In
universal algebra and in
model theory
In mathematical logic, model theory is the study of the relationship between theory (mathematical logic), formal theories (a collection of Sentence (mathematical logic), sentences in a formal language expressing statements about a Structure (mat ...
, a structure consists of a
set along with a collection of
finitary operations and
relations that are defined on it.
Universal algebra studies structures that generalize the
algebraic structure
In mathematics, an algebraic structure or algebraic system consists of a nonempty set ''A'' (called the underlying set, carrier set or domain), a collection of operations on ''A'' (typically binary operations such as addition and multiplicatio ...
s such as
groups,
rings,
fields and
vector space
In mathematics and physics, a vector space (also called a linear space) is a set (mathematics), set whose elements, often called vector (mathematics and physics), ''vectors'', can be added together and multiplied ("scaled") by numbers called sc ...
s. The term universal algebra is used for structures of
first-order theories with no
relation symbols.
Model theory
In mathematical logic, model theory is the study of the relationship between theory (mathematical logic), formal theories (a collection of Sentence (mathematical logic), sentences in a formal language expressing statements about a Structure (mat ...
has a different scope that encompasses more arbitrary
first-order theories, including
foundational structures such as models of
set theory
Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies Set (mathematics), sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory – as a branch of mathema ...
.
From the model-theoretic point of view, structures are the objects used to define the semantics of
first-order logic, cf. also
Tarski's theory of truth or
Tarskian semantics.
For a given theory in model theory, a structure is called a model if it satisfies the defining axioms of that theory, although it is sometimes disambiguated as a ''
semantic model'' when one discusses the notion in the more general setting of
mathematical model
A mathematical model is an abstract and concrete, abstract description of a concrete system using mathematics, mathematical concepts and language of mathematics, language. The process of developing a mathematical model is termed ''mathematical m ...
s. Logicians sometimes refer to structures as "
interpretations", whereas the term "interpretation" generally has a different (although related) meaning in model theory; see
interpretation (model theory).
In
database theory, structures with no functions are studied as models for relational
database
In computing, a database is an organized collection of data or a type of data store based on the use of a database management system (DBMS), the software that interacts with end users, applications, and the database itself to capture and a ...
s, in the form of
relational models.
History
In the context of mathematical logic, the term "
model
A model is an informative representation of an object, person, or system. The term originally denoted the plans of a building in late 16th-century English, and derived via French and Italian ultimately from Latin , .
Models can be divided in ...
" was first applied in 1940 by the philosopher
Willard Van Orman Quine
Willard Van Orman Quine ( ; known to his friends as "Van"; June 25, 1908 – December 25, 2000) was an American philosopher and logician in the analytic tradition, recognized as "one of the most influential philosophers of the twentieth century" ...
, in a reference to mathematician
Richard Dedekind (1831–1916), a pioneer in the development of
set theory
Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies Set (mathematics), sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory – as a branch of mathema ...
. Since the 19th century, one main method for proving the consistency of a set of axioms has been to provide a model for it.
Definition
Formally, a structure can be defined as a triple
consisting of a
domain a
signature
A signature (; from , "to sign") is a depiction of someone's name, nickname, or even a simple "X" or other mark that a person writes on documents as a proof of identity and intent. Signatures are often, but not always, Handwriting, handwritt ...
and an interpretation function
that indicates how the signature is to be interpreted on the domain. To indicate that a structure has a particular signature
one can refer to it as a
-structure.
Domain
The domain of a structure is an arbitrary set; it is also called the of the structure, its (especially in universal algebra), its (especially in model theory, cf.
universe
The universe is all of space and time and their contents. It comprises all of existence, any fundamental interaction, physical process and physical constant, and therefore all forms of matter and energy, and the structures they form, from s ...
), or its . In classical first-order logic, the definition of a structure prohibits the
empty domain.
Sometimes the notation
or
is used for the domain of
but often no notational distinction is made between a structure and its domain (that is, the same symbol
refers both to the structure and its domain.)
Signature
The signature
of a structure consists of:
* a set
of
function symbols and
relation symbols, along with
* a function
that ascribes to each symbol
a
natural number
In mathematics, the natural numbers are the numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, and so on, possibly excluding 0. Some start counting with 0, defining the natural numbers as the non-negative integers , while others start with 1, defining them as the positive in ...
The
natural number
In mathematics, the natural numbers are the numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, and so on, possibly excluding 0. Some start counting with 0, defining the natural numbers as the non-negative integers , while others start with 1, defining them as the positive in ...
of a symbol
is called the arity of
because it is the
arity
In logic, mathematics, and computer science, arity () is the number of arguments or operands taken by a function, operation or relation. In mathematics, arity may also be called rank, but this word can have many other meanings. In logic and ...
of the interpretation of
Since the signatures that arise in
algebra
Algebra is a branch of mathematics that deals with abstract systems, known as algebraic structures, and the manipulation of expressions within those systems. It is a generalization of arithmetic that introduces variables and algebraic ope ...
often contain only function symbols, a signature with no relation symbols is called an
algebraic signature. A structure with such a signature is also called an algebra; this should not be confused with the notion of an
algebra over a field
In mathematics, an algebra over a field (often simply called an algebra) is a vector space equipped with a bilinear map, bilinear product (mathematics), product. Thus, an algebra is an algebraic structure consisting of a set (mathematics), set to ...
.
Interpretation function
The interpretation function
of
assigns functions and relations to the symbols of the signature. To each function symbol
of arity
is assigned an
-ary function
on the domain. Each relation symbol
of arity
is assigned an
-ary relation
on the domain. A nullary (
-ary) function symbol
is called a
constant symbol, because its interpretation
can be identified with a constant element of the domain.
When a structure (and hence an interpretation function) is given by context, no notational distinction is made between a symbol
and its interpretation
For example, if
is a binary function symbol of
one simply writes
rather than
Examples
The standard signature
for
fields consists of two binary function symbols
and
where additional symbols can be derived, such as a unary function symbol
(uniquely determined by
) and the two constant symbols
and
(uniquely determined by
and
respectively).
Thus a structure (algebra) for this signature consists of a set of elements
together with two binary functions, that can be enhanced with a unary function, and two distinguished elements; but there is no requirement that it satisfy any of the field axioms. The
rational number
In mathematics, a rational number is a number that can be expressed as the quotient or fraction of two integers, a numerator and a non-zero denominator . For example, is a rational number, as is every integer (for example,
The set of all ...
s
the
real number
In mathematics, a real number is a number that can be used to measure a continuous one- dimensional quantity such as a duration or temperature. Here, ''continuous'' means that pairs of values can have arbitrarily small differences. Every re ...
s
and the
complex number
In mathematics, a complex number is an element of a number system that extends the real numbers with a specific element denoted , called the imaginary unit and satisfying the equation i^= -1; every complex number can be expressed in the for ...
s
like any other field, can be regarded as
-structures in an obvious way:
In all three cases we have the standard signature given by
with
and
The interpretation function
is:
:
is addition of rational numbers,
:
is multiplication of rational numbers,
:
is the function that takes each rational number
to
and
:
is the number
and
:
is the number
and
and
are similarly defined.
[Note: and on the left refer to signs of and on the right refer to natural numbers of and to the unary operation ''minus'' in ]
But the ring
of
integer
An integer is the number zero (0), a positive natural number (1, 2, 3, ...), or the negation of a positive natural number (−1, −2, −3, ...). The negations or additive inverses of the positive natural numbers are referred to as negative in ...
s, which is not a field, is also a
-structure in the same way. In fact, there is no requirement that of the field axioms hold in a
-structure.
A signature for
ordered field
In mathematics, an ordered field is a field together with a total ordering of its elements that is compatible with the field operations. Basic examples of ordered fields are the rational numbers and the real numbers, both with their standard ord ...
s needs an additional binary relation such as
or
and therefore structures for such a signature are not algebras, even though they are of course
algebraic structure
In mathematics, an algebraic structure or algebraic system consists of a nonempty set ''A'' (called the underlying set, carrier set or domain), a collection of operations on ''A'' (typically binary operations such as addition and multiplicatio ...
s in the usual, loose sense of the word.
The ordinary signature for set theory includes a single binary relation
A structure for this signature consists of a set of elements and an interpretation of the
relation as a binary relation on these elements.
Induced substructures and closed subsets
is called an
(induced) substructure of
if
*
and
have the same signature
* the domain of
is contained in the domain of
and
* the interpretations of all function and relation symbols agree on
The usual notation for this relation is
A subset
of the domain of a structure
is called closed if it is closed under the functions of
that is, if the following condition is satisfied: for every natural number
every
-ary function symbol
(in the signature of
) and all elements
the result of applying
to the
-tuple
is again an element of
For every subset
there is a smallest closed subset of
that contains
It is called the closed subset generated by
or the hull of
and denoted by
or
. The operator
is a
finitary closure operator on the
set of subsets of
.
If
and
is a closed subset, then
is an induced substructure of
where
assigns to every symbol of σ the restriction to
of its interpretation in
Conversely, the domain of an induced substructure is a closed subset.
The closed subsets (or induced substructures) of a structure form a
lattice. The
meet of two subsets is their intersection. The
join of two subsets is the closed subset generated by their union. Universal algebra studies the lattice of substructures of a structure in detail.
Examples
Let
be again the standard signature for fields. When regarded as
-structures in the natural way, the
rational number
In mathematics, a rational number is a number that can be expressed as the quotient or fraction of two integers, a numerator and a non-zero denominator . For example, is a rational number, as is every integer (for example,
The set of all ...
s form a substructure of the
real number
In mathematics, a real number is a number that can be used to measure a continuous one- dimensional quantity such as a duration or temperature. Here, ''continuous'' means that pairs of values can have arbitrarily small differences. Every re ...
s, and the real numbers form a substructure of the
complex number
In mathematics, a complex number is an element of a number system that extends the real numbers with a specific element denoted , called the imaginary unit and satisfying the equation i^= -1; every complex number can be expressed in the for ...
s. The rational numbers are the smallest substructure of the real (or complex) numbers that also satisfies the field axioms.
The set of integers gives an even smaller substructure of the real numbers which is not a field. Indeed, the integers are the substructure of the real numbers generated by the empty set, using this signature. The notion in abstract algebra that corresponds to a substructure of a field, in this signature, is that of a
subring, rather than that of a
subfield.
The most obvious way to define a
graph is a structure with a signature
consisting of a single binary relation symbol
The vertices of the graph form the domain of the structure, and for two vertices
and
means that
and
are connected by an edge. In this encoding, the notion of induced substructure is more restrictive than the notion of
subgraph. For example, let
be a graph consisting of two vertices connected by an edge, and let
be the graph consisting of the same vertices but no edges.
is a subgraph of
but not an induced substructure. The notion in
graph theory
In mathematics and computer science, graph theory is the study of ''graph (discrete mathematics), graphs'', which are mathematical structures used to model pairwise relations between objects. A graph in this context is made up of ''Vertex (graph ...
that corresponds to induced substructures is that of
induced subgraphs.
Homomorphisms and embeddings
Homomorphisms
Given two structures
and
of the same signature σ, a (σ-)homomorphism from
to
is a
map that preserves the functions and relations. More precisely:
* For every ''n''-ary function symbol ''f'' of σ and any elements
, the following equation holds:
::
.
* For every ''n''-ary relation symbol ''R'' of σ and any elements
, the following implication holds:
::
where
,
is the interpretation of the relation symbol
of the object theory in the structure
,
respectively.
A homomorphism ''h'' from
to
is typically denoted as
, although technically the function ''h'' is between the domains
,
of the two structures
,
.
For every signature σ there is a
concrete
Concrete is a composite material composed of aggregate bound together with a fluid cement that cures to a solid over time. It is the second-most-used substance (after water), the most–widely used building material, and the most-manufactur ...
category σ-Hom which has σ-structures as objects and σ-homomorphisms as
morphisms
In mathematics, a morphism is a concept of category theory that generalizes structure-preserving maps such as homomorphism between algebraic structures, functions from a set to another set, and continuous functions between topological spaces. Al ...
.
A homomorphism
is sometimes called strong if:
* For every ''n''-ary relation symbol ''R'' of the object theory and any elements
such that
, there are
such that
and
The strong homomorphisms give rise to a subcategory of the category σ-Hom that was defined above.
Embeddings
A (σ-)homomorphism
is called a (σ-)embedding if it is
one-to-one and
* for every ''n''-ary relation symbol ''R'' of σ and any elements
, the following equivalence holds:
::
(where as before
,
refers to the interpretation of the relation symbol ''R'' of the object theory σ in the structure
,
respectively).
Thus an embedding is the same thing as a strong homomorphism which is one-to-one.
The category σ-Emb of σ-structures and σ-embeddings is a concrete
subcategory of σ-Hom.
Induced substructures correspond to
subobject In category theory, a branch of mathematics, a subobject is, roughly speaking, an object that sits inside another object in the same category. The notion is a generalization of concepts such as subsets from set theory, subgroups from group theory ...
s in σ-Emb. If σ has only function symbols, σ-Emb is the subcategory of
monomorphisms of σ-Hom. In this case induced substructures also correspond to subobjects in σ-Hom.
Example
As seen above, in the standard encoding of graphs as structures the induced substructures are precisely the induced subgraphs. However, a
homomorphism between graphs is the same thing as a homomorphism between the two structures coding the graph. In the example of the previous section, even though the subgraph ''H'' of ''G'' is not induced, the identity map id: ''H'' → ''G'' is a homomorphism. This map is in fact a
monomorphism in the category σ-Hom, and therefore ''H'' is a
subobject In category theory, a branch of mathematics, a subobject is, roughly speaking, an object that sits inside another object in the same category. The notion is a generalization of concepts such as subsets from set theory, subgroups from group theory ...
of ''G'' which is not an induced substructure.
Homomorphism problem
The following problem is known as the ''homomorphism problem'':
:Given two finite structures
and
of a finite relational signature, find a homomorphism
or show that no such homomorphism exists.
Every
constraint satisfaction problem (CSP) has a translation into the homomorphism problem. Therefore, the
complexity of CSP can be studied using the methods of
finite model theory.
Another application is in
database theory, where a
relational model of a
database
In computing, a database is an organized collection of data or a type of data store based on the use of a database management system (DBMS), the software that interacts with end users, applications, and the database itself to capture and a ...
is essentially the same thing as a relational structure. It turns out that a
conjunctive query on a database can be described by another structure in the same signature as the database model. A homomorphism from the relational model to the structure representing the query is the same thing as a solution to the query. This shows that the conjunctive query problem is also equivalent to the homomorphism problem.
Structures and first-order logic
Structures are sometimes referred to as "first-order structures". This is misleading, as nothing in their definition ties them to any specific logic, and in fact they are suitable as semantic objects both for very restricted fragments of first-order logic such as that used in universal algebra, and for
second-order logic. In connection with first-order logic and model theory, structures are often called models, even when the question "models of what?" has no obvious answer.
Satisfaction relation
Each first-order structure
has a satisfaction relation
defined for all formulas
in the language consisting of the language of
together with a constant symbol for each element of
which is interpreted as that element.
This relation is defined inductively using Tarski's
T-schema.
A structure
is said to be a model of a
theory
A theory is a systematic and rational form of abstract thinking about a phenomenon, or the conclusions derived from such thinking. It involves contemplative and logical reasoning, often supported by processes such as observation, experimentation, ...
if the language of
is the same as the language of
and every sentence in
is satisfied by
Thus, for example, a "ring" is a structure for the language of rings that satisfies each of the ring axioms, and a model of
ZFC set theory is a structure in the language of set theory that satisfies each of the ZFC axioms.
Definable relations
An
-ary relation
on the universe (i.e. domain)
of the structure
is said to be definable (or explicitly definable cf.
Beth definability, or
-definable, or definable with parameters from
cf. below) if there is a formula
such that
In other words,
is definable if and only if there is a formula
such that
is correct.
An important special case is the definability of specific elements. An element
of
is definable in
if and only if there is a formula
such that
Definability with parameters
A relation
is said to be definable with parameters (or
-definable) if there is a formula
with parameters from
such that
is definable using
Every element of a structure is definable using the element itself as a parameter.
Some authors use ''definable'' to mean ''definable without parameters'', while other authors mean ''definable with parameters''. Broadly speaking, the convention that ''definable'' means ''definable without parameters'' is more common amongst set theorists, while the opposite convention is more common amongst model theorists.
Implicit definability
Recall from above that an
-ary relation
on the universe
of
is explicitly definable if there is a formula
such that
Here the formula
used to define a relation
must be over the signature of
and so
may not mention
itself, since
is not in the signature of
If there is a formula
in the extended language containing the language of
and a new symbol
and the relation
is the only relation on
such that
then
is said to be implicitly definable over
By
Beth's theorem, every implicitly definable relation is explicitly definable.
Many-sorted structures
Structures as defined above are sometimes called s to distinguish them from the more general s. A many-sorted structure can have an arbitrary number of domains. The sorts are part of the signature, and they play the role of names for the different domains.
Many-sorted signatures also prescribe which sorts the functions and relations of a many-sorted structure are defined on. Therefore, the arities of function symbols or relation symbols must be more complicated objects such as tuples of sorts rather than natural numbers.
Vector space
In mathematics and physics, a vector space (also called a linear space) is a set (mathematics), set whose elements, often called vector (mathematics and physics), ''vectors'', can be added together and multiplied ("scaled") by numbers called sc ...
s, for example, can be regarded as two-sorted structures in the following way. The two-sorted signature of vector spaces consists of two sorts ''V'' (for vectors) and ''S'' (for scalars) and the following function symbols:
If ''V'' is a vector space over a field ''F'', the corresponding two-sorted structure
consists of the vector domain
, the scalar domain
, and the obvious functions, such as the vector zero
, the scalar zero
, or scalar multiplication
.
Many-sorted structures are often used as a convenient tool even when they could be avoided with a little effort. But they are rarely defined in a rigorous way, because it is straightforward and tedious (hence unrewarding) to carry out the generalization explicitly.
In most mathematical endeavours, not much attention is paid to the sorts. A
many-sorted logic however naturally leads to a
type theory
In mathematics and theoretical computer science, a type theory is the formal presentation of a specific type system. Type theory is the academic study of type systems.
Some type theories serve as alternatives to set theory as a foundation of ...
. As
Bart Jacobs puts it: "A logic is always a logic over a type theory." This emphasis in turn leads to
categorical logic because a logic over a type theory categorically corresponds to one ("total") category, capturing the logic, being
fibred over another ("base") category, capturing the type theory.
Other generalizations
Partial algebras
Both universal algebra and model theory study classes of (structures or) algebras that are defined by a signature and a set of axioms. In the case of model theory these axioms have the form of first-order sentences. The formalism of universal algebra is much more restrictive; essentially it only allows first-order sentences that have the form of universally quantified equations between terms, e.g. ''x'' ''y'' (''x'' + ''y'' = ''y'' + ''x''). One consequence is that the choice of a signature is more significant in universal algebra than it is in model theory. For example, the class of groups, in the signature consisting of the binary function symbol × and the constant symbol 1, is an
elementary class, but it is not a
variety. Universal algebra solves this problem by adding a unary function symbol
−1.
In the case of fields this strategy works only for addition. For multiplication it fails because 0 does not have a multiplicative inverse. An ad hoc attempt to deal with this would be to define 0
−1 = 0. (This attempt fails, essentially because with this definition 0 × 0
−1 = 1 is not true.) Therefore, one is naturally led to allow partial functions, i.e., functions that are defined only on a subset of their domain. However, there are several obvious ways to generalize notions such as substructure, homomorphism and identity.
Structures for typed languages
In
type theory
In mathematics and theoretical computer science, a type theory is the formal presentation of a specific type system. Type theory is the academic study of type systems.
Some type theories serve as alternatives to set theory as a foundation of ...
, there are many sorts of variables, each of which has a type. Types are inductively defined; given two types δ and σ there is also a type σ → δ that represents functions from objects of type σ to objects of type δ. A structure for a typed language (in the ordinary first-order semantics) must include a separate set of objects of each type, and for a function type the structure must have complete information about the function represented by each object of that type.
Higher-order languages
There is more than one possible semantics for
higher-order logic
In mathematics and logic, a higher-order logic (abbreviated HOL) is a form of logic that is distinguished from first-order logic by additional quantifiers and, sometimes, stronger semantics. Higher-order logics with their standard semantics are m ...
, as discussed in the article on
second-order logic. When using full higher-order semantics, a structure need only have a universe for objects of type 0, and the T-schema is extended so that a quantifier over a higher-order type is satisfied by the model if and only if it is disquotationally true. When using first-order semantics, an additional sort is added for each higher-order type, as in the case of a many sorted first order language.
Structures that are proper classes
In the study of
set theory
Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies Set (mathematics), sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory – as a branch of mathema ...
and
category theory
Category theory is a general theory of mathematical structures and their relations. It was introduced by Samuel Eilenberg and Saunders Mac Lane in the middle of the 20th century in their foundational work on algebraic topology. Category theory ...
, it is sometimes useful to consider structures in which the domain of discourse is a
proper class
Proper may refer to:
Mathematics
* Proper map, in topology, a property of continuous function between topological spaces, if inverse images of compact subsets are compact
* Proper morphism, in algebraic geometry, an analogue of a proper map f ...
instead of a set. These structures are sometimes called class models to distinguish them from the "set models" discussed above. When the domain is a proper class, each function and relation symbol may also be represented by a proper class.
In
Bertrand Russell
Bertrand Arthur William Russell, 3rd Earl Russell, (18 May 1872 – 2 February 1970) was a British philosopher, logician, mathematician, and public intellectual. He had influence on mathematics, logic, set theory, and various areas of analytic ...
's ''
Principia Mathematica
The ''Principia Mathematica'' (often abbreviated ''PM'') is a three-volume work on the foundations of mathematics written by the mathematician–philosophers Alfred North Whitehead and Bertrand Russell and published in 1910, 1912, and 1 ...
'', structures were also allowed to have a proper class as their domain.
See also
*
Notes
References
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
External links
Semanticssection i
Classical Logic(an entry o
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
{{Authority control
Mathematical logic
Mathematical structures
Model theory
Universal algebra