In
term logic
In philosophy, term logic, also known as traditional logic, syllogistic logic or Aristotelian logic, is a loose name for an approach to formal logic that began with Aristotle and was developed further in ancient history mostly by his followers, th ...
(a branch of
philosophical logic
Understood in a narrow sense, philosophical logic is the area of logic that studies the application of logical methods to philosophical problems, often in the form of extended logical systems like modal logic. Some theorists conceive philosophical ...
), the square of opposition is a diagram representing the relations between the four basic
categorical propositions.
The origin of the square can be traced back to
Aristotle
Aristotle (; grc-gre, Ἀριστοτέλης ''Aristotélēs'', ; 384–322 BC) was a Greek philosopher and polymath during the Classical period in Ancient Greece. Taught by Plato, he was the founder of the Peripatetic school of phil ...
's tractate ''
On Interpretation
''De Interpretatione'' or ''On Interpretation'' (Greek: Περὶ Ἑρμηνείας, ''Peri Hermeneias'') is the second text from Aristotle's ''Organon'' and is among the earliest surviving philosophical works in the Western tradition to deal ...
'' and its distinction between two oppositions:
contradiction
In traditional logic, a contradiction occurs when a proposition conflicts either with itself or established fact. It is often used as a tool to detect disingenuous beliefs and bias. Illustrating a general tendency in applied logic, Aristotle's ...
and
contrariety.
However, Aristotle did not draw any diagram. This was done several centuries later by
Apuleius
Apuleius (; also called Lucius Apuleius Madaurensis; c. 124 – after 170) was a Numidian Latin-language prose writer, Platonist philosopher and rhetorician. He lived in the Roman province of Numidia, in the Berber city of Madauros, modern-day ...
and
Boethius
Anicius Manlius Severinus Boethius, commonly known as Boethius (; Latin: ''Boetius''; 480 – 524 AD), was a Roman senator, consul, ''magister officiorum'', historian, and philosopher of the Early Middle Ages. He was a central figure in the tr ...
.
Summary
In traditional logic, a proposition (Latin: ''propositio'') is a spoken assertion (''oratio enunciativa''), not the meaning of an assertion, as in modern philosophy of language and logic. A ''
categorical proposition'' is a simple proposition containing two terms, subject () and predicate (), in which the predicate is either asserted or denied of the subject.
Every categorical proposition can be reduced to one of four
logical form
In logic, logical form of a statement is a precisely-specified semantic version of that statement in a formal system. Informally, the logical form attempts to formalize a possibly ambiguous statement into a statement with a precise, unambiguou ...
s, named , , , and based on the Latin ' (I affirm), for the affirmative propositions and , and ' (I deny), for the negative propositions and . These are:
* The proposition, the universal affirmative (''universalis affirmativa''), whose form in Latin is 'omne est ', usually translated as 'every is a '.
* The proposition, the universal negative (''universalis negativa''), Latin form 'nullum est ', usually translated as 'no are '.
* The proposition, the particular affirmative (''particularis affirmativa''), Latin 'quoddam est ', usually translated as 'some are '.
* The proposition, the particular negative (''particularis negativa''), Latin 'quoddam nōn est ', usually translated as 'some are not '.
In tabular form:
*Proposition may be stated as "All is ." However, Proposition when stated correspondingly as "All is not ." is ambiguous because it can be either an or proposition, thus requiring a context to determine the form; the standard form "No is " is unambiguous, so it is preferred. Proposition also takes the forms "Sometimes is not ." and "A certain is not ." (literally the Latin 'Quoddam nōn est .')
** in the modern forms means that a statement
applies on an object
. It may be simply interpreted as "
is
" in many cases.
can be also written as
.
Aristotle states (in chapters six and seven of the ''Peri hermēneias'' (Περὶ Ἑρμηνείας, Latin ''
De Interpretatione'', English 'On Interpretation')), that there are certain logical relationships between these four kinds of proposition. He says that to every affirmation there corresponds exactly one negation, and that every affirmation and its negation are 'opposed' such that always one of them must be true, and the other false. A pair of an affirmative statement and its negation is, he calls, a 'contradiction
' (in medieval Latin, ''contradictio''). Examples of contradictories are 'every man is white' and 'not every man is white' (also read as 'some men are not white'), 'no man is white' and 'some man is white'.
The below relations, contrary, subcontrary, subalternation, and superalternation, do hold based on the traditional logic assumption that things stated as (or things satisfying a statement in modern logic) exist. If this assumption is taken out, then these relations do not hold.
'Contrary
' (medieval: ''contrariae'') statements, are such that both statements cannot be true at the same time. Examples of these are the universal affirmative 'every man is white', and the universal negative 'no man is white'. These cannot be true at the same time. However, these are not contradictories because both of them may be false. For example, it is false that every man is white, since some men are not white. Yet it is also false that no man is white, since there are some white men.
Since every statement has the contradictory opposite (its negation), and since a contradictory is true when its opposite is false, it follows that the opposites of contraries (which the medievals called subcontraries, ''subcontrariae'') can both be true, but they cannot both be false. Since subcontraries are negations of universal statements, they were called 'particular' statements by the medieval logicians.
Another logical relation implied by this, though not mentioned explicitly by Aristotle, is 'alternation' (''alternatio''), consisting of 'subalternation
' and 'superalternation
'. Subalternation is a relation between the particular statement and the universal statement of the same quality (affirmative or negative) such that the particular is implied by the universal, while superalternation is a relation between them such that the falsity of the universal (equivalently the negation of the universal) is implied by the falsity of the particular (equivalently the negation of the particular). (The superalternation is the
contrapositive
In logic and mathematics, contraposition refers to the inference of going from a conditional statement into its logically equivalent contrapositive, and an associated proof method known as proof by contraposition. The contrapositive of a statem ...
of the subalternation.) In these relations, the particular is the subaltern of the universal, which is the particular's superaltern. For example, if 'every man is white' is true, its contrary 'no man is white' is false. Therefore, the contradictory 'some man is white' is true. Similarly the universal 'no man is white' implies the particular 'not every man is white'.
In summary:
* Universal statements are contraries: 'every man is just' and 'no man is just' cannot be true together, although one may be true and the other false, and also both may be false (if at least one man is just, and at least one man is not just).
* Particular statements are subcontraries. 'Some man is just' and 'some man is not just' cannot be false together.
* The particular statement of one quality is the subaltern of the universal statement of that same quality, which is the superaltern of the particular statement because in Aristotelian semantics 'every is ' implies 'some is ' and 'no is ' implies 'some is not '. Note that modern formal interpretations of English sentences interpret 'every is ' as 'for any , a statement that is implies a statement that is ', which does ''not'' imply 'some is . This is a matter of semantic interpretation, however, and does not mean, as is sometimes claimed, that Aristotelian logic is 'wrong'.
* The universal affirmative () and the particular negative () are contradictories. If some is not , then not every is . Conversely, though this is not the case in modern semantics, it was thought that if every is not , some is not . This interpretation has caused difficulties (see below). While Aristotle's Greek does not represent the particular negative as 'some is not , but as 'not every is ', someone in his commentary on the ''Peri hermaneias'', renders the particular negative as 'quoddam A nōn est ', literally 'a certain is not a ', and in all medieval writing on logic it is customary to represent the particular proposition in this way.
These relationships became the basis of a diagram originating with
Boethius
Anicius Manlius Severinus Boethius, commonly known as Boethius (; Latin: ''Boetius''; 480 – 524 AD), was a Roman senator, consul, ''magister officiorum'', historian, and philosopher of the Early Middle Ages. He was a central figure in the tr ...
and used by medieval logicians to classify the logical relationships. The propositions are placed in the four corners of a square, and the relations represented as lines drawn between them, whence the name 'The Square of Opposition'.
Therefore, the following cases can be made:
# If is true, then is false, is true, is false;
# If is true, then is false, is false, is true;
# If is true, then is false, and are indeterminate;
# If is true, then is false, and are indeterminate;
# If is false, then is true, and are indeterminate;
# If is false, then is true, and are indeterminate;
# If is false, then is false, is true, is true;
# If is false, then is true, is false, is true.
To memorize them, the medievals invented the following Latin rhyme:
:'' adfirmat, negat , sed universaliter ambae;
firmat, negat , sed particulariter ambae.''
It affirms that and are not neither both true nor both false in each of the above cases. The same applies to and . While the first two are universal statements, the couple / refers to particular ones.
The Square of Oppositions was used for the categorical inferences described by the Greek philosopher Aristotle:
conversion
Conversion or convert may refer to:
Arts, entertainment, and media
* "Conversion" (''Doctor Who'' audio), an episode of the audio drama ''Cyberman''
* "Conversion" (''Stargate Atlantis''), an episode of the television series
* "The Conversion" ...
,
obversion
In traditional logic, obversion is a "type of immediate inference in which from a given proposition another proposition is inferred whose subject is the same as the original subject, whose predicate is the contradictory of the original predicate, ...
and
contraposition
In logic and mathematics, contraposition refers to the inference of going from a conditional statement into its logically equivalent contrapositive, and an associated proof method known as proof by contraposition. The contrapositive of a stateme ...
. Each of those three types of categorical inference was applied to the four Boethian logical forms: , , , and .
The problem of existential import
Subcontraries ( and ), which medieval logicians represented in the form 'quoddam est ' (some particular is ) and 'quoddam non est ' (some particular is not ) cannot both be false, since their universal contradictory statements (no is / every is ) cannot both be true. This leads to a difficulty firstly identified by
Peter Abelard
Peter Abelard (; french: link=no, Pierre Abélard; la, Petrus Abaelardus or ''Abailardus''; 21 April 1142) was a medieval French scholastic philosopher, leading logician, theologian, poet, composer and musician. This source has a detailed desc ...
(1079 – 21 April 1142). 'Some is ' seems to imply 'something is ', in other words, there exists something that is . For example, 'Some man is white' seems to imply that at least one thing that exists is a man, namely the man who has to be white, if 'some man is white' is true. But, 'some man is not white' also implies that something as a man exists, namely the man who is not white, if the statement 'some man is not white' is true. But Aristotelian logic requires that one of these statements (more generally 'some particular is ' and 'some particular is not ') is necessarily true, i.e., they cannot both be false. Therefore, since both statements imply the presence of at least one thing that is a man, the presence of a man or men is followed. But, as Abelard points out in the ''Dialectica'', surely men might not exist?
: For with absolutely no man existing, neither the proposition 'every man is a man' is true nor 'some man is not a man'.
Abelard also points out that subcontraries containing subject terms denoting nothing, such as 'a man who is a stone', are both false.
: If 'every stone-man is a stone' is true, also its conversion ''per accidens'' is true ('some stones are stone-men'). But no stone is a stone-man, because neither this man nor that man etc. is a stone. But also this 'a certain stone-man is not a stone' is false by necessity, since it is impossible to suppose it is true.
Terence Parsons
Terence Dwight Parsons (1939-2022) was an American philosopher, specializing in philosophy of language and metaphysics. He was emeritus professor of philosophy at UCLA.
Life and career
Parsons was born in Endicott, New York and graduated from th ...
(born 1939) argues that ancient philosophers did not experience the problem of
existential import
A syllogism ( grc-gre, συλλογισμός, ''syllogismos'', 'conclusion, inference') is a kind of logical argument that applies deductive reasoning to arrive at a conclusion based on two propositions that are asserted or assumed to be true.
...
as only the A (universal affirmative) and I (particular affirmative) forms had existential import. (If a statement includes a term such that the statement is false if the term has no instances, i.e., no thing associated with the term exists, then the statement is said to have ''existential import'' with respect to that term.)
: Affirmatives have existential import, and negatives do not. The ancients thus did not see the incoherence of the square as formulated by
Aristotle
Aristotle (; grc-gre, Ἀριστοτέλης ''Aristotélēs'', ; 384–322 BC) was a Greek philosopher and polymath during the Classical period in Ancient Greece. Taught by Plato, he was the founder of the Peripatetic school of phil ...
because there was no incoherence to see.
He goes on to cite a medieval philosopher
William of Moerbeke
William of Moerbeke, O.P. ( nl, Willem van Moerbeke; la, Guillelmus de Morbeka; 1215–35 – 1286), was a prolific medieval translator of philosophical, medical, and scientific texts from Greek language into Latin, enabled by the period ...
(1215–35 – ),
:In affirmative propositions a term is always asserted to supposit for something. Thus, if it supposits for nothing the proposition is false. However, in negative propositions the assertion is either that the term does not supposit for something or that it supposits for something of which the predicate is truly denied. Thus a negative proposition has two causes of truth.
And points to
Boethius
Anicius Manlius Severinus Boethius, commonly known as Boethius (; Latin: ''Boetius''; 480 – 524 AD), was a Roman senator, consul, ''magister officiorum'', historian, and philosopher of the Early Middle Ages. He was a central figure in the tr ...
' translation of Aristotle's work as giving rise to the mistaken notion that the form has existential import.
:But when Boethius (477 – 524 AD) comments on this text he illustrates Aristotle's doctrine with the now-famous diagram, and he uses the wording 'Some man is not just'. So this must have seemed to him to be a natural equivalent in Latin. It looks odd to us in English, but he wasn't bothered by it.
Modern squares of opposition
In the 19th century,
George Boole
George Boole (; 2 November 1815 – 8 December 1864) was a largely self-taught English mathematician, philosopher, and logician, most of whose short career was spent as the first professor of mathematics at Queen's College, Cork in Ire ...
(November 1815 – 8 December 1864) argued for requiring
existential import
A syllogism ( grc-gre, συλλογισμός, ''syllogismos'', 'conclusion, inference') is a kind of logical argument that applies deductive reasoning to arrive at a conclusion based on two propositions that are asserted or assumed to be true.
...
on both terms in particular claims ( and ), but allowing all terms of universal claims ( and ) to lack existential import. This decision made
Venn diagram
A Venn diagram is a widely used diagram style that shows the logical relation between set (mathematics), sets, popularized by John Venn (1834–1923) in the 1880s. The diagrams are used to teach elementary set theory, and to illustrate simple ...
s particularly easy to use for term logic. The square of opposition, under this Boolean set of assumptions, is often called the ''modern Square of opposition''. In the modern square of opposition, and claims are contradictories, as are and , but all other forms of opposition cease to hold; there are no contraries, subcontraries, subalternations, and superalternations. Thus, from a modern point of view, it often makes sense to talk about 'the' opposition of a claim, rather than insisting, as older logicians did, that a claim has several different opposites, which are in different kinds of opposition with the claim.
Gottlob Frege
Friedrich Ludwig Gottlob Frege (; ; 8 November 1848 – 26 July 1925) was a German philosopher, logician, and mathematician. He was a mathematics professor at the University of Jena, and is understood by many to be the father of analytic phil ...
(8 November 1848 – 26 July 1925)'s ''
Begriffsschrift
''Begriffsschrift'' (German for, roughly, "concept-script") is a book on logic by Gottlob Frege, published in 1879, and the formal system set out in that book.
''Begriffsschrift'' is usually translated as ''concept writing'' or ''concept notatio ...
'' also presents a square of oppositions, organised in an almost identical manner to the classical square, showing the contradictories, subalternates and contraries between four formulae constructed from universal quantification, negation and implication.
Algirdas Julien Greimas
Algirdas Julien Greimas (; born ''Algirdas Julius Greimas''; 9 March 1917 – 27 February 1992) was a Lithuanian literary scientist who wrote most of his body of work in French while living in France. Greimas is known among other things for th ...
(9 March 1917 – 27 February 1992)'
semiotic square
The semiotic square, also known as the Greimas square, is a tool used in structural analysis of the relationships between semiotic signs through the opposition of concepts, such as feminine-masculine or beautiful-ugly, and of extending the relevan ...
was derived from Aristotle's work.
The traditional square of opposition is now often compared with squares based on inner- and outer-negation.
Logical hexagons and other bi-simplexes
The square of opposition has been extended to a logical hexagon which includes the relationships of six statements. It was discovered independently by both
Augustin Sesmat
Augustin Sesmat ( Dieulouard -- ) was a French mathematician and logician. He was professor of history and criticism of science at the Institut Catholique de Paris in the 1930s. He was probably the first person to discover the logical hexagon ...
(April 7, 1885 – December 12, 1957) and
Robert Blanché __NOTOC__
Robert Blanché (1898–1975) was an associate professor of philosophy at the University of Toulouse. He wrote many books addressing the philosophy of mathematics
The philosophy of mathematics is the branch of philosophy that studie ...
(1898–1975). It has been proven that both the square and the hexagon, followed by a "
logical cube
In the system of Aristotelian logic, the logical cube is a diagram representing the different ways in which each of the eight propositions of the system is logically related ('opposed') to each of the others. The system is also useful in the a ...
", belong to a regular series of n-dimensional objects called "logical bi-simplexes of dimension ." The pattern also goes even beyond this.
[Moretti, Pellissier]
Square of opposition (or logical square) and modal logic
The logical square, also called square of opposition or square of
Apuleius
Apuleius (; also called Lucius Apuleius Madaurensis; c. 124 – after 170) was a Numidian Latin-language prose writer, Platonist philosopher and rhetorician. He lived in the Roman province of Numidia, in the Berber city of Madauros, modern-day ...
, has its origin in the four marked sentences to be employed in syllogistic reasoning: "Every man is bad," the universal affirmative - The negation of the universal affirmative "Not every man is bad" (or "Some men are not bad") - "Some men are bad," the particular affirmative - and finally, the negation of the particular affirmative "No man is bad".
Robert Blanché __NOTOC__
Robert Blanché (1898–1975) was an associate professor of philosophy at the University of Toulouse. He wrote many books addressing the philosophy of mathematics
The philosophy of mathematics is the branch of philosophy that studie ...
published with Vrin his Structures intellectuelles in 1966 and since then many scholars think that the logical square or square of opposition representing four values should be replaced by the
logical hexagon
Logic is the study of correct reasoning. It includes both formal and informal logic. Formal logic is the science of deductively valid inferences or of logical truths. It is a formal science investigating how conclusions follow from premises ...
which by representing six values is a more potent figure because it has the power to explain more things about logic and natural language.
Set-theoretical interpretation of categorical statements
In modern
mathematical logic
Mathematical logic is the study of logic, formal logic within mathematics. Major subareas include model theory, proof theory, set theory, and recursion theory. Research in mathematical logic commonly addresses the mathematical properties of for ...
, statements containing words "all", "some" and "no", can be stated in terms of
set theory
Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory, as a branch of mathematics, is mostly conce ...
if we assume a set-like domain of discourse. If the set of all 's is labeled as
and the set of all 's as
, then:
* "All is " (AaB) is equivalent to "
is a
subset
In mathematics, Set (mathematics), set ''A'' is a subset of a set ''B'' if all Element (mathematics), elements of ''A'' are also elements of ''B''; ''B'' is then a superset of ''A''. It is possible for ''A'' and ''B'' to be equal; if they are ...
of
", or
.
* "No is " (AeB) is equivalent to "The
intersection of
and
is
empty
Empty may refer to:
Music Albums
* ''Empty'' (God Lives Underwater album) or the title song, 1995
* ''Empty'' (Nils Frahm album), 2020
* ''Empty'' (Tait album) or the title song, 2001
Songs
* "Empty" (The Click Five song), 2007
* ...
", or
.
* "Some is " (AiB) is equivalent to "The intersection of
and
is not empty", or
.
* "Some is not " (AoB) is equivalent to "
is not a subset of
", or
.
By definition, the
empty set
In mathematics, the empty set is the unique set having no elements; its size or cardinality (count of elements in a set) is zero. Some axiomatic set theories ensure that the empty set exists by including an axiom of empty set, while in other ...
is a subset of all sets. From this fact it follows that, according to this mathematical convention, if there are no 's, then the statements "All is " and "No is " are always true whereas the statements "Some is " and "Some is not " are always false. This also implies that AaB does not entail AiB, and some of the syllogisms mentioned above are not valid when there are no 's (
).
See also
*
Boole's syllogistic
*
Free logic
References
External links
*
International Congress on the Square of OppositionSpecial Issue of Logica Universalis Vol. 2 N. 1 (2008) on the Square of OppositionCatlogic: An open source computer script written in Ruby to construct, investigate, and compute categorical propositions and syllogisms{{Mathematical logic
Conceptual models
Term logic
Inference
Syllogism