dynamic semantics
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

Dynamic semantics is a framework in
logic Logic is the study of correct reasoning. It includes both formal and informal logic. Formal logic is the study of deductively valid inferences or logical truths. It examines how conclusions follow from premises based on the structure o ...
and natural language semantics that treats the meaning of a sentence as its potential to update a context. In static semantics, knowing the meaning of a sentence amounts to knowing when it is true; in dynamic semantics, knowing the meaning of a sentence means knowing "the change it brings about in the information state of anyone who accepts the news conveyed by it." In dynamic semantics, sentences are mapped to functions called ''context change potentials'', which take an input context and return an output context. Dynamic semantics was originally developed by Irene Heim and
Hans Kamp Johan Anthony Willem "Hans" Kamp (born 5 September 1940) is a Dutch philosopher and Linguistics, linguist, responsible for introducing discourse representation theory (DRT) in 1981. Biography Kamp was born in Den Burg. He received a Ph.D. in UC ...
in 1981 to model anaphora, but has since been applied widely to phenomena including presupposition, plurals,
questions A question is an utterance which serves as a request for information. Questions are sometimes distinguished from interrogatives, which are the grammar, grammatical forms, typically used to express them. Rhetorical questions, for instance, are i ...
, discourse relations, and modality.


Dynamics of anaphora

The first systems of dynamic semantics were the closely related ''File Change Semantics'' and '' discourse representation theory'', developed simultaneously and independently by Irene Heim and
Hans Kamp Johan Anthony Willem "Hans" Kamp (born 5 September 1940) is a Dutch philosopher and Linguistics, linguist, responsible for introducing discourse representation theory (DRT) in 1981. Biography Kamp was born in Den Burg. He received a Ph.D. in UC ...
. These systems were intended to capture donkey anaphora, which resists an elegant compositional treatment in classic approaches to semantics such as Montague grammar. Donkey anaphora is exemplified by the infamous donkey sentences, first noticed by the medieval logician Walter Burley and brought to modern attention by Peter Geach. ::Donkey sentence (relative clause): Every farmer who owns a donkey beats it. ::Donkey sentence (conditional): If a farmer owns a donkey, he beats it. To capture the empirically observed truth conditions of such sentences in first order logic, one would need to translate the indefinite noun phrase "a donkey" as a universal quantifier scoping over the variable corresponding to the pronoun "it". :: FOL translation of donkey sentence: : \forall x \forall y (\,(\text (x) \land \text(y) \land \text(x,y)) \rightarrow \text(x,y)\,) While this translation captures (or approximates) the truth conditions of the natural language sentences, its relationship to the syntactic form of the sentence is puzzling in two ways. First, indefinites in non-donkey contexts normally express existential rather than universal quantification. Second, the syntactic position of the donkey pronoun would not normally allow it to be bound by the indefinite. To explain these peculiarities, Heim and Kamp proposed that natural language indefinites are special in that they introduce a new ''discourse referent'' that remains available outside the syntactic scope of the operator that introduced it. To cash this idea out, they proposed their respective formal systems that capture donkey anaphora because they validate ''Egli's theorem'' and its corollary. ::Egli's theorem: (\exists x \varphi) \land \psi \Leftrightarrow \exists x (\varphi \land \psi) ::Egli's corollary: (\exists x \phi \rightarrow \psi) \Leftrightarrow \forall x(\phi \rightarrow \psi )


Update semantics

''Update semantics'' is a framework within dynamic semantics that was developed by Frank Veltman. In update semantics, each formula \varphi is mapped to a function varphi/math> that takes and returns a ''discourse context''. Thus, if C is a context, then C varphi/math> is the context one gets by updating C with \varphi . Systems of update semantics vary both in how they define a context and in the semantic entries they assign to formulas. The simplest update systems are ''intersective'' ones, which simply lift static systems into the dynamic framework. However, update semantics includes systems more expressive than what can be defined in the static framework. In particular, it allows ''information sensitive'' semantic entries, in which the information contributed by updating with some formula can depend on the information already present in the context. This property of update semantics has led to its widespread application to presuppositions, modals, and conditionals.


Intersective update

An update with \varphi is called ''intersective'' if it amounts to taking the intersection of the input context with the proposition denoted by \varphi. Crucially, this definition assumes that there is a single fixed proposition that \varphi always denotes, regardless of the context. * Intersective update: Let ![\varphi!">varphi.html" ;"title="![\varphi">![\varphi! be the proposition denoted by \varphi. Then \varphi is ''intersective'' if and only if for any C , we have that C varphi= C \cap ![\varphi!">varphi.html" ;"title="![\varphi">![\varphi! Intersective update was proposed by Robert Stalnaker">varphi">![\varphi!">varphi.html" ;"title="![\varphi">![\varphi! Intersective update was proposed by Robert Stalnaker in 1978 as a way of formalizing the speech act of assertion. In Stalnaker's original system, a context (or ''context set'') is defined as a set of possible worlds representing the information in the common ground of a conversation. For instance, if C = \ this represents a scenario where the information agreed upon by all participants in the conversation indicates that the actual world must be either w, v, or u. If ![\varphi!">varphi.html" ;"title="![\varphi">![\varphi!= \, then updating C with \varphi would return a new context C varphi= \. Thus, an assertion of \varphi would be understood as an attempt to rule out the possibility that the actual world is u . From a formal perspective, intersective update can be taken as a recipe for lifting one's preferred static semantics to dynamic semantics. For instance, if we take classical propositional semantics as our starting point, this recipe delivers the following intersective update semantics. * Intersective update semantics based on classical propositional logic: # C = \ # C neg \varphi= C - C varphi # C varphi \land \psi= C varphi\cap C psi # C varphi \lor \psi= C varphi\cup C psi The notion of intersectivity can be decomposed into the two properties known as ''eliminativity'' and ''distributivity''. Eliminativity says that an update can only ever remove worlds from the context—it can't add them. Distributivity says that updating C with \varphi is equivalent to updating each singleton subset of C with \varphi and then pooling the results. * Eliminativity: \varphi is ''eliminative'' iff C varphi\subseteq C for all contexts C * Distributivity: \varphi is ''distributive'' iff C varphi= \bigcup\ Intersectivity amounts to the conjunction of these two properties, as proven by Johan van Benthem.


The test semantics for modals

The framework of update semantics is more general than static semantics because it is not limited to intersective meanings. Nonintersective meanings are theoretically useful because they contribute different information depending on what information is already present in the context. For instance, if \varphi is intersective, then it will update any input context with the exact same information, namely the information encoded by the proposition ![\varphi!">varphi.html" ;"title="![\varphi">![\varphi!/math>. On the other hand, if \varphi is nonintersective, it could contribute ![\varphi!">varphi.html" ;"title="![\varphi">![\varphi!/math> when it updates some contexts, but some completely different information when it updates other contexts. Many natural language expressions have been argued to have nonintersective meanings. The nonintersectivity of epistemic modals can be seen in the infelicity of ''epistemic contradictions''. :Epistemic contradiction: #It's raining and it might not be raining. These sentences have been argued to be bona fide logical contradictions, unlike superficially similar examples such as Moore sentences, which can be given a pragmatics (linguistics)">pragmatic explanation. :Epistemic contradiction principle: \varphi \land \Diamond \neg \varphi \models \bot These sentences cannot be analysed as logical contradictions within purely intersective frameworks such as the relational semantics for modal logic. The Epistemic Contradiction Principle only holds on the class of Kripke frame, relational frames such that Rwv \Rightarrow (w=v) . However, such frames also validate an entailment from \Diamond \varphi to \varphi. Thus, accounting for the infelicity of epistemic contradictions within a classical semantics for modals would bring along the unwelcome prediction that "It might be raining" entails "It is raining". Update Semantics skirts this problem by providing a nonintersective denotation for modals. When given such a denotation, the formula \Diamond \neg \varphi can update input contexts differently depending on whether they already contain the information that \varphi provides. The most widely adopted semantic entry for modals in update semantics is the ''test semantics'' proposed by Frank Veltman. *The test semantics for modals: C Diamond \varphi = \begin C & \text C varphi\neq \varnothing \\ \varnothing & \text \end On this semantics, \Diamond \varphi tests whether the input context could be updated with \varphi without getting trivialized, i.e. without returning the empty set. If the input context passes the test, it remains unchanged. If it fails the test, the update trivializes the context by returning the empty set. This semantics can handle epistemic contradictions because no matter the input context, updating with \varphi will always output a context that fails the test imposed by \Diamond \neg \varphi .For a complete derivation of the Epistemic Contradiction Principle within Update Semantics, see for instance Goldstein (2016), p. 13. This derivation crucially depends on a particular definition of entailment, as well as an intersective semantic entry for \neg and a treatment of \land as updating consecutively with the conjuncts in their linear order.


See also

* Conversational scoreboard * Donkey anaphora * Discourse representation theory *
Formal semantics of programming languages In programming language theory, semantics is the rigorous mathematical study of the meaning of programming languages. Semantics assigns computational meaning to valid string (computer science), strings in a programming language syntax. It is cl ...
*
Hans Kamp Johan Anthony Willem "Hans" Kamp (born 5 September 1940) is a Dutch philosopher and Linguistics, linguist, responsible for introducing discourse representation theory (DRT) in 1981. Biography Kamp was born in Den Burg. He received a Ph.D. in UC ...
* Import-Export * Irene Heim *
Modal logic Modal logic is a kind of logic used to represent statements about Modality (natural language), necessity and possibility. In philosophy and related fields it is used as a tool for understanding concepts such as knowledge, obligation, and causality ...
*
Scope (formal semantics) In formal semantics (linguistics), formal semantics, the scope of a semantic operator is the semantic object to which it applies. For instance, in the sentence "''Paulina doesn't drink beer but she does drink wine''," the proposition that Paulina ...


Notes


External links


Dynamic Semantics, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Dynamic Semantics Notes, Daniel Rothschild

Dynamic Semantics and Pragmatic Alternatives, ESSLLI 2017 Course Notes
{{Non-classical logic Semantics Logic Philosophy of language Non-classical logic Systems of formal logic Linguistic modality