HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

{{short description, Algorithm in modal logic In
modal logic Modal logic is a kind of logic used to represent statements about Modality (natural language), necessity and possibility. In philosophy and related fields it is used as a tool for understanding concepts such as knowledge, obligation, and causality ...
, standard translation is a logic translation that transforms formulas of modal logic into formulas of
first-order logic First-order logic, also called predicate logic, predicate calculus, or quantificational logic, is a collection of formal systems used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. First-order logic uses quantified variables over ...
which capture the meaning of the modal formulas. Standard translation is defined inductively on the structure of the formula. In short,
atomic formula In mathematical logic, an atomic formula (also known as an atom or a prime formula) is a formula with no deeper propositional structure, that is, a formula that contains no logical connectives or equivalently a formula that has no strict subformu ...
s are mapped onto unary predicates and the objects in the first-order language are the accessible worlds. The
logical connective In logic, a logical connective (also called a logical operator, sentential connective, or sentential operator) is a logical constant. Connectives can be used to connect logical formulas. For instance in the syntax of propositional logic, the ...
s from
propositional logic The propositional calculus is a branch of logic. It is also called propositional logic, statement logic, sentential calculus, sentential logic, or sometimes zeroth-order logic. Sometimes, it is called ''first-order'' propositional logic to contra ...
remain untouched and the modal operators are transformed into first-order formulas according to their
semantics Semantics is the study of linguistic Meaning (philosophy), meaning. It examines what meaning is, how words get their meaning, and how the meaning of a complex expression depends on its parts. Part of this process involves the distinction betwee ...
.


Definition

Standard translation is defined as follows: *ST_x(p) \equiv P(x), where p is an
atomic formula In mathematical logic, an atomic formula (also known as an atom or a prime formula) is a formula with no deeper propositional structure, that is, a formula that contains no logical connectives or equivalently a formula that has no strict subformu ...
; P(x) is true when p holds in world x. *ST_x(\top) \equiv \top *ST_x(\bot) \equiv \bot *ST_x(\neg \varphi) \equiv \neg ST_x(\varphi) *ST_x(\varphi \wedge \psi) \equiv ST_x(\varphi) \wedge ST_x(\psi) *ST_x(\varphi \vee \psi) \equiv ST_x(\varphi) \vee ST_x(\psi) *ST_x(\varphi \rightarrow \psi) \equiv ST_x(\varphi) \rightarrow ST_x(\psi) *ST_x(\Diamond_m \varphi) \equiv \exists y ( R_m(x, y) \wedge ST_y(\varphi)) *ST_x(\Box_m \varphi) \equiv \forall y ( R_m(x, y) \rightarrow ST_y(\varphi)) In the above, x is the world from which the formula is evaluated. Initially, a
free variable In mathematics, and in other disciplines involving formal languages, including mathematical logic and computer science, a variable may be said to be either free or bound. Some older books use the terms real variable and apparent variable for f ...
x is used and whenever a modal operator needs to be translated, a fresh variable is introduced to indicate that the remainder of the formula needs to be evaluated from that world. Here, the subscript m refers to the
accessibility relation An accessibility relation is a relation (math), relation which plays a key role in assigning truth values to sentences in the Kripke semantics, relational semantics for modal logic. In relational semantics, a modal formula's truth value at a '' ...
that should be used: normally, \Box and \Diamond refer to a relation R of the Kripke model but more than one accessibility relation can exist (a multimodal logic) in which case subscripts are used. For example, \Box_a and \Diamond_a refer to an accessibility relation R_a and \Box_b and \Diamond_b to R_b in the model. Alternatively, it can also be placed inside the modal symbol.


Example

As an example, when standard translation is applied to \Box \Box p, we expand the outer box to get : \forall y ( R(x, y) \rightarrow ST_y(\Box p)) meaning that we have now moved from x to an accessible world y and we now evaluate the remainder of the formula, \Box p, in each of those accessible worlds. The whole standard translation of this example becomes : \forall y ( R(x, y) \rightarrow (\forall z ( R(y, z) \rightarrow P(z)))) which precisely captures the semantics of two boxes in modal logic. The formula \Box \Box p holds in x when for all accessible worlds y from x and for all accessible worlds z from y, the predicate P is true for z. Note that the formula is also true when no such accessible worlds exist. In case x has no accessible worlds then R(x,y) is false but the whole formula is vacuously true: an implication is also true when the antecedent is false.


Standard translation and modal depth

The modal depth of a formula also becomes apparent in the translation to first-order logic. When the modal depth of a formula is ''k'', then the first-order logic formula contains a 'chain' of ''k'' transitions from the starting world x. The worlds are 'chained' in the sense that these worlds are visited by going from accessible to accessible world. Informally, the number of transitions in the 'longest chain' of transitions in the first-order formula is the modal depth of the formula. The modal depth of the formula used in the example above is two. The first-order formula indicates that the transitions from x to y and from y to z are needed to verify the validity of the formula. This is also the modal depth of the formula as each modal operator increases the modal depth by one.


References

* Patrick Blackburn and Johan van Benthem (1988), ''Modal Logic: A Semantic Perspective''. Modal logic Predicate logic