HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
computability theory Computability theory, also known as recursion theory, is a branch of mathematical logic, computer science, and the theory of computation that originated in the 1930s with the study of computable functions and Turing degrees. The field has since ...
, a Specker sequence is a computable,
monotonically increasing In mathematics, a monotonic function (or monotone function) is a function between ordered sets that preserves or reverses the given order. This concept first arose in calculus, and was later generalized to the more abstract setting of ord ...
,
bounded Boundedness or bounded may refer to: Economics * Bounded rationality, the idea that human rationality in decision-making is bounded by the available information, the cognitive limitations, and the time available to make the decision * Bounded e ...
sequence In mathematics, a sequence is an enumerated collection of objects in which repetitions are allowed and order matters. Like a set, it contains members (also called ''elements'', or ''terms''). The number of elements (possibly infinite) is called ...
of
rational number In mathematics, a rational number is a number that can be expressed as the quotient or fraction of two integers, a numerator and a non-zero denominator . For example, is a rational number, as is every integer (e.g. ). The set of all ra ...
s whose
supremum In mathematics, the infimum (abbreviated inf; plural infima) of a subset S of a partially ordered set P is a greatest element in P that is less than or equal to each element of S, if such an element exists. Consequently, the term ''greatest l ...
is not a computable real number. The first example of such a sequence was constructed by Ernst Specker (1949). The existence of Specker sequences has consequences for computable analysis. The fact that such sequences exist means that the collection of all computable real numbers does not satisfy the least upper bound principle of real analysis, even when considering only computable sequences. A common way to resolve this difficulty is to consider only sequences that are accompanied by a
modulus of convergence In real analysis, a branch of mathematics, a modulus of convergence is a function that tells how quickly a convergent sequence converges. These moduli are often employed in the study of computable analysis and constructive mathematics. If a sequ ...
; no Specker sequence has a computable modulus of convergence. More generally, a Specker sequence is called a ''recursive counterexample'' to the least upper bound principle, i.e. a construction that shows that this theorem is false when restricted to computable reals. The least upper bound principle has also been analyzed in the program of
reverse mathematics Reverse mathematics is a program in mathematical logic that seeks to determine which axioms are required to prove theorems of mathematics. Its defining method can briefly be described as "going backwards from the theorems to the axioms", in cont ...
, where the exact strength of this principle has been determined. In the terminology of that program, the least upper bound principle is equivalent to ACA0 over RCA0. In fact, the proof of the forward implication, i.e. that the least upper bound principle implies ACA0, is readily obtained from the textbook proof (see Simpson, 1999) of the non-computability of the supremum in the least upper bound principle.


Construction

The following construction is described by Kushner (1984). Let ''A'' be any
recursively enumerable In computability theory, a set ''S'' of natural numbers is called computably enumerable (c.e.), recursively enumerable (r.e.), semidecidable, partially decidable, listable, provable or Turing-recognizable if: *There is an algorithm such that the ...
set of
natural number In mathematics, the natural numbers are those numbers used for counting (as in "there are ''six'' coins on the table") and ordering (as in "this is the ''third'' largest city in the country"). Numbers used for counting are called '' cardinal ...
s that is not decidable, and let (''a''''i'') be a computable enumeration of ''A'' without repetition. Define a sequence (''q''''n'') of rational numbers with the rule :q_n = \sum_^n 2^. It is clear that each ''q''''n'' is nonnegative and rational, and that the sequence ''q''''n'' is strictly increasing. Moreover, because ''a''''i'' has no repetition, it is possible to estimate each ''q''''n'' against the series :\sum_^\infty 2^ = 1. Thus the sequence (''q''''n'') is bounded above by 1. Classically, this means that ''q''''n'' has a supremum ''x''. It is shown that ''x'' is not a computable real number. The proof uses a particular fact about computable real numbers. If ''x'' were computable then there would be a
computable function Computable functions are the basic objects of study in computability theory. Computable functions are the formalized analogue of the intuitive notion of algorithms, in the sense that a function is computable if there exists an algorithm that can d ...
''r''(''n'') such that , ''q''''j'' - ''q''''i'', < 1/''n'' for all ''i'',''j'' > ''r''(''n''). To compute ''r'', compare the binary expansion of ''x'' with the binary expansion of ''q''''i'' for larger and larger values of ''i''. The definition of ''q''''i'' causes a single binary digit to go from 0 to 1 each time ''i'' increases by 1. Thus there will be some ''n'' where a large enough initial segment of ''x'' has already been determined by ''q''''n'' that no additional binary digits in that segment could ever be turned on, which leads to an estimate on the distance between ''q''''i'' and ''q''''j'' for ''i'',''j'' > ''n''. If any such a function ''r'' were computable, it would lead to a decision procedure for ''A'', as follows. Given an input ''k'', compute ''r''(2''k''+1). If ''k'' were to appear in the sequence (''a''''i''), this would cause the sequence (''q''''i'') to increase by 2−''k''-1, but this cannot happen once all the elements of (''q''''i'') are within 2−''k''-1 of each other. Thus, if ''k'' is going to be enumerated into ''a''''i'', it must be enumerated for a value of ''i'' less than ''r''(2''k''+1). This leaves a finite number of possible places where ''k'' could be enumerated. To complete the decision procedure, check these in an effective manner and then return 0 or 1 depending on whether ''k'' is found.


See also

* Computation in the limit


References

* Douglas Bridges and Fred Richman. Varieties of Constructive Mathematics, Oxford, 1987. * B.A. Kushner (1984), ''Lectures on constructive mathematical analysis'', American Mathematical Society, Translations of Mathematical Monographs v. 60. * Jakob G. Simonsen (2005), "Specker sequences revisited", ''Mathematical Logic Quarterly'', v. 51, pp. 532–540. {{doi, 10.1002/malq.200410048 * S. Simpson (1999), ''Subsystems of second-order arithmetic'', Springer. * E. Specker (1949), "Nicht konstruktiv beweisbare Sätze der Analysis" ''Journal of Symbolic Logic'', v. 14, pp. 145–158. Computable analysis Sequences and series