inductive type
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
type theory In mathematics and theoretical computer science, a type theory is the formal presentation of a specific type system. Type theory is the academic study of type systems. Some type theories serve as alternatives to set theory as a foundation of ...
, a system has inductive types if it has facilities for creating a new type from constants and functions that create terms of that type. The feature serves a role similar to
data structure In computer science, a data structure is a data organization and storage format that is usually chosen for Efficiency, efficient Data access, access to data. More precisely, a data structure is a collection of data values, the relationships amo ...
s in a programming language and allows a type theory to add concepts like
number A number is a mathematical object used to count, measure, and label. The most basic examples are the natural numbers 1, 2, 3, 4, and so forth. Numbers can be represented in language with number words. More universally, individual numbers can ...
s, relations, and trees. As the name suggests, inductive types can be self-referential, but usually only in a way that permits structural recursion. The standard example is encoding the
natural number In mathematics, the natural numbers are the numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, and so on, possibly excluding 0. Some start counting with 0, defining the natural numbers as the non-negative integers , while others start with 1, defining them as the positive in ...
s using Peano's encoding. It can be defined in Rocq (previously known as ''Coq'') as follows: Inductive nat : Type := , 0 : nat , S : nat -> nat. Here, a natural number is created either from the constant "0" or by applying the function "S" to another natural number. "S" is the successor function which represents adding 1 to a number. Thus, "0" is zero, "S 0" is one, "S (S 0)" is two, "S (S (S 0))" is three, and so on. Since their introduction, inductive types have been extended to encode more and more structures, while still being predicative and supporting structural recursion.


Elimination

Inductive types usually come with a function to prove properties about them. Thus, "nat" may come with (in Rocq syntax): nat_elim : (forall P : nat -> Prop, (P 0) -> (forall n, P n -> P (S n)) -> (forall n, P n)). In words: for any predicate "P" over natural numbers, given a proof of "P 0" and a proof of "P n -> P (n+1)", we get back a proof of "forall n, P n". This is the familiar induction principle for natural numbers.


Implementations


W- and M-types

W-types are well-founded types in intuitionistic type theory (ITT). They generalize natural numbers, lists, binary trees, and other "tree-shaped" data types. Let be a universe of types. Given a type : and a dependent family : → , one can form a W-type \mathsf_ B(a). The type may be thought of as "labels" for the (potentially infinitely many) constructors of the inductive type being defined, whereas indicates the (potentially infinite)
arity In logic, mathematics, and computer science, arity () is the number of arguments or operands taken by a function, operation or relation. In mathematics, arity may also be called rank, but this word can have many other meanings. In logic and ...
of each constructor. W-types (resp. M-types) may also be understood as well-founded (resp. non-well-founded) trees with nodes labeled by elements : and where the node labeled by has ()-many subtrees. Each W-type is isomorphic to the initial algebra of a so-called polynomial functor. Let 0, 1, 2, etc. be finite types with inhabitants 11 : 1, 12, 22:2, etc. One may define the natural numbers as the W-type \mathbb:= \mathsf_ f(x) with : 2 → is defined by (12) = 0 (representing the constructor for zero, which takes no arguments), and (22) = 1 (representing the successor function, which takes one argument). One may define lists over a type : as \operatorname(A) := \mathsf_ f(x) where \begin f(\operatorname(1_)) &= \mathbf \\ f(\operatorname(a)) &= \mathbf \end and 11 is the sole inhabitant of 1. The value of f(\operatorname(1_)) corresponds to the constructor for the empty list, whereas the value of f(\operatorname(a)) corresponds to the constructor that appends to the beginning of another list. The constructor for elements of a generic W-type \mathsf_B(x) has type \mathsf:\prod_\Big(B(a)\to\mathsf_B(x)\Big)\to \mathsf_B(x). We can also write this rule in the style of a natural deduction proof, \frac. The elimination rule for W-types works similarly to structural induction on trees. If, whenever a property (under the propositions-as-types interpretation) C : \mathsf_B(x) \to U holds for all subtrees of a given tree it also holds for that tree, then it holds for all trees. \frac In extensional type theories, W-types (resp. M-types) can be defined up to isomorphism as
initial algebra In mathematics, an initial algebra is an initial object in the Category (mathematics), category of F-algebra, -algebras for a given endofunctor . This initiality provides a general framework for mathematical induction, induction and recursion. ...
s (resp. final coalgebras) for polynomial functors. In this case, the property of initiality (res. finality) corresponds directly to the appropriate induction principle. In intensional type theories with the univalence axiom, this correspondence holds up to homotopy (propositional equality). M-types are dual to W-types, and represent coinductive (potentially infinite) data such as streams. M-types can be derived from W-types.


Mutually inductive definitions

This technique allows ''some'' definitions of multiple types that depend on each other. For example, defining two parity predicates on
natural number In mathematics, the natural numbers are the numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, and so on, possibly excluding 0. Some start counting with 0, defining the natural numbers as the non-negative integers , while others start with 1, defining them as the positive in ...
s using two mutually inductive types in Rocq: Inductive even : nat -> Prop := , zero_is_even : even O , S_of_odd_is_even : (forall n:nat, odd n -> even (S n)) with odd : nat -> Prop := , S_of_even_is_odd : (forall n:nat, even n -> odd (S n)).


Induction-recursion

Induction-recursion started as a study into the limits of ITT. Once found, the limits were turned into rules that allowed defining new inductive types. These types could depend upon a function and the function on the type, as long as both were defined simultaneously. Universe types can be defined using induction-recursion.


Induction-induction

Induction-induction allows definition of a type and a family of types at the same time. So, a type and a family of types B : A \to Type.


Higher inductive types

This is a current research area in Homotopy Type Theory (HoTT). HoTT differs from ITT by its identity type (equality). Higher inductive types not only define a new type with constants and functions that create elements of the type, but also new instances of the identity type that relate them. A simple example is the type, which is defined with two constructors, a basepoint; : and a loop; : The existence of a new constructor for the identity type makes a higher inductive type.


See also

* Coinduction permits (effectively) infinite structures in type theory.


References

* {{cite book, author=Univalent Foundations Program, title=Homotopy Type Theory: Univalent Foundations of Mathematics, year=2013, publisher=Institute for Advanced Study, url=http://homotopytypetheory.org/book/


External links


Induction-Recursion Slides

Induction-Induction Slides

Higher Inductive Types: a tour of the menagerie
Type theory