context change potential
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

Dynamic semantics is a framework in
logic Logic is the study of correct reasoning. It includes both formal and informal logic. Formal logic is the study of deductively valid inferences or logical truths. It examines how conclusions follow from premises based on the structure o ...
and
natural language semantics Semantics is the study of linguistic meaning. It examines what meaning is, how words get their meaning, and how the meaning of a complex expression depends on its parts. Part of this process involves the distinction between sense and referenc ...
that treats the meaning of a sentence as its potential to update a context. In static semantics, knowing the meaning of a sentence amounts to knowing when it is true; in dynamic semantics, knowing the meaning of a sentence means knowing "the change it brings about in the information state of anyone who accepts the news conveyed by it." In dynamic semantics, sentences are mapped to functions called ''context change potentials'', which take an input context and return an output context. Dynamic semantics was originally developed by
Irene Heim Irene Roswitha Heim (born October 30, 1954) is a linguist and a leading specialist in semantics. She was a professor at the University of Texas at Austin and UCLA before moving to the Massachusetts Institute of Technology in 1989, where she is Pr ...
and
Hans Kamp Johan Anthony Willem "Hans" Kamp (born 5 September 1940) is a Dutch philosopher and Linguistics, linguist, responsible for introducing discourse representation theory (DRT) in 1981. Biography Kamp was born in Den Burg. He received a Ph.D. in UC ...
in 1981 to model anaphora, but has since been applied widely to phenomena including
presupposition In linguistics and philosophy, a presupposition is an implicit assumption about the world or background belief relating to an utterance whose truth is taken for granted in discourse. Examples of presuppositions include: * ''Jane no longer writes ...
,
plurals In many languages, a plural (sometimes abbreviated as pl., pl, , or ), is one of the values of the grammatical category of number. The plural of a noun typically denotes a quantity greater than the default quantity represented by that noun. This ...
,
questions A question is an utterance which serves as a request for information. Questions are sometimes distinguished from interrogatives, which are the grammar, grammatical forms, typically used to express them. Rhetorical questions, for instance, are i ...
,
discourse relation A discourse relation (also coherence relation or rhetorical relation) is a description of how two segments of discourse are logically and/or structurally connected to one another. A widely upheld position is that in Coherence (linguistics), coheren ...
s, and
modality Modality may refer to: Humanities * Modality (theology), the organization and structure of the church, as distinct from sodality or parachurch organizations * Modality (music), in music, the subject concerning certain diatonic scales * Modalit ...
.


Dynamics of anaphora

The first systems of dynamic semantics were the closely related ''File Change Semantics'' and ''
discourse representation theory In formal linguistics, discourse representation theory (DRT) is a framework for exploring meaning under a formal semantics approach. One of the main differences between DRT-style approaches and traditional Montagovian approaches is that DRT inc ...
'', developed simultaneously and independently by
Irene Heim Irene Roswitha Heim (born October 30, 1954) is a linguist and a leading specialist in semantics. She was a professor at the University of Texas at Austin and UCLA before moving to the Massachusetts Institute of Technology in 1989, where she is Pr ...
and
Hans Kamp Johan Anthony Willem "Hans" Kamp (born 5 September 1940) is a Dutch philosopher and Linguistics, linguist, responsible for introducing discourse representation theory (DRT) in 1981. Biography Kamp was born in Den Burg. He received a Ph.D. in UC ...
. These systems were intended to capture donkey anaphora, which resists an elegant compositional treatment in classic approaches to semantics such as
Montague grammar Montague grammar is an approach to natural language semantics, named after American logician Richard Montague. The Montague grammar is based on mathematical logic, especially higher-order predicate logic and lambda calculus, and makes use of th ...
. Donkey anaphora is exemplified by the infamous donkey sentences, first noticed by the medieval logician Walter Burley and brought to modern attention by
Peter Geach Peter Thomas Geach (29 March 1916 – 21 December 2013) was a British philosopher who was Professor of Logic at the University of Leeds. His areas of interest were philosophical logic, ethics, history of philosophy, philosophy of religion and ...
. ::Donkey sentence (relative clause): Every farmer who owns a donkey beats it. ::Donkey sentence (conditional): If a farmer owns a donkey, he beats it. To capture the empirically observed truth conditions of such sentences in
first order logic First-order logic, also called predicate logic, predicate calculus, or quantificational logic, is a collection of formal systems used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. First-order logic uses quantified variables over ...
, one would need to translate the indefinite noun phrase "a donkey" as a
universal quantifier In mathematical logic, a universal quantification is a type of quantifier, a logical constant which is interpreted as "given any", "for all", "for every", or "given an arbitrary element". It expresses that a predicate can be satisfied by e ...
scoping over the variable corresponding to the pronoun "it". :: FOL translation of donkey sentence: : \forall x \forall y (\,(\text (x) \land \text(y) \land \text(x,y)) \rightarrow \text(x,y)\,) While this translation captures (or approximates) the truth conditions of the natural language sentences, its relationship to the syntactic form of the sentence is puzzling in two ways. First, indefinites in non-donkey contexts normally express existential rather than universal quantification. Second, the syntactic position of the donkey pronoun would not normally allow it to be bound by the indefinite. To explain these peculiarities, Heim and Kamp proposed that natural language indefinites are special in that they introduce a new ''discourse referent'' that remains available outside the syntactic scope of the operator that introduced it. To cash this idea out, they proposed their respective formal systems that capture donkey anaphora because they validate ''Egli's theorem'' and its corollary. ::Egli's theorem: (\exists x \varphi) \land \psi \Leftrightarrow \exists x (\varphi \land \psi) ::Egli's corollary: (\exists x \phi \rightarrow \psi) \Leftrightarrow \forall x(\phi \rightarrow \psi )


Update semantics

''Update semantics'' is a framework within dynamic semantics that was developed by Frank Veltman. In update semantics, each formula \varphi is mapped to a function
varphi Phi ( ; uppercase Φ, lowercase φ or ϕ; ''pheî'' ; Modern Greek: ''fi'' ) is the twenty-first letter of the Greek alphabet. In Archaic and Classical Greek (c. 9th to 4th century BC), it represented an aspirated voiceless bilabial plos ...
/math> that takes and returns a ''discourse context''. Thus, if C is a context, then C
varphi Phi ( ; uppercase Φ, lowercase φ or ϕ; ''pheî'' ; Modern Greek: ''fi'' ) is the twenty-first letter of the Greek alphabet. In Archaic and Classical Greek (c. 9th to 4th century BC), it represented an aspirated voiceless bilabial plos ...
/math> is the context one gets by updating C with \varphi . Systems of update semantics vary both in how they define a context and in the semantic entries they assign to formulas. The simplest update systems are ''intersective'' ones, which simply lift static systems into the dynamic framework. However, update semantics includes systems more expressive than what can be defined in the static framework. In particular, it allows ''information sensitive'' semantic entries, in which the information contributed by updating with some formula can depend on the information already present in the context. This property of update semantics has led to its widespread application to
presupposition In linguistics and philosophy, a presupposition is an implicit assumption about the world or background belief relating to an utterance whose truth is taken for granted in discourse. Examples of presuppositions include: * ''Jane no longer writes ...
s, modals, and conditionals.


Intersective update

An update with \varphi is called ''intersective'' if it amounts to taking the intersection of the input context with the proposition denoted by \varphi. Crucially, this definition assumes that there is a single fixed proposition that \varphi always denotes, regardless of the context. * Intersective update: Let ![\varphi!">varphi.html" ;"title="![\varphi">![\varphi! be the proposition denoted by \varphi. Then \varphi is ''intersective'' if and only if for any C , we have that C
varphi Phi ( ; uppercase Φ, lowercase φ or ϕ; ''pheî'' ; Modern Greek: ''fi'' ) is the twenty-first letter of the Greek alphabet. In Archaic and Classical Greek (c. 9th to 4th century BC), it represented an aspirated voiceless bilabial plos ...
= C \cap ![\varphi!">varphi.html" ;"title="![\varphi">![\varphi! Intersective update was proposed by Robert Stalnaker">varphi">![\varphi!">varphi.html" ;"title="![\varphi">![\varphi! Intersective update was proposed by Robert Stalnaker in 1978 as a way of formalizing the speech act of assertion. In Stalnaker's original system, a context (or ''context set'') is defined as a set of possible worlds representing the information in the common ground of a conversation. For instance, if C = \ this represents a scenario where the information agreed upon by all participants in the conversation indicates that the actual world must be either w, v, or u. If ![\varphi!">varphi.html" ;"title="![\varphi">![\varphi!= \, then updating C with \varphi would return a new context C
varphi Phi ( ; uppercase Φ, lowercase φ or ϕ; ''pheî'' ; Modern Greek: ''fi'' ) is the twenty-first letter of the Greek alphabet. In Archaic and Classical Greek (c. 9th to 4th century BC), it represented an aspirated voiceless bilabial plos ...
= \. Thus, an assertion of \varphi would be understood as an attempt to rule out the possibility that the actual world is u . From a formal perspective, intersective update can be taken as a recipe for lifting one's preferred static semantics to dynamic semantics. For instance, if we take classical propositional semantics as our starting point, this recipe delivers the following intersective update semantics. * Intersective update semantics based on classical propositional logic: # C = \ # C neg \varphi= C - C
varphi Phi ( ; uppercase Φ, lowercase φ or ϕ; ''pheî'' ; Modern Greek: ''fi'' ) is the twenty-first letter of the Greek alphabet. In Archaic and Classical Greek (c. 9th to 4th century BC), it represented an aspirated voiceless bilabial plos ...
# C varphi \land \psi= C
varphi Phi ( ; uppercase Φ, lowercase φ or ϕ; ''pheî'' ; Modern Greek: ''fi'' ) is the twenty-first letter of the Greek alphabet. In Archaic and Classical Greek (c. 9th to 4th century BC), it represented an aspirated voiceless bilabial plos ...
\cap C
psi Psi, PSI or Ψ may refer to: Alphabetic letters * Psi (Greek) (Ψ or ψ), the twenty-third letter of the Greek alphabet * Psi (Cyrillic), letter of the early Cyrillic alphabet, adopted from Greek Arts and entertainment * "Psi" as an abbreviat ...
# C varphi \lor \psi= C
varphi Phi ( ; uppercase Φ, lowercase φ or ϕ; ''pheî'' ; Modern Greek: ''fi'' ) is the twenty-first letter of the Greek alphabet. In Archaic and Classical Greek (c. 9th to 4th century BC), it represented an aspirated voiceless bilabial plos ...
\cup C
psi Psi, PSI or Ψ may refer to: Alphabetic letters * Psi (Greek) (Ψ or ψ), the twenty-third letter of the Greek alphabet * Psi (Cyrillic), letter of the early Cyrillic alphabet, adopted from Greek Arts and entertainment * "Psi" as an abbreviat ...
The notion of intersectivity can be decomposed into the two properties known as ''eliminativity'' and ''distributivity''. Eliminativity says that an update can only ever remove worlds from the context—it can't add them. Distributivity says that updating C with \varphi is equivalent to updating each singleton subset of C with \varphi and then pooling the results. * Eliminativity: \varphi is ''eliminative'' iff C
varphi Phi ( ; uppercase Φ, lowercase φ or ϕ; ''pheî'' ; Modern Greek: ''fi'' ) is the twenty-first letter of the Greek alphabet. In Archaic and Classical Greek (c. 9th to 4th century BC), it represented an aspirated voiceless bilabial plos ...
\subseteq C for all contexts C * Distributivity: \varphi is ''distributive'' iff C
varphi Phi ( ; uppercase Φ, lowercase φ or ϕ; ''pheî'' ; Modern Greek: ''fi'' ) is the twenty-first letter of the Greek alphabet. In Archaic and Classical Greek (c. 9th to 4th century BC), it represented an aspirated voiceless bilabial plos ...
= \bigcup\ Intersectivity amounts to the conjunction of these two properties, as proven by Johan van Benthem.


The test semantics for modals

The framework of update semantics is more general than static semantics because it is not limited to intersective meanings. Nonintersective meanings are theoretically useful because they contribute different information depending on what information is already present in the context. For instance, if \varphi is intersective, then it will update any input context with the exact same information, namely the information encoded by the proposition ![\varphi!">varphi.html" ;"title="![\varphi">![\varphi!/math>. On the other hand, if \varphi is nonintersective, it could contribute ![\varphi!">varphi.html" ;"title="![\varphi">![\varphi!/math> when it updates some contexts, but some completely different information when it updates other contexts. Many natural language expressions have been argued to have nonintersective meanings. The nonintersectivity of epistemic modals can be seen in the infelicity of ''epistemic contradictions''. :Epistemic contradiction: #It's raining and it might not be raining. These sentences have been argued to be bona fide logical contradictions, unlike superficially similar examples such as Moore sentences, which can be given a pragmatics (linguistics)">pragmatic explanation. :Epistemic contradiction principle: \varphi \land \Diamond \neg \varphi \models \bot These sentences cannot be analysed as logical contradictions within purely intersective frameworks such as the relational semantics for modal logic. The Epistemic Contradiction Principle only holds on the class of Kripke frame, relational frames such that Rwv \Rightarrow (w=v) . However, such frames also validate an entailment from \Diamond \varphi to \varphi. Thus, accounting for the infelicity of epistemic contradictions within a classical semantics for modals would bring along the unwelcome prediction that "It might be raining" entails "It is raining". Update Semantics skirts this problem by providing a nonintersective denotation for modals. When given such a denotation, the formula \Diamond \neg \varphi can update input contexts differently depending on whether they already contain the information that \varphi provides. The most widely adopted semantic entry for modals in update semantics is the ''test semantics'' proposed by Frank Veltman. *The test semantics for modals: C Diamond \varphi = \begin C & \text C
varphi Phi ( ; uppercase Φ, lowercase φ or ϕ; ''pheî'' ; Modern Greek: ''fi'' ) is the twenty-first letter of the Greek alphabet. In Archaic and Classical Greek (c. 9th to 4th century BC), it represented an aspirated voiceless bilabial plos ...
\neq \varnothing \\ \varnothing & \text \end On this semantics, \Diamond \varphi tests whether the input context could be updated with \varphi without getting trivialized, i.e. without returning the empty set. If the input context passes the test, it remains unchanged. If it fails the test, the update trivializes the context by returning the empty set. This semantics can handle epistemic contradictions because no matter the input context, updating with \varphi will always output a context that fails the test imposed by \Diamond \neg \varphi .For a complete derivation of the Epistemic Contradiction Principle within Update Semantics, see for instance Goldstein (2016), p. 13. This derivation crucially depends on a particular definition of entailment, as well as an intersective semantic entry for \neg and a treatment of \land as updating consecutively with the conjuncts in their linear order.


See also

*
Conversational scoreboard In linguistics and philosophy of language, the conversational scoreboard is a tuple which represents the discourse context at a given point in a conversation. The scoreboard is updated by each speech act performed by one of the interlocutors. M ...
* Donkey anaphora *
Discourse representation theory In formal linguistics, discourse representation theory (DRT) is a framework for exploring meaning under a formal semantics approach. One of the main differences between DRT-style approaches and traditional Montagovian approaches is that DRT inc ...
*
Formal semantics of programming languages In programming language theory, semantics is the rigorous mathematical study of the meaning of programming languages. Semantics assigns computational meaning to valid string (computer science), strings in a programming language syntax. It is cl ...
*
Hans Kamp Johan Anthony Willem "Hans" Kamp (born 5 September 1940) is a Dutch philosopher and Linguistics, linguist, responsible for introducing discourse representation theory (DRT) in 1981. Biography Kamp was born in Den Burg. He received a Ph.D. in UC ...
* Import-Export *
Irene Heim Irene Roswitha Heim (born October 30, 1954) is a linguist and a leading specialist in semantics. She was a professor at the University of Texas at Austin and UCLA before moving to the Massachusetts Institute of Technology in 1989, where she is Pr ...
*
Modal logic Modal logic is a kind of logic used to represent statements about Modality (natural language), necessity and possibility. In philosophy and related fields it is used as a tool for understanding concepts such as knowledge, obligation, and causality ...
*
Scope (formal semantics) In formal semantics (linguistics), formal semantics, the scope of a semantic operator is the semantic object to which it applies. For instance, in the sentence "''Paulina doesn't drink beer but she does drink wine''," the proposition that Paulina ...


Notes


External links


Dynamic Semantics, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Dynamic Semantics Notes, Daniel Rothschild

Dynamic Semantics and Pragmatic Alternatives, ESSLLI 2017 Course Notes
{{Non-classical logic Semantics Logic Philosophy of language Non-classical logic Systems of formal logic Linguistic modality