plotinian theodicy, named after Plotinus the Augustinian theodicy, which Hick based on the writings of Augustine of Hippo the Irenaean theodicy, which Hick developed, based on the thinking of St. Irenaeus

The problem was also analyzed by pre-modern theologians and philosophers in the Islamic world. German philosopher Max Weber (1864–1920) saw theodicy as a social problem, based on the human need to explain puzzling aspects of the world.[3] Sociologist Peter L. Berger (1929–2017) argued that religion arose out of a need for social order, and an “implicit theodicy of all social order” developed to sustain it.[4] Following the Holocaust, a number of Jewish theologians developed a new response to the problem of evil, sometimes called anti-theodicy, which maintains that God
God
cannot be meaningfully justified. As an alternative to theodicy, a defense has been proposed by the American philosopher Alvin Plantinga, which is focused on showing the logical possibility of God's existence. Plantinga's version of the free-will defence argued that the coexistence of God
God
and evil is not logically impossible, and that free will further explains the existence of evil without threatening the existence of God.[not verified in body] Similar to a theodicy, a cosmodicy attempts to justify the fundamental goodness of the universe, and an anthropodicy attempts to justify the goodness of humanity.

Contents

1 Definition and etymology 2 Reasons for theodicy 3 History

3.1 Ancient religions

3.1.1 Biblical theodicy

3.2 Augustinian theodicy 3.3 Irenaean theodicy 3.4 Origenian theodicy 3.5 Relatively minor theodicies 3.6 Islamic world

4 Alternatives

4.1 Jewish anti-theodicy 4.2 Christian alternatives to theodicy 4.3 Free will
Free will
defense 4.4 Cosmodicy and anthropodicy

4.4.1 Essential kenosis

5 See also 6 References 7 Bibliography 8 External links

Definition and etymology[edit] As defined by Alvin Plantinga, theodicy is the "answer to the question of why God
God
permits evil".[5] Theodicy
Theodicy
is defined as a theological construct that attempts to vindicate God
God
in response to the evidential problem of evil that mitigates against the existence of an omnipotent and omnibenevolent deity.[6] The word theodicy derives from the Greek words Θεός Τheos and δίκη dikē. Theos is translated "God" and dikē can be translated as either "trial" or "judgement".[7] Thus, theodicy literally means "justifying God".[8] In the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy, Nick Trakakis proposed an additional three requirements which must be contained within a theodicy:

Common sense views of the world Widely held historical and scientific opinion Plausible moral principles[9]

As a response to the problem of evil, a theodicy is distinct from a defence. A defence attempts to demonstrate that the occurrence of evil does not contradict God's existence, but it does not propose that rational beings are able to understand why God
God
permits evil. A theodicy seeks to show that it is reasonable to believe in God
God
despite evidence of evil in the world and offers a framework which can account for why evil exists.[10] A theodicy is often based on a prior natural theology, which attempts to prove the existence of God, and seeks to demonstrate that God's existence remains probable after the problem of evil is posed by giving a justification for God's permitting evil to happen.[11] Defenses propose solutions to the logical problem of evil, while theodicies attempt to answer the evidential (inductive) problem.[9]

"It is important to note that there are at least two concepts of evil: a broad concept and a narrow concept. The broad concept picks out any bad state of affairs... [and] has been divided into two categories: natural evil and moral evil. Natural evils are bad states of affairs which do not result from the intentions or negligence of moral agents. Hurricanes and toothaches are examples of natural evils. By contrast, moral evils do result from the intentions or negligence of moral agents. Murder and lying are examples of moral evils. Evil
Evil
in the broad sense, which includes all natural and moral evils, tends to be the sort of evil referenced in theological contexts... [T]he narrow concept of evil picks out only the most morally despicable... [it] involves moral condemnation, [and] is appropriately ascribed only to moral agents and their actions."[12]

Philosopher [Susan Nieman] says "a crime against humanity is something for which we have procedures, ... [and it] can be ... fit into the rest of our experience. To call an action evil is to suggest that it cannot [be fitted in]..."[13]:8 Marxism, "selectively elaborating Hegel," defines evil in terms of its effect.[14]:44 Philosopher John Kekes says the effect of evil must include actual harm "that 'interferes with the functioning of a person as a full-fledged agent.' (Kekes 1998, 217)."[12] Christian philosophers and theologians such as Richard Swinburne
Richard Swinburne
and N. T. Wright also define evil in terms of effect saying an "...act is objectively good (or bad) if it is good (or bad) in its consequences".[15]:12[14] Hinduism defines evil in terms of its effect saying "the evils that afflict people (and indeed animals) in the present life are the effects of wrongs committed in a previous life".[14]:34 Some contemporary philosophers argue a focus on the effects of evil is inadequate as a definition since evil can observe without actively causing the harm, and it is still evil.[12] Pseudo-Dionysus
Pseudo-Dionysus
defines evil by those aspects that show an absence of good.[14]:37 Writers in this tradition saw things as belonging to 'forms' and evil as an absence of being a good example of their form: as a deficit of goodness where goodness ought to have been present. In this same line of thinking, St.Augustine also defined evil as an absence of good, as did theologian and monk Thomas Aquinas
Thomas Aquinas
who said: "... a man is called bad insofar as he lacks a virtue, and an eye is called bad insofar as it lacks the power of sight."[15]:37 Bad as an absence of good resurfaces in Hegel, Heidegger and Barth. Very similar are the Neoplatonists, such as Plotinus
Plotinus
and contemporary philosopher Denis O'Brien, who say evil is a privation.[16] [17] Immanuel Kant
Immanuel Kant
was the first to offer a purely secular theory of evil, giving an evaluative definition of evil based on its cause as having a will that is not fully good. Kant has been an important influence on philosophers like Hanna Arendt, Claudia Card, and Richard Bernstein.[18] "...Hanna Arendt... uses the term [radical evil] to denote a new form of wrongdoing which cannot be captured by other moral concepts."[12] The Muslim also provides an evaluative definition of evil saying it is the result of the world not being fully Muslim.[14]:34 Claudia Card
Claudia Card
says evil is excessive wrong-doing; others like Hillel Steiner say evil is qualitatively not quantitatively distinct from mere wrongdoing.[12] Locke, Hobbes and Liebniz define good and evil in terms of pleasure and pain.[19][20][21] Others such as Richard Swinburne
Richard Swinburne
find that definition inadequate, saying, "the good of individual humans...consists...in their having free will...the ability to develop ...character..., to show courage and loyalty, to love, to be of use, to contemplate beauty and discover truth... All that [good]...cannot be achieved without ... suffering along the way."[15]:4

"Most theorists writing about evil believe that evil action requires a certain sort of motivation... the desire to cause harm, or to do wrong,...pleasure (Steiner 2002), the desire to annihilate all being (Eagleton 2010), or the destruction of others for its own sake (Cole 2006). When evil is restricted to actions that follow from these sorts of motivations, theorists sometimes say that their subject is pure, radical, diabolical, or monstrous evil. This suggests that their discussion is restricted to a type, or form, of evil and not to evil per se."[12]

Some theorists define evil by what emotions are connected to it. "For example, Laurence Thomas believes that evildoers take delight in causing harm or feel hatred toward their victims (Thomas 1993, 76–77)."[12] Buddhism defines evil as behavior resulting from a failure to emotionally detach from the world.[22] Christian theologians generally define evil in terms of both human responsibility and the nature of God: "If we take the essentialist view of Christian ethics... evil is anything contrary to God's good nature...(character or attributes)."[23] The Judaic view, while acknowledging the difference between the human and divine perspective of evil, is rooted in the nature of creation itself and the limitation inherent in matter's capacity to be perfected; the action of freewill includes the potential for perfection from individual effort and leaves the responsibility for evil in human hands.[24]:70 "[It is] deeply central to the whole tradition of Christian (and other western) religion that God
God
is loving toward his creation and that involves him behaving in morally good ways toward it."[15]:3 Within Christianity " God
God
is supposed to be in some way personal... a being who is essentially eternal, omnipotent, omniscient, Creator and sustainer of the universe, and perfectly good. An omnipotent being is one who can do anything logically possible... such a being could not make me exist and not exist at the same time but he could eliminate the stars... An omniscient being is one who knows everything logically possible for him to know... he will not necessarily know everything that will happen [i.e. humans with freewill] unless it is predetermined that it will happen..." [15]:3-15 God's perfect goodness is moral goodness.[15]:15 "Western religion has always held that there is a deep problem about why there is pain and suffering--which there would not be if God
God
were not supposed to be morally good... a personal being who was not morally good would not be the great being God
God
is supposed to be... [Since theodicy is concerned with] the existence (or not) of the sort of God
God
with which Western religion is concerned, this understanding of the definition of God
God
must stand."[15]:16 Reasons for theodicy[edit] German philosopher Max Weber
Max Weber
interpreted theodicy as a social problem,[25] and viewed theodicy as a "problem of meaning". Weber argued that, as human society became increasingly rational, the need to explain why good people suffered and evil people prospered became more important because religion casts the world as a "meaningful cosmos". Weber framed the problem of evil as the dilemma that the good can suffer and the evil can prosper, which became more important as religion became more sophisticated.[26] He identified two purposes of theodicy: to explain why good people suffer (a theodicy of suffering), and why people prosper (a theodicy of good fortune). A theodicy of good fortune seeks to justify the good fortune of people in society; Weber believed that those who are successful are not satisfied unless they can justify why they deserve to be successful.[27] For theodicies of suffering, Weber argued that three different kinds of theodicy emerged—predestination, dualism, and karma—all of which attempt to satisfy the human need for meaning, and he believed that the quest for meaning, when considered in light of suffering, becomes the problem of suffering.[28] Sociologist Peter L. Berger
Peter L. Berger
characterised religion as the human attempt to build order out of a chaotic world. He believed that humans could not accept that anything in the world was meaningless and saw theodicy as an assertion that the cosmos has meaning and order, despite evidence to the contrary.[29] Berger presented an argument similar to that of Weber, but suggested that the need for theodicy arose primarily out of the situation of human society. He believed that theodicies existed to allow individuals to transcend themselves, denying the individual in favour of the social order.[30] Philosopher Richard Swinburne
Richard Swinburne
says "most theists need a theodicy, [they need] an account of reasons why God
God
might allow evil to occur. Without a theodicy evil counts against the existence of God."[15]:2 History[edit] The term theodicy was coined by German philosopher Gottfried Leibniz in his 1710 work, written in French, Essais de Théodicée
Théodicée
sur la bonté de Dieu, la liberté de l'homme et l'origine du mal (Theodicy: Essays on the Goodness of God, the Freedom of Man and the Origin of Evil).[31] Leibniz's Théodicée
Théodicée
was a response to skeptical Protestant philosopher Pierre Bayle, who wrote in his work Dictionnaire Historique et Critique that, after rejecting three attempts to solve it, he saw no rational solution to the problem of evil. Bayle argued that, because the Bible
Bible
asserts the coexistence of God
God
and evil, this state of affairs must simply be accepted.[32] French philosopher Voltaire
Voltaire
criticised Leibniz's concept of theodicy in his Poème sur le désastre de Lisbonne (Poem on the Lisbon disaster), suggesting that the massive destruction of innocent lives caused by the Lisbon earthquake
Lisbon earthquake
demonstrated that God
God
was not providing the "best of all possible worlds".[33] Voltaire
Voltaire
also includes the earthquake/theodicy theme in his novel Candide.[34] In The Catholic Encyclopedia
The Catholic Encyclopedia
(1914), Constantine Kempf argued that, following Leibniz's work, philosophers called their works on the problem of evil "theodicies", and philosophy about God
God
was brought under the discipline of theodicy. He argued that theodicy began to include all of natural theology, meaning that theodicy came to consist of the human knowledge of God
God
through the systematic use of reason.[35] In 1966, British philosopher John Hick published Evil
Evil
and the God
God
of Love, in which he surveyed various Christian responses to the problem of evil, before developing his own.[36] In his work, Hick identified and distinguished between three types of theodicy: Plotinian, which was named after Plotinus, Augustinian, which had dominated Western Christianity for many centuries, and Irenaean, which was developed by the Eastern Church Father
Church Father
Irenaeus, a version of which Hick subscribed to himself.[37] In his dialogue "Is God
God
a Taoist?",[38] published in 1977 in his book The Tao is Silent, Raymond Smullyan
Raymond Smullyan
claims to prove that it is logically impossible to have sentient beings without allowing "evil", even for God, just as it is impossible for him to create a triangle in the Euclidean plane having an angular sum other than 180°. So the capability of feeling implies free will, which in turn may produce "evil", understood here as hurting other sentient beings. The problem of evil happening to good or innocent people is not addressed directly here, but both reincarnation and karma are hinted at.[citation needed] Ancient religions[edit] “Writings and discourses on theodicy by Jews, Greeks, Christians, and Eastern religions have graced our planet for thousands of years.”[39] In the Middle Kingdom of Egypt
Middle Kingdom of Egypt
(2000 BC to 1700 BC) as “in Ancient Mesopotamian and Israelite literature,” theodicy was an important issue.[40] Dr Philip Irving Mitchell of the Dallas Baptist University
Dallas Baptist University
notes that some philosophers have cast the pursuit of theodicy as a modern one, as earlier scholars used the problem of evil to support the existence of one particular god over another, explain wisdom, or explain a conversion, rather than to justify God's goodness.[41] Professor Sarah Iles Johnston argues that ancient civilizations, such as the ancient Mesopotamians, Greeks, Romans, and Egyptians held polytheistic beliefs that may have enabled them to deal with the concept of theodicy differently. These religions taught the existence of many gods and goddesses who controlled various aspects of daily life. These early religions may have avoided the question of theodicy by endowing their deities with the same flaws and jealousies that plagued humanity. No one god or goddess was fundamentally good or evil; this explained that bad things could happen to good people if they angered a deity because the gods could exercise the same free will that humankind possesses. Such religions taught that some gods were more inclined to be helpful and benevolent, while others were more likely to be spiteful and aggressive. In this sense, the evil gods could be blamed for misfortune, while the good gods could be petitioned with prayer and sacrifices to make things right. There was still a sense of justice in that individuals who were right with the gods could avoid punishment.[42] Biblical theodicy[edit] Main article: Theodicy
Theodicy
and the Bible The biblical account of the justification of evil and suffering in the presence of God
God
has both similarities and contrasts in the Hebrew Bible
Bible
and the New Testament. For the Hebrew Bible, the Book of Job
Book of Job
is often quoted as the authoritative source of discussion.[43] "The author of Job seeks to expand the understanding of divine justice ...beyond mere retribution, to include a system of divine sovereignty [showing] the King has the right to test His subject's loyalty... The book of Job corrects the rigid and overly simplistic doctrine of retribution in attributing suffering to sin and punishment. It closes with a focus on the bond between creator and creation, on placing one's trust in that, and on hope rooted in belief that God
God
is in ultimate control."[44]:Chapter 3:Job It is generally accepted that God's responsive speeches in Job do not directly answer Job's complaints; God
God
does not explain Himself or reveal the reason for Job's suffering to him; instead Yahweh's speeches focus on increasing Job's overall understanding of his relationship with God. This exemplifies Biblical theodicy.[45]:21,28 There is general agreement among Bible
Bible
scholars that the Bible
Bible
"does not admit of a singular perspective on evil. ...Instead we encounter a variety of perspectives... Consequently [the Bible
Bible
focuses on] moral and spiritual remedies, not rational or logical [justifications]. ...It is simply that the Bible
Bible
operates within a cosmic, moral and spiritual landscape rather than within a rationalist, abstract, ontological landscape."[46][47]:27 This is in evidence in Yahweh's first and second speech in Job. Yahweh's first speech concerns human ignorance and God's authority. Job had seen himself at the center of events, lamenting that God
God
has singled him out to oppress; God
God
responds that Job is not the center, Yahweh is; His kingdom is complex, He governs on a large scale, and has the right to exercise divine authority; since God
God
is the rightful owner of everything in the universe, Job cannot justly accuse Him of wrongful deprivation.[44]:Chapter 3:Job Yahweh's second speech is against human self-righteousness. Job has vehemently accused God
God
of thwarting justice as "the omnipotent tyrant, the cosmic thug". Some scholars interpret Yahweh's response as an admission of failure on His part, but He goes on to say He has the power and in His own timing will bring justice in the end.[44]:Chapter 3:Job "Isaiah is generally recognized as one of the most progressive books of the prophetic corpus."[48]:208 Hebrew Bible
Bible
scholar Marvin A. Sweeney says "...a unified reading of [Isaiah] places the question of theodicy at the forefront... [with] three major dimensions of the question...: Yahweh's identification with the conqueror, Yahweh's decree of judgment against Israel without possibility of repentance, and the failure of Yahweh's program to be realized by the end of the book."[48]:209 Christian theologians read some passages in Isaiah differently. "In either case, suffering is understood as having transcendent meaning... human agency can give particular instances of suffering a mystical significance that transforms it into something productive."[49] Theodicy
Theodicy
in the book of Ezekiel (and also in Jeremiah 31:29-30) confronts the concept of personal moral responsibility. "The main point is stated at the beginning and at the end--"the soul that sins shall die"--and is explicated by a case history of a family traced through three generations." It is not about heredity but is about understanding divine justice in a world under divine governance.[50]:82 " Theodicy
Theodicy
in the Minor Prophets differs little from that in Isaiah, Jeremiah and Ezekiel."[51] For example, the first chapter of Habakuk raises questions about Yahweh's justice, laments God's inaction in punishing injustice, and looks for God's action in response--then objects to what God
God
chooses.[44]:Chapter 1 Instead of engaging in debate, God
God
gives Habakuk a vision of the future which includes five oracles that form a theodicy: (1) God
God
has a plan and has appointed a time for judgment. It may be slow in coming as humans see things, but it will come. (2) The woe oracles confront the prevalence of evil in the world and the justice those acts have earned (3) The vision of the manifestation of God
God
is a recognition of God's power to address these issues (4) God
God
as a warrior will fight for his people (5) The song of triumph says the faithful will prevail by holding to trust and hope.[44]:Intro, Chapter 3 Joel and the other minor prophets demonstrate that theodicy and eschatology are connected in the Bible.[51]:201 Psalm 73 presents the internal struggle created by personal suffering and the prosperity of the wicked. The writer gains perspective when he "enters the sanctuary of God
God
(16-17)" seeing that God's justice will eventually prevail. He reaffirms his relationship with Yahweh, is ashamed of his resentment, and chooses trust. [44]:Chapter 3:Psalm 73 Psalm 77 contains real outspokenness to God
God
as well as determination to hold onto faith and trust.[44]:Chapter 3:Psalm 77 For the Christian, the Scriptures assure him or her that the allowance of evil is for a good purpose based on relationship with God.[52] "Some of the good ... cannot be achieved without delay and suffering, and the evil of this world is indeed necessary for the achievement of those good purposes. ... God
God
has the right to allow such evils to occur, so long as the 'goods' are facilitated and the 'evils' are limited and compensated in the way that various other Christian doctrines (of human freewill, life after death, the end of the world, etc.) affirm. ...the 'good states' which (according to Christian doctrine) God
God
seeks are so good that they outweigh the accompanying evils."[15]:Intro.,51 This is somewhat illustrated in the Book of Exodus
Book of Exodus
when Pharaoh is described as being raised up that God's name be known in all the earth Exodus 9:16. This is mirrored in Romans' ninth chapter, where Paul makes an appeal to God's sovereignty as sufficient explanation, with God's goodness experientially known to the Christian.[53] Augustinian theodicy[edit] Main article: Augustinian theodicy The Protestant and Reformed reading of Augustinian theodicy, as promoted primarily by John Hick, is based on the writings of Augustine of Hippo, a Christian philosopher and theologian who lived from AD 354 to 430.[54] The catholic (pre-reformation) formulation of the same issue is substantially different and is outlined below. In Hick's approach, this form of theodicy argues that evil does not exist except as a privation—or corruption—of goodness, and therefore God
God
did not create evil.[55] Augustinian scholars have argued that God
God
created the world perfectly, with no evil or human suffering. Evil
Evil
entered the world through the disobedience of Adam and Eve
Adam and Eve
and the theodicy casts the existence of evil as a just punishment for this original sin.[56] The theodicy argues that humans have an evil nature in as much as it is deprived of its original goodness, form, order, and measure due to the inherited original sin of Adam
Adam
and Eve, but still ultimately remains good due to existence coming from God, for if a nature was completely evil (deprived of the good), it would cease to exist.[57] It maintains that God
God
remains blameless and good.[58] In the Roman Catholic reading of Augustine, the issue of just war as developed in his book The City of God
God
substantially established his position concerning the positive justification of killing, suffering and pain as inflicted upon an enemy when encountered in war for a just cause.[59] Augustine asserted that peacefulness in the face of a grave wrong that could only be stopped by violence would be a sin. Defense of one's self or others could be a necessity, especially when authorized by a legitimate authority. While not elaborating the conditions necessary for war to be just, Augustine nonetheless originated the very phrase, itself, in his work The City of God.[60] In essence, the pursuit of peace must include the option of fighting with all of its eventualities in order to preserve peace in the long-term.[61] Such a war could not be pre-emptive, but defensive, to restore peace.[62] Thomas Aquinas, centuries later, used the authority of Augustine's arguments in an attempt to define the conditions under which a war could be just.[63][64] Irenaean theodicy[edit] Main article: Irenaean theodicy Irenaeus
Irenaeus
(died c. 202), born in the early second century, expressed ideas which explained the existence of evil as necessary for human development. Irenaeus
Irenaeus
argued that human creation comprised two parts: humans were made first in the image, then in the likeness, of God. The image of God
God
consists of having the potential to achieve moral perfection, whereas the likeness of God
God
is the achievement of that perfection. To achieve moral perfection, Irenaeus
Irenaeus
suggested that humans must have free will. To achieve such free will, humans must experience suffering and God
God
must be at an epistemic distance (a distance of knowledge) from humanity. Therefore, evil exists to allow humans to develop as moral agents.[65] In the twentieth century, John Hick collated the ideas of Irenaeus
Irenaeus
into a distinct theodicy. He argued that the world exists as a "vale of soul-making" (a phrase that he drew from John Keats), and that suffering and evil must therefore occur. He argued that human goodness develops through the experience of evil and suffering.[66] Origenian theodicy[edit] In direct response to John Hick's description of theodicy, Mark Scott has indicated that neither Augustine of Hippo
Augustine of Hippo
nor Irenaeus
Irenaeus
of Lyons provide an appropriate context for the discussion of Hick's theistic version of theodicy. As a theologian among the Church Fathers
Church Fathers
who articulated a theory of apokatastasis (or universal reconciliation), Origen
Origen
of Alexandria provides a more direct theological comparison for the discussion of Hick's presentation of universal salvation and theodicy. Neither Irenaeus
Irenaeus
nor Augustine endorsed a theology of universal salvation in any form comparable to that of John Hick.[67] Relatively minor theodicies[edit] Michael Martin summarizes what he calls “relatively minor” theodicies.[68]

The Finite God
God
Theodicy
Theodicy
maintains that God
God
is all-good (omnibenevolent) but not all-powerful (omnipotent). The Best of all Possible Worlds Theodicy, a traditional theology, argues that the creation is the best of all possible worlds. The Original Sin
Original Sin
Theodicy
Theodicy
holds that evil came into the world because of humanity's original sin. The Ultimate Harmony Theodicy
Theodicy
justifies evil as leading to “good long-range consequences”. The Degree of Desirability of a Conscious State Theodicy
Theodicy
has been reckoned a “complex theodicy.”[69] It argues that a person’s state is deemed evil only when it is undesirable to the person. However, because God
God
is unable to make a person’s state desirable to the person, the theodic problem does not exist.[70] The Reincarnation
Reincarnation
Theodicy
Theodicy
believes that people suffer evil because of their wrong-doing in a previous life. The Contrast Theodicy
Theodicy
holds that evil is needed to enable people to appreciate or understand good. The Warning Theodicy
Theodicy
rationalizes evil as God’s warning to people to mend their ways.

Islamic world[edit] Mu'tazila
Mu'tazila
theologians approached the problem of theodicy within a framework of moral realism, according to which the moral value of acts is accessible to unaided reason, so that humans can make moral judgments about divine acts.[71] They argued that the divine act of creation is good despite existence of suffering, because it allows humans a compensation of greater reward in the afterlife.[71] They posited that individuals have free will to commit evil and absolved God
God
of responsibility for such acts.[71] God's justice thus consists of punishing wrongdoers.[71] Following the demise of Mu'tazila
Mu'tazila
as a school, their theodicy was adopted in the Zaydi
Zaydi
and Twelver
Twelver
branches of Shia Islam.[71] Most Sunni theologians analyzed theodicy from an anti-realist metaethical standpoint.[71] Ash'ari
Ash'ari
theologians argued that ordinary moral judgments stem from emotion and social convention, which are inadequate to either condemn or justify divine actions.[71] Ash'arites hold that God
God
creates everything, including human actions, but distinguish creation (khalq) from acquisition (kasb) of actions.[72] They allow individuals the latter ability, though they do not posit existence of free will in a fuller sense of the term. In the words of Al-Shahrastani (1086–1153):[72]

God
God
creates, in man, the power, ability, choice, and will to perform an act, and man, endowed with this derived power, chooses freely one of the alternatives and intends or wills to do the action, and, corresponding to this intention, God
God
creates and completes the action.

Ash'ari
Ash'ari
theology, which dominated Sunni Islam from the tenth to the nineteenth century, also insists on ultimate divine transcendence and teaches that human knowledge regarding it is limited to what has been revealed through the prophets, so that on the question of God's creation of evil, revelation has to accepted bila kayfa (without [asking] how).[73][72] Ibn Sina, the most influential Muslim philosopher, analyzed theodicy from a purely ontological, neoplatonic standpoint, aiming to prove that God, as the absolutely good First Cause, created a good world.[71] Ibn Sina
Ibn Sina
argued that evil refers either to a cause of an entity (such as burning in a fire), being a quality of another entity, or to its imperfection (such as blindness), in which case it does not exist as an entity. According to Ibn Sina, such qualities are necessary attributes of the best possible order of things, so that the good they serve is greater than the harm they cause.[71] Philosophical Sufi theologians such as Ibn Arabi
Ibn Arabi
were influenced by the neoplatonic theodicy of Ibn Sina.[71] Al-Ghazali
Al-Ghazali
echoed the optimistic theodicy of Leibniz in his dictum "There is nothing in possibility more wonderful than what is."[74] Fakhr al-Din al-Razi, who represented the mainstream Sunni view, challenged Ibn Sina's analysis and argued that it merely sidesteps the real problem of evil, which is rooted in the human experience of suffering in a world that contains more pain than pleasure.[71] The influential Hanbali
Hanbali
scholar Ibn Taymiyya
Ibn Taymiyya
argued that, while God creates human acts, humans are responsible for their deeds as the agents of their acts.[75] He held that divine creation is good from a casual standpoint, as God
God
creates all things for wise purposes.[75] Thus apparent evil is in actuality good in view of its purpose, and pure evil does not exist.[75] This analysis was developed further with practical illustrations by Ibn al-Qayyim.[75] Alternatives[edit] Jewish anti-theodicy[edit] Main article: Holocaust
Holocaust
theology In 1998, Jewish theologian Zachary Braiterman coined the term anti-theodicy in his book (God) After Auschwitz to describe Jews, both in a biblical and post- Holocaust
Holocaust
context, whose response to the problem of evil is protest and refusal to investigate the relationship between God
God
and suffering. An anti-theodicy acts in opposition to a theodicy and places full blame for all experience of evil onto God, but must rise from an individual's belief in and love of God. Anti-theodicy has been likened to Job's protests in the Book of Job.[76] Braiterman wrote that an anti-theodicy rejects the idea that there is a meaningful relationship between God
God
and evil or that God could be justified for the experience of evil.[77] The Holocaust
Holocaust
prompted a reconsideration of theodicy in some Jewish circles.[78] French Jewish philosopher Emmanuel Levinas, who had himself been a prisoner of war in Nazi Germany, declared theodicy to be "blasphemous", arguing that it is the "source of all immorality", and demanded that the project of theodicy be ended. Levinas asked whether the idea of absolutism survived after the Holocaust, which he proposed it did. He argued that humans are not called to justify God in the face of evil, but to attempt to live godly lives; rather than considering whether God
God
was present during the Holocaust, the duty of humans is to build a world where goodness will prevail.[79] Professor of theology David R. Blumenthal, in his book Facing the Abusing God, supports the "theology of protest", which he saw as presented in the play, The Trial of God. He supports the view that survivors of the Holocaust
Holocaust
cannot forgive God
God
and so must protest about it. Blumenthal believes that a similar theology is presented in the book of Job, in which Job does not question God's existence or power, but his morality and justice.[80] Other prominent voices in the Jewish tradition commenting on the justification of God
God
in the presence of the Holocaust
Holocaust
have been the Nobel prize winning author Elie Wiesel and Richard L. Rubinstein in his book The Cunning of History.[81] Rabbi Menachem Mendel Schneerson, the seventh Rebbe of Chabad Lubavitch, sought to elucidate how faith (or trust, emunah) in God defines the full, transcendental preconditions of anti-theodicy. Endorsing the attitude of "holy protest" found in the stories of Job and Jeremiah, but also in those of Abraham (Genesis 18) and Moses (Exodus 33), Rabbi Schneerson argued that a phenomenology of protest, when carried through to its logical limits, reveals a profound conviction in cosmic justice such, as we first find in Abraham's question: "Will the Judge of the whole earth not do justice?" (Genesis 18:25). Recalling Kant's 1791 essay on the failure of all theoretical attempts in theodicy,[82] a viable practical theodicy is identified with messianism. This faithful anti-theodicy is worked out in a long letter of 26 April 1965 to Elie Wiesel.[83] Christian alternatives to theodicy[edit] A number of Christian writers oppose theodicies. Todd Billings deems constructing theodicies to be a “destructive practice”.[84] In the same vein, Nick Trakakis observes that “theodical discourse can only add to the world’s evils, not remove or illuminate them.”[85] As an alternative to theodicy, some theologians have advocated “reflection on tragedy” as a more befitting reply to evil.[86] For example, Wendy Farley believes that “a desire for justice” and “anger and pity at suffering” should replace “theodicy’s cool justifications of evil”.[87] Sarah K. Pinnock opposes abstract theodicies that would legitimize evil and suffering. However, she endorses theodicy discussions in which people ponder God, evil, and suffering from a practical faith perspective.[88] Karl Barth
Karl Barth
viewed the evil of human suffering as ultimately in the “control of divine providence”.[89] Given this view, Barth deemed it impossible for humans to devise a theodicy that establishes "the idea of the goodness of God".[90] For Barth only the crucifixion could establish the goodness of God. In the crucifixion, God
God
bears and suffers what humanity suffers.[91] This suffering by God
God
Himself makes human theodicies anticlimactic.[92] Barth found a “twofold justification” in the crucifixion:[93] the justification of sinful humanity and “the justification in which God
God
justifies Himself”.[94] Christian Science
Christian Science
offers a rational, though widely unacceptable, solution to the problem by denying that evil ultimately exists.[95][96] Mary Baker Eddy
Mary Baker Eddy
and Mark Twain
Mark Twain
had some contrasting views on theodicy and suffering, which are well-described by Stephen Gottschalk.[97] Redemptive suffering based in Pope John Paul II's theology of the body embraces suffering as having value in and of itself.[98][99] Eleonore Stump in "Wandering in Darkness" uses psychology, narrative and exegesis to demonstrate that redemptive suffering, as found in Thomistic theodicy, can constitute a consistent and cogent defence for the problem of suffering.[100] Free will
Free will
defense[edit] See also: Theodicy
Theodicy
and the Bible
Bible
§  Bible
Bible
and free will theodicy As an alternative to a theodicy, a defense may be offered as a response to the problem of evil. A defense attempts to show that God's existence is not made logically impossible by the existence of evil; it does not need to be true or plausible, merely logically possible.[according to whom?] American philosopher Alvin Plantinga offers a free will defense which argues that human free will sufficiently explains the existence of evil while maintaining that God's existence remains logically possible.[101] He argues that, if God's existence and the existence of evil are to be logically inconsistent, a premise must be provided which, if true, would make them inconsistent; as none has been provided, the existence of God
God
and evil must be consistent. Free will
Free will
furthers this argument by providing a premise which, in conjunction with the existence of evil, entails that God's existence remains consistent.[102] Opponents have argued this defense is discredited by the existence of non-human related evil such as droughts, tsunamis and malaria.[103] Cosmodicy and anthropodicy[edit] A cosmodicy attempts to justify the fundamental goodness of the universe in the face of evil, and an anthropodicy attempts to justify the fundamental goodness of human nature in the face of the evils produced by humans.[104] Considering the relationship between theodicy and cosmodicy, Johannes van der Ven argued that the choice between theodicy and cosmodicy is a false dilemma.[105] Philip E. Devenish proposed what he described as "a nuanced view in which theodicy and cosmodicy are rendered complementary, rather than alternative concepts".[106] Theologian J. Matthew Ashley described the relationship between theodicy, cosmodicy and anthropodicy:

In classical terms, this is to broach the problem of theodicy: how to think about God
God
in the face of the presence of suffering in God's creation. After God's dethronement as the subject of history, the question rebounds to the new subject of history: the human being. As a consequence, theodicy becomes anthropodicy – justifications of our faith in humanity as the subject of history, in the face of the suffering that is so inextricably woven into the history that humanity makes.[107]

Essential kenosis[edit] Essential kenosis is a form of process theology, (also known as "open theism") that allows one to affirm that God
God
is almighty, while simultaneously affirming that God
God
cannot prevent genuine evil. Because out of love God
God
necessarily gives freedom, agency, self-organization, natural processes, and law-like regularities to creation, God
God
cannot override, withdraw, or fail to provide such capacities. Consequently, God
God
is not culpable for failing to prevent genuine evil. Thomas Jay Oord's work explains this view most fully.[108][109] Gijsbert van den Brink effectively refutes any view which says God
God
has restricted His power because of his love saying it creates a "metaphysical dualism", and it would not alleviate God's responsibility for evil because God
God
could have prevented evil by not restricting himself. Van den Brink goes on to elaborate an explanation of power and love within the Trinitarian view which equates power and love, and what he calls "the power of love" as representative of God's involvement in the struggle against evil.[110] See also[edit]

Religion
Religion
portal

Dystheism Misotheism Problem of hell Global justice

References[edit]

^ Philip A. Pecorino, An Introduction to Philosophy: An Online Textbook (2000), Chapter 3: ‘Philosophy of Religion’, Section 11: Problem of Evil, online at http://www.qcc.cuny.edu/SocialSciences/ppecorino/INTRO_TEXT/Chapter%203%20Religion/Problem_of_Evil.htm. Retrieved September 26, 2015. ^ A defence is “an effort to show that there is no formal contradiction between the existence of God... and the existence of evil.” Michael Rea and Louis B. Pojman, eds., Philosophy of Religion: An Anthology (Cengage Learning, 2015, 7th ed.), 229. ^ Richard Swedberg, Ola Agevall, The Max Weber
Max Weber
Dictionary: Key Words and Central Concepts (Stanford University Press, 2005), 274. ^ Peter L. Berger, The Sacred Canopy: Elements of a Sociological Theory of Religion
Religion
(Doubleday, 1st ed, 1967), 55. ^ Plantinga, Alvin (1974). God, Freedom, and Evil, William B. Eerdmans Publishing Company, p. 10. ^ http://www.thefreedictionary.com/theodicy and Anthony J. Tambasco, ed. (2002). The Bible
Bible
on Suffering. New York: Paulist Press. p. 1. ISBN 0809140489.  ^ "δίκη". A Greek–English Lexicon. ^ Encyclopædia Britannica Online, s. v. "theodicy", accessed October 20, 2013. ^ a b Trakakis, Nick (March 31, 2005). "The Evidential Problem of Evil". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved January 16, 2012.  ^ Bunnin & Tsui-James 2002, p. 481 ^ Geivett 1995, pp. 60–61 ^ a b c d e f g Calder, Todd, "The Concept of Evil", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2016 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/concept-evil/> ^ Nieman, Susan. Evil
Evil
in Modern Thought: An Alternative History of Philosophy. Princeton, New Jersey: Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-0-691-16850-0.  ^ a b c d e Wright, N. T. (2006). Evil
Evil
and the Justice of God. Downer's Grove, Illinois: Intervarsity Press. ISBN 978-0-8308-3415-0.  ^ a b c d e f g h i Swinburne, Richard (1998). Providence and the Problem of Evil. Oxford, England: Oxford University Press. ISBN 0-19-823799-5.  ^ O'Brien, D., 1996, “ Plotinus
Plotinus
on matter and evil,” in The Cambridge Companion to Plotinus, L.P. Gerson (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 171–195. ^ Plotinus, The Enneads, S. Mackenna (trans.), London: Faber, 4th edition, revised by B.S. Page, 1969. ^ Kant, Immanuel (2003). Kant: Religion
Religion
Within the Boundaries of Mere Reason: And Other Writings. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-59049-3.  ^ Locke, John (1836). An Essay Concerning Human
Human
Understanding. Glasgow: B.Griffin and Co.  ^ Hobbes, Thomas (2018). Leviathan. Minneapolis, Minnesota: Lerner Publishing Group. ISBN 978 151 248609 4.  ^ Liebniz, Gottfried Wilhelm (2009). Theodicy. Cosimo books. ISBN 978-1-61640-295-2.  ^ Thera, Nyanaponika (2008). The Roots of Good and Evil: Buddhist Texts translated from the Pali. ISBN 978-955-24-0316-3.  ^ Okello, Joseph B. Onyango (2017). Evil
Evil
and Pain: A Critique of the Materialistic Account of Evil. Eugene, Oregon: Wipf and Stock. ISBN 978-1-5326-0134-7.  ^ Leaman, Oliver (1995). Evil
Evil
and Suffering in Jewish Philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-41724-4.  ^ Swedberg 2005, pp. 273–74 ^ Scott 2009, p. 2 ^ Swedberg 2005, p. 275 ^ Scott 2009, p. 4 ^ Scott 2009, pp. 5–7 ^ Woodhead 2001, p. 74 ^ Leibniz 1734 ^ Lennon, Thomas (7 February 2003). "Pierre Bayle". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved January 22, 2012.  ^ Voltaire, Candide
Candide
and Poème sur le désastre de Lisbonne ^ Mason (1992), p. 10 ^ Kempf, Constantine (2012). "Theodicy". The Catholic Encyclopedia. Retrieved September 4, 2012.  ^ Cheetham 2003, p. 40 ^ Hall 2003, p. 132 ^ Smullyan 1977, p. 86 ^ Birnbaum, David (1989). God
God
and Evil. Hoboken: Ktav Pub. House. p. 4 ^ Assman, Jan (2001). The Search for God
God
in Ancient Egypt
Ancient Egypt
trans. David Lorton. Cornell University Press. 169 ^ Mitchell, Dr Philip Irving. "Theodicy: An Overview". Dallas Baptist University. Retrieved July 17, 2012.  ^ Johnston 2004, pp. 531–47 ^ The Old Testament. Modern Library Edition, Introduction, authored by George Steiner. ^ a b c d e f g Ko, Grace (2014). Theodicy
Theodicy
in Habakkuk. United Kingdom: Paternoster.  ^ Pathways in Theodicy: An Introduction to the Problem of Evil
Evil
By Mark S. M. Scott ^ Pathways in Theodicy: An Introduction to the Problem of Evil, By Mark S. M. Scott ^ Scott, Mark S. M. (2015). Pathways in Theodicy: An Introduction to the Problem of Evil. Fortress Press. ISBN 978-1-4514-6470-2.  ^ a b Linafelt, Tod, ed. (2000). Strange Fire: Reading the Bible
Bible
After the Holocaust. New York University Press. ISBN 0-8147-5165-2.  ^ Pinnock, Sarah K. (2002). Beyond Theodicy: Jewish and Christian Continental Thinkers Respond to the Holocaust. New York: State University of New York Press. ISBN 0-7914-5523-8.  ^ Blenkinsopp, Joseph (1990). Ezekiel. Louisville: John Knox Press. ISBN 0-8042-3118-4.  ^ a b Redditt, Paul L (2003). Thematic Threads in the Book of the Twelve. New York: Walter De Gruyter. ISBN 3-11-017594-0.  ^ John M. Frame and Joseph E. Torres, Apologetics: A Justification of Christian Belief (Phillipsburg, NJ: P&R Publishing, 2015), 184. ^ Apologetics, Frame 178–79. ^ Mendelson, Michael (24 March 2000; substantive revision 12 November 2010). "Saint Augustine". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 9 October 2011.  Check date values in: date= (help) ^ Menn 2002, p. 170 ^ Corey 2000, pp. 177–78 ^ Green 2011, p. 779 ^ Geivett 1995, p. 19 ^ A Time For War? Christianity Today (2001-01-09). Retrieved on 2013-04-28. ^ Augustine of Hippo
Augustine of Hippo
Archived 2012-07-28 at Archive.is. Crusades-encyclopedia.com. Retrieved on 2013-04-28. ^ St. Augustine of Hippo
Augustine of Hippo
Archived 2012-07-28 at Archive.is, Crusades-Encyclopedia ^ Saint Augustine and the Theory of Just War. Jknirp.com (2007-01-23). Retrieved on 2013-04-28. ^ The Just War. Catholiceducation.org. Retrieved on 2013-04-28. ^ Gonzalez, Justo L. (1984). The Story of Christianity. San Francisco: Harper. ISBN 006185588X.  ^ Davis 2001, pp. 40-42 ^ Stump 1999, pp. 222–27 ^ Scott, Mark (2012). Origen
Origen
and the Problem of Evil, Oxford University Press. ^ Michael Martin, Atheism: A Philosophical Justification (Temple University Press, 1992), 436–54. ^ Ramblings of a Thomist, Blog of March 27, 2008 http://thomisticramblings.blogspot.com/2008/03/minor-theodicies-and.html. Accessed September 25, 2015. ^ Michael Martin, Atheism: A Philosophical Justification (Temple University Press, 1992), 444–45. Martin finds this theodicy in George Schlesinger, Religion
Religion
and Scientific Method (Springer Science & Business Media, 2012) and judges it unsatisfactory. ^ a b c d e f g h i j k Ayman Shihadeh (2005). "Suffering". In Josef W. Meri. Medieval Islamic Civilization: An Encyclopedia. Routledge. p. 772.  ^ a b c Roy Jackson. What is Islamic Philosophy?. Routledge. pp. 32–33.  ^ Tamara Sonn (2009). "Tawḥīd". In John L. Esposito. The Oxford Encyclopedia of the Islamic World. Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Subscription required (help)).  ^ Michael L. Peterson (2011). "Religious Diversity, Evil, and a Variety of Theodicies". In Chad Meister. The Oxford Handbook of Religious Diversity. p. 162. (Subscription required (help)).  ^ a b c d Hoover, Jon (2014). "Ḥanbalī Theology". In Sabine Schmidtke. The Oxford Handbook of Islamic Theology. Oxford: Oxford University Press. p. 642. (Subscription required (help)).  ^ Marty & Taliaferro 2010, p. 17 ^ Gibbs & Wolfson 2002, p. 38 ^ Pinnock 2002, p. 8 ^ Patterson & Roth 2005, pp. 189–90 ^ Blumenthal 1993, pp. 250–51 ^ Rubinstein, Richard L. The Cunning of History. ^ Über das Misslingen aller philosophischen Versuche in der Theodizee http://cas.uchicago.edu/workshops/germanphilosophy/files/2013/02/Kant-On-the-Miscarriage-of-all-Philosophical-Trials-at-Theodicy.pdf ^ http://www.chighel.com/opening-statement-7a/ The original letter in YIddish is found in R. Menachem Mendel Schneerson, Likutei Siḥot, Vol. 33 (New York: Kehot, 1962–2001), pp. 255–60. ^ Todd Billings, " Theodicy
Theodicy
as a 'Lived Question': Moving Beyond a Theoretical Approach to Theodicy", http://www.luthersem.edu/ctrf/JCTR/Vol05/billings.htm Accessed September 25, 2013. About the author: http://www.westernsem.edu/about/faculty-staff/. ^ Nick Trakakis, “Theodicy: The Solution to the Problem of Evil, or Part of the Problem?”, Springerlink.com, accessed December 19, 2009. ^ Donald W. Musser and Joseph L. Price, eds., A New Handbook of Christian Theology
Theology
(Abingdon Press, 1992), s.v. “Tragedy.” ^ Wendy Farley, Tragic Vision and Divine Compassion: a Contemporary Theodicy
Theodicy
(Westminster John Knox Press, 1990) 12, 23. ^ Sarah Katherine Pinnock, Beyond Theodicy
Theodicy
(SUNY Press, 2002), 135, 141. ^ Karl Barth, Church Dogmatics (T & T Clark, 1957), IV-1, 246. ^ Barth, Church Dogmatics, III-1, 368. ^ Barth, Church Dogmatics, II-2, 165. ^ Barth, Church Dogmatics, IV-1, 246. ^ Barth, Church Dogmatics, II-2, 223. ^ Barth, Church Dogmatics, IV-1, 564. ^ Ben Dupre, "The Problem of Evil", 50 Philosophy Ideas You Really Need to Know, London, Quercus, 2007, p. 166: "Denying that there is ultimately any such thing as evil, as advocated by Christian Scientists, solves the problem at a stroke, but such a remedy is too hard for most to swallow." ^ Whale, J. S. The Christian answer to the problem of evil. 1948 ^ "Rolling Away the Stone: Mary Baker Eddy's Challenge to Materialism" (Indiana University Press, 2006) 83, 123, etc. ^ Reimers, Adrian J. " Human
Human
Suffering and Jon Paul II's Theology
Theology
of the Body".  ^ "Catholicprimer.org" (PDF). www.catholicprimer.org.  ^ Stump, Eleonore (2010). Wandering in Darkness: Narrative and the Problem of Suffering. N.Y. New York: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-927742-1.  ^ McGrath 1995, p. 193 ^ Plantinga & Sennett 1998, pp. 22–24 ^ Bart D. Ehrman (13 October 2009). God's Problem: How the Bible
Bible
Fails to Answer Our Most Important Question – Why We Suffer. HarperCollins. p. 12. ISBN 978-0-06-174440-2.  ^ Carsten Meiner, Kristin Veel, eds., The Cultural Life of Catastrophes and Crises (Walter de Gruyter, 2012), 243. ^ van der Ven 1989, p. 205 ^ Devenish 1992, pp. 5–23 ^ Ashley 2010, pp. 870–902 ^ Oord, Thomas Jay (2015-12-06). The Uncontrolling Love of God: An Open and Relational Account of Providence. IVP Academic. ISBN 9780830840847.  ^ Oord, Dr Thomas (2010-04-10). The Nature of Love: A Theology. Chalice Press.  ^ "van den Brink", Gijsbert (1993). Almighty God: A Study on the Doctrine of Divine Omnipotence. Kampen, the Netherlands: Kok Pharos publishing House. pp. 263–73. 

Bibliography[edit]

Adams, Marilyn McCord (1999). Horrendous Evils and the Goodness of God. Cornell University Press. ISBN 978-0-80148-686-9.  Ashley, J. Matthew (2010). "Reading the universe story theologically: the contribution of a biblical narrative imagination". Theological Studies. 71 (4).  Assman, Jan (2001). The Search for God
God
in Ancient Egypt
Ancient Egypt
trans. David Lorton. Cornell University Press Birnbaum, David (1989). God
God
and Evil. Ktav Publishing House Blumenthal, David R. (1993). Facing the Abusing God: A Theology
Theology
of Protest. Westminster John Knox Press. ISBN 978-0-66425-464-3.  Bunnin, Nicholas; Tsui James, E. P. (2002). The Blackwell Companion to Philosophy. John Wiley & Sons. ISBN 9780631219088.  Cheetham, David (2003). John Hick: a critical introduction and reflection. Ashgate Publishing. ISBN 978-0-7546-1599-6.  Davis, Stephen T. (2001). Encountering evil: live options in theodicy. Westminster John Knox Press. ISBN 978-0-664-22251-2.  Devenish, Philip E. (1992). " Theodicy
Theodicy
and Cosmodicy: The Contribution of Neoclassical Theism". Journal of Empirical Theology. 4.  Ehrman, Bart D. (2008). God's Problem:How the Bible
Bible
Fails to Answer Our Most Important Question – Why We Suffer. HarperCollins Publishers. ISBN 978-0-06-117397-4.  Geiviett, R. Douglas (1995). Evil
Evil
& the Evidence For God: The Challenge of John Hick's Theodicy. Temple University Press. ISBN 978-1-56639-397-3.  Inati, Shams C. (2000). The Problem of Evil: Ibn Sînâ's Theodicy. ISBN 1586840061. Global Academic Publishing, Binghamton University, New York. Gibbs, Robert; Wolfson, Elliot (2002). Suffering religion. Psychology Press. ISBN 978-0-415-26612-3.  Hall, Lindsey (2003). Swinburne's hell and Hick's universalism: are we free to reject God?. Ashgate Publishing. ISBN 978-0-7546-3400-3.  Johnston, Sarah Iles (2004). Religions of the Ancient World: A Guide. Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-01517-3.  Leibniz, Gottfried (1734). Theodicy.  Marty, Marty; Taliaferro, Charles (2010). Dictionary of Philosophy of Religion. Continuum International Publishing Group. ISBN 978-1-4411-1197-5.  McGrath, Alister (1995). The Blackwell encyclopedia of modern Christian thought. Wiley-Blackwell. ISBN 978-0-631-19896-3.  Neiman, Susan. Evil
Evil
in Modern Thought: An Alternative History of Philosophy, 2002, Princeton: Princeton University Press. Revised edition, 2015. Oord, Thomas Jay (2015), The Uncontrolling Love of God. Intervarsity Academic. ISBN 978-0830840847 Patterson, David; Roth, John (2005). Fire in the ashes: God, evil, and the Holocaust. University of Washington Press. ISBN 978-0-295-98547-3.  Pinnock, Sarah Katherine (2002). Beyond theodicy: Jewish and Christian continental thinkers respond to the Holocaust. SUNY Press. ISBN 978-0-7914-5523-4.  Plantinga, Alvin; Sennett, James (1998). The analytic theist: an Alvin Plantinga reader. Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing. ISBN 978-0-8028-4229-9.  Scott, Mark S. M. (2009). "Theorising Theodicy
Theodicy
in the Study of Religion" (PDF). University of Chicago Divinity School.  Sharma, Arvind (2006). A primal perspective on the philosophy of religion. Springer. ISBN 978-1-4020-5013-8.  Smullyan, Raymond (1977). The Tao is Silent. Harper. ISBN 978-0-06-067469-4.  Stump, Eleonore (1999). Philosophy of religion: the big questions. Wiley-Blackwell. ISBN 978-0-631-20604-0.  Svendsen, Lars Fr. H.; Pierce, Kerri A. (2010). A philosophy of evil. Dalkey Archive Press. ISBN 1-56478-571-8.  Swedberg, Richard (2005). The Max Weber
Max Weber
Dictionary: Key Words and Central Concepts. Stanford University Press. ISBN 978-0-80475-095-0.  van der Ven, Johannes A. (1989). " Theodicy
Theodicy
or cosmodicy: a false dilemma?". Journal of Empirical Theology. 2 (1).  Woo, B. Hoon (2014). "Is God
God
the Author of Sin? – Jonathan Edwards's Theodicy". Puritan Reformed Journal. 6 (1): 98–123.  Woodhead, Linda (2001). Peter Berger and the Study of Religion. Routledge. ISBN 978-0-41521-532-9. 

External links[edit]

Brown, Paterson. "Religious Morality", Mind, 1963. Brown, Paterson. "Religious Morality: a Reply to Flew and Campbell", Mind, 1964. Brown, Paterson. " God
God
and the Good", Religious Studies, 1967. "Theodicy", Catholic Encyclopedia, New advent . The Polkinghorne Reader: Science, Faith, and the Search for Meaning (edited by Thomas Jay Oord; SPCK and Templeton Foundation Press, 2010) ISBN 1-59947-315-1 and ISBN 978-0-281-06053-5. Why Does God
God
Allow It? Article discussing men's responsibility on the one hand and his powerlessness regarding natural disasters on the other hand.

v t e

Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz

Mathematics and philosophy

Alternating series test Best of all possible worlds Calculus ratiocinator Characteristica universalis Difference Identity of indiscernibles Law of Continuity Leibniz wheel Leibniz's gap Pre-established harmony Principle of sufficient reason Salva veritate Theodicy Transcendental law of homogeneity Vis viva Well-founded phenomenon

Works

De Arte Combinatoria
De Arte Combinatoria
(1666) Discourse on Metaphysics
Metaphysics
(1686) New Essays on Human
Human
Understanding (1704) Théodicée
Théodicée
(1710) Monadology
Monadology
(1714) Leibniz–Clarke correspondence
Leibniz–Clarke correspondence
(1715–1716)

Other

Calculus controversy

v t e

Hamartiology

Adam Good and evil The Fall Original sin Christian views on sin Imputation of sin Other views on sin Logical order of God's decrees Theodicy Total depravity

See also Apologetics Soteriology Demonology

v t e

Philosophy of religion

Concepts in religion

Afterlife Euthyphro dilemma Faith Intelligent design Miracle Problem of evil Religious belief Soul Spirit Theodicy Theological veto

Conceptions of God

Aristotelian view Brahman Demiurge Divine simplicity Egoism Holy Spirit Misotheism Pandeism Personal god Process theology Supreme Being Unmoved mover

God
God
in

Abrahamic religions Buddhism Christianity Hinduism Islam Jainism Judaism Mormonism Sikhism Bahá'í Faith Wicca

Existence of God

For

Beauty Christological Consciousness Cosmological

Kalam Contingency

Degree Desire Experience Fine-tuning of the Universe Love Miracles Morality Necessary existent Ontological Pascal's Wager Proper basis Reason Teleological

Natural law Watchmaker analogy

Transcendental

Against

747 gambit Atheist's Wager Evil Free will Hell Inconsistent revelations Nonbelief Noncognitivism Occam's razor Omnipotence Poor design Russell's teapot

Theology

Acosmism Agnosticism Animism Antireligion Atheism Creationism Dharmism Deism Demonology Divine command theory Dualism Esotericism Exclusivism Existentialism

Christian Agnostic Atheistic

Feminist theology

Thealogy Womanist theology

Fideism Fundamentalism Gnosticism Henotheism Humanism

Religious Secular Christian

Inclusivism Theories about religions Monism Monotheism Mysticism Naturalism

Metaphysical Religious Humanistic

New Age Nondualism Nontheism Pandeism Panentheism Pantheism Perennialism Polytheism Possibilianism Process theology Religious skepticism Spiritualism Shamanism Taoic Theism Transcendentalism more...

Religious language

Eschatological verification Language-game Logical positivism Apophatic theology Verificationism

Problem of evil

Augustinian theodicy Best of all possible worlds Euthyphro dilemma Inconsistent triad Irenaean theodicy Natural evil Theodicy

Philosophers of religion

(by date active)

Ancient and Medieval

Anselm of Canterbury Augustine of Hippo Avicenna Averroes Boethius Erasmus Gaunilo of Marmoutiers Pico della Mirandola Heraclitus King James VI and I Marcion of Sinope Thomas Aquinas Maimonides

Enlightenment

Augustin Calmet René Descartes Blaise Pascal Baruch Spinoza Nicolas Malebranche Gottfried W Leibniz William Wollaston Thomas Chubb David Hume Baron d'Holbach Immanuel Kant Johann G Herder

1800 1850

Friedrich Schleiermacher Karl C F Krause Georg W F Hegel

William Whewell Ludwig Feuerbach Søren Kierkegaard Karl Marx Albrecht Ritschl Afrikan Spir

1880 1900

Ernst Haeckel W. K. Clifford Friedrich Nietzsche Harald Høffding William James

Vladimir Solovyov Ernst Troeltsch Rudolf Otto Lev Shestov Sergei Bulgakov Pavel Florensky Ernst Cassirer Joseph Maréchal

1920 postwar

George Santayana Bertrand Russell Martin Buber René Guénon Paul Tillich Karl Barth Emil Brunner Rudolf Bultmann Gabriel Marcel Reinhold Niebuhr

Charles Hartshorne Mircea Eliade Frithjof Schuon J L Mackie Walter Kaufmann Martin Lings Peter Geach George I Mavrodes William Alston Antony Flew

1970 1990 2010

William L Rowe Dewi Z Phillips Alvin Plantinga Anthony Kenny Nicholas Wolterstorff Richard Swinburne Robert Merrihew Adams

Peter van Inwagen Daniel Dennett Loyal Rue Jean-Luc Marion William Lane Craig Ali Akbar Rashad

Alexander Pruss

Related topics

Criticism of religion Ethics in religion Exegesis History of religions Religion Religious language Religious philosophy Relationship between religion and science Political science of religion Faith
Faith
and rationality more...

.