HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
computational complexity theory In theoretical computer science and mathematics, computational complexity theory focuses on classifying computational problems according to their resource usage, and explores the relationships between these classifications. A computational problem ...
, the class NC (for "Nick's Class") is the set of
decision problem In computability theory and computational complexity theory, a decision problem is a computational problem that can be posed as a yes–no question on a set of input values. An example of a decision problem is deciding whether a given natura ...
s decidable in polylogarithmic time on a parallel computer with a polynomial number of processors. In other words, a problem with input size ''n'' is in NC if there exist constants ''c'' and ''k'' such that it can be solved in time using parallel processors. Stephen Cook coined the name "Nick's class" after Nick Pippenger, who had done extensive research on circuits with polylogarithmic depth and polynomial size.Arora & Barak (2009) p.120 As in the case of circuit complexity theory, usually the class has an extra constraint that the circuit family must be ''uniform'' ( see below). Just as the class P can be thought of as the tractable problems ( Cobham's thesis), so NC can be thought of as the problems that can be efficiently solved on a parallel computer.Arora & Barak (2009) p.118 NC is a subset of P because polylogarithmic parallel computations can be simulated by polynomial-time sequential ones. It is unknown whether NC = P, but most researchers suspect this to be false, meaning that there are probably some tractable problems that are "inherently sequential" and cannot significantly be sped up by using parallelism. Just as the class
NP-complete In computational complexity theory, NP-complete problems are the hardest of the problems to which ''solutions'' can be verified ''quickly''. Somewhat more precisely, a problem is NP-complete when: # It is a decision problem, meaning that for any ...
can be thought of as "probably intractable", so the class
P-complete In computational complexity theory, a decision problem is P-complete ( complete for the complexity class P) if it is in P and every problem in P can be reduced to it by an appropriate reduction. The notion of P-complete decision problems is use ...
, when using NC reductions, can be thought of as "probably not parallelizable" or "probably inherently sequential". The parallel computer in the definition can be assumed to be a ''parallel, random-access machine'' ( PRAM). That is a parallel computer with a central pool of memory, and any processor can access any bit of memory in constant time. The definition of NC is not affected by the choice of how the PRAM handles simultaneous access to a single bit by more than one processor. It can be CRCW, CREW, or EREW. See PRAM for descriptions of those models. Equivalently, NC can be defined as those decision problems decidable by a uniform Boolean circuit (which can be calculated from the length of the input, for NC, we suppose we can compute the Boolean circuit of size ''n'' in logarithmic space in ''n'') with polylogarithmic depth and a polynomial number of gates with a maximum fan-in of 2. RNC is a class extending NC with access to randomness.


Problems in NC

As with P, by a slight abuse of language, one might classify function problems and search problems as being in NC. NC is known to include many problems, including * Integer addition, multiplication and division; *
Matrix multiplication In mathematics, specifically in linear algebra, matrix multiplication is a binary operation that produces a matrix (mathematics), matrix from two matrices. For matrix multiplication, the number of columns in the first matrix must be equal to the n ...
, determinant, inverse, rank; * Polynomial GCD, by a reduction to linear algebra using Sylvester matrix * Finding a maximal matching. Often algorithms for those problems had to be separately invented and could not be naïvely adapted from well-known algorithms –
Gaussian elimination In mathematics, Gaussian elimination, also known as row reduction, is an algorithm for solving systems of linear equations. It consists of a sequence of row-wise operations performed on the corresponding matrix of coefficients. This method can a ...
and
Euclidean algorithm In mathematics, the Euclidean algorithm,Some widely used textbooks, such as I. N. Herstein's ''Topics in Algebra'' and Serge Lang's ''Algebra'', use the term "Euclidean algorithm" to refer to Euclidean division or Euclid's algorithm, is a ...
rely on operations performed in sequence. One might contrast ripple carry adder with a carry-lookahead adder.


Example

An example of problem in NC1 is the parity check on a bit string. The problem consists in counting the number of 1s in a string made of 1 and 0. A simple solution consists in summing all the string's bits. Since
addition Addition (usually signified by the Plus and minus signs#Plus sign, plus symbol, +) is one of the four basic Operation (mathematics), operations of arithmetic, the other three being subtraction, multiplication, and Division (mathematics), divis ...
is associative, x_1 + \cdots + x_n = \left(x_1 + \cdots + x_\right) + \left(x_ + \cdots + x_n\right). Recursively applying such property, it is possible to build a
binary tree In computer science, a binary tree is a tree data structure in which each node has at most two children, referred to as the ''left child'' and the ''right child''. That is, it is a ''k''-ary tree with . A recursive definition using set theor ...
of length O(\log(n)) in which every sum between two bits x_i and x_j is expressible by means of basic
logical operator In logic, a logical connective (also called a logical operator, sentential connective, or sentential operator) is a logical constant. Connectives can be used to connect logical formulas. For instance in the syntax of propositional logic, the ...
s, e.g. through the boolean expression (x_i \land \neg x_j) \lor (\neg x_i \land x_j).


The NC hierarchy

NC''i'' is the class of decision problems decidable by uniform boolean circuits with a polynomial number of gates of at most two inputs and depth , or the class of decision problems solvable in time ''O''((log ''n'')''i'') on a parallel computer with a polynomial number of processors. Clearly, :\mathsf^0 \subseteq \mathsf^1 \subseteq \cdots \subseteq \mathsf^i \subseteq \cdots \subseteq \mathsf which forms the NC-hierarchy. The smallest class, NC''0'', is the class of functions definable by boolean circuits with constant depth and bounded fan-in. The next-smallest class, NC''1'', is equal to BW4''0'' , the set of all problems solvable by polynomial-size, bounded fan-in circuits of width 4 or less. This is true for both the uniform and nonuniform case (DLOGTIME-uniformity suffices). One can relate the NC classes to the space classes L, SL, NL, LOGCFL, and AC.Clote & Kranakis (2002) p.437 : \mathsf^1 \subseteq \mathsf = \mathsf \subseteq \mathsf \subseteq \mathsf \subseteq \mathsf^1 \subseteq \mathsf^2. The NC classes are related to the AC classes, which are defined similarly, but with gates having unbounded fan-in. For each ''i'', :\mathsf^i \subseteq \mathsf^i \subseteq \mathsf^ \subseteq \mathsf^\subseteq \mathsf^ \subseteq \mathsf^ As an immediate consequence of this, NC = AC.Clote & Kranakis (2002) p.12 Also, \mathsf^0 \subsetneq \mathsf^0 \subsetneq \mathsf^. Similarly, NC is equivalent to the problems solvable on an alternating Turing machine restricted to at most two options at each step with ''O''(log ''n'') space and (\log n)^ alternations. It is a major open question whether \mathsf^ \subsetneq \mathsf^ . A significant partial result states that if there exists some \epsilon > 0, and a problem in \mathsf^, such that it requires at least \Omega(n^) gates in \mathsf^, then this can be bootstrapped so that it requires superpolynomial gates, and thus not in \mathsf^.


Uniformity

There are various levels of uniformity being considered. A family of boolean circuits is uniform if the schematics for any member of the family can be produced by a Turing machine under various resource constraints. With different levels of constraints, we would obtain possibly different complexity classes, with a more stringent constraint leading to a possibly smaller complexity class. In the literature, the following uniformities have been considered for the NC''1'' class, arranged according to strength: * NC''1'' itself. This is also called the U_-uniformity. It is equivalent to ALOGTIME. * LOGSPACE. * P. * Computable. Any halting Turing machine is allowed. * Non-uniform. This is the strongest case. The boolean circuit family may contain arbitrary elements of the correct width and depth, even if the family cannot be generated by any algorithm. By default, the literature uses LOGSPACE uniformity. Because it is possible that \mathsf^1 \subsetneq \mathsf, researchers may use NC''1''-uniformity, since it is a possible strengthening. To avoid self-reference, NC''1''-uniform NC''1'' is defined as follows: A NC''1'' Boolean circuit family is NC''1''-uniform if the set of descriptions is decided by an ALOGTIME alternating Turing machine. The machine reads in a length-n description of a Boolean circuit, and halts in time O(\log n). For higher classes NC''2'', NC''3'', ..., there are similar uniformities definable. However, for k \geq 2, NC''k''-uniform NC''k'' and LOGSPACE-uniform NC''k'' are equal, and both are equivalent to the following definition: The family is decided by an alternating Turing machine. The machine reads in a length-n description of a Boolean circuit, and halts in time O((\log n)^k) and space O(\log n).


Open problem: Is NC proper?

One major open question in complexity theory is whether or not every containment in the NC hierarchy is proper. It was observed by Papadimitriou that, if NC''i'' = NC''i''+1 for some ''i'', then NC''i'' = NC''j'' for all ''j'' ≥ ''i'', and as a result, NC''i'' = NC. This observation is known as NC-hierarchy collapse because even a single equality in the chain of containments :\mathsf^1 \subseteq \mathsf^2 \subseteq \cdots implies that the entire NC hierarchy "collapses" down to some level ''i''. Thus, there are 2 possibilities: # \mathsf^1 \subset \cdots \subset \mathsf^i \subset \cdots \subset \mathsf^ \subset \cdots \mathsf # \mathsf^1 \subset \cdots \subset \mathsf^i = \cdots = \mathsf^ = \cdots \mathsf It is widely believed that (1) is the case, although no proof as to the truth of either statement has yet been discovered. If there exists a problem that is NC-complete under LOGSPACE or NC''1'' reductions, then the NC hierarchy collapses.


Barrington's theorem

A branching program with ''n'' variables of width ''k'' and length ''m'' consists of a sequence of ''m'' instructions. Each of the instructions is a tuple (''i'', ''p'', ''q'') where ''i'' is the index of variable to check (1 ≤ ''i'' ≤ ''n''), and ''p'' and ''q'' are functions from to . Numbers 1, 2, ..., ''k'' are called states of the branching program. The program initially starts in state 1, and each instruction (''i'', ''p'', ''q'') changes the state from ''x'' to ''p''(''x'') or ''q''(''x''), depending on whether the ''i''th variable is 0 or 1. The function mapping an input to a final state of the program is called the ''yield'' of the program (more precisely, the yield on an input is the function mapping any initial state to the corresponding final state). The program ''accepts'' a set A \subset 2^n of variable values when there is some set of functions F \subset k^k such that a variable sequence x \in 2^n is in ''A'' precisely when its yield is in ''F''. A family of branching programs consists of a branching program with ''n'' variables for each ''n''. It accepts a language when the ''n'' variable program accepts the language restricted to length ''n'' inputs. It is easy to show that every language ''L'' on can be recognized by a family of branching programs of width 5 and exponential length, or by a family of exponential width and linear length. Every regular language on can be recognized by a family of branching programs of constant width and linear number of instructions (since a DFA can be converted to a branching program). BWBP denotes the class of languages recognizable by a family of branching programs of bounded width and polynomial length.Clote & Kranakis (2002) p.50 Barrington's theorem says that BWBP is exactly nonuniform NC1. The proof uses the nonsolvability of the symmetric group S5. The theorem is rather surprising. For instance, it implies that the majority function can be computed by a family of branching programs of constant width and polynomial size, while intuition might suggest that to achieve polynomial size, one needs a linear number of states.


Proof of Barrington's theorem

A branching program of constant width and polynomial size can be easily converted (via divide-and-conquer) to a circuit in NC1. Conversely, suppose a circuit in NC1 is given. Without loss of generality, assume it uses only AND and NOT gates. Call a branching program α-computing a circuit ''C'' if it works as identity when 's output is 0, and as when 's output is 1. As a consequence of Lemma 1 and the fact that all cycles of length 5 are conjugate, for any two 5-cycles , , if there exists a branching program α-computing a circuit ''C'', then there exists a branching program β-computing the circuit ''C'', of the same length. The size of the branching program is at most 4, where ''d'' is the depth of the circuit. If the circuit has logarithmic depth, the branching program has polynomial length.


Notes


References

* *
Greenlaw, Raymond, James Hoover, and Walter Ruzzo. ''Limits To Parallel computation; P-Completeness Theory''.
* Lectures 28 - 34 and 36 * Lecture 12: Relation of ''NC'' to Time-Space Classes * * * {{DEFAULTSORT:Nc (Complexity) Complexity classes Circuit complexity