Mahlo Cardinal
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
mathematics Mathematics is an area of knowledge that includes the topics of numbers, formulas and related structures, shapes and the spaces in which they are contained, and quantities and their changes. These topics are represented in modern mathematics ...
, a Mahlo cardinal is a certain kind of
large cardinal In the mathematical field of set theory, a large cardinal property is a certain kind of property of transfinite cardinal numbers. Cardinals with such properties are, as the name suggests, generally very "large" (for example, bigger than the least Î ...
number. Mahlo cardinals were first described by . As with all large cardinals, none of these varieties of Mahlo cardinals can be proven to exist by ZFC (assuming ZFC is
consistent In classical deductive logic, a consistent theory is one that does not lead to a logical contradiction. The lack of contradiction can be defined in either semantic or syntactic terms. The semantic definition states that a theory is consistent i ...
). A
cardinal number In mathematics, cardinal numbers, or cardinals for short, are a generalization of the natural numbers used to measure the cardinality (size) of sets. The cardinality of a finite set is a natural number: the number of elements in the set. Th ...
\kappa is called strongly Mahlo if \kappa is strongly inaccessible and the
set Set, The Set, SET or SETS may refer to: Science, technology, and mathematics Mathematics *Set (mathematics), a collection of elements *Category of sets, the category whose objects and morphisms are sets and total functions, respectively Electro ...
U = \ is stationary in κ. A cardinal \kappa is called weakly Mahlo if \kappa is weakly inaccessible and the set of weakly inaccessible cardinals less than \kappa is stationary in \kappa. The term "Mahlo cardinal" now usually means "strongly Mahlo cardinal", though the cardinals originally considered by Mahlo were weakly Mahlo cardinals.


Minimal condition sufficient for a Mahlo cardinal

* If κ is a limit ''ordinal'' and the set of regular ordinals less than κ is stationary in κ, then κ is weakly Mahlo. The main difficulty in proving this is to show that κ is regular. We will suppose that it is not regular and construct a club set which gives us a μ such that: :μ = cf(μ) < cf(κ) < μ < κ which is a contradiction. If κ were not regular, then cf(κ) < κ. We could choose a strictly increasing and continuous cf(κ)-sequence which begins with cf(κ)+1 and has κ as its limit. The limits of that sequence would be club in κ. So there must be a regular μ among those limits. So μ is a limit of an initial subsequence of the cf(κ)-sequence. Thus its cofinality is less than the cofinality of κ and greater than it at the same time; which is a contradiction. Thus the assumption that κ is not regular must be false, i.e. κ is regular. No stationary set can exist below \aleph_0 with the required property because is club in ω but contains no regular ordinals; so κ is uncountable. And it is a regular limit of regular cardinals; so it is weakly inaccessible. Then one uses the set of uncountable limit cardinals below κ as a club set to show that the stationary set may be assumed to consist of weak inaccessibles. *If κ is weakly Mahlo and also a strong limit, then κ is Mahlo. κ is weakly inaccessible and a strong limit, so it is strongly inaccessible. We show that the set of uncountable strong limit cardinals below κ is club in κ. Let μ0 be the larger of the threshold and ω1. For each finite n, let μn+1 = 2μn which is less than κ because it is a strong limit cardinal. Then their limit is a strong limit cardinal and is less than κ by its regularity. The limits of uncountable strong limit cardinals are also uncountable strong limit cardinals. So the set of them is club in κ. Intersect that club set with the stationary set of weakly inaccessible cardinals less than κ to get a stationary set of strongly inaccessible cardinals less than κ.


Example: showing that Mahlo cardinals κ are κ-inaccessible (hyper-inaccessible)

The term "hyper-inaccessible" is ambiguous. In this section, a cardinal κ is called hyper-inaccessible if it is κ-inaccessible (as opposed to the more common meaning of 1-inaccessible). Suppose κ is Mahlo. We proceed by transfinite induction on α to show that κ is α-inaccessible for any α ≤ κ. Since κ is Mahlo, κ is inaccessible; and thus 0-inaccessible, which is the same thing. If κ is α-inaccessible, then there are β-inaccessibles (for β < α) arbitrarily close to κ. Consider the set of simultaneous limits of such β-inaccessibles larger than some threshold but less than κ. It is unbounded in κ (imagine rotating through β-inaccessibles for β < α ω-times choosing a larger cardinal each time, then take the limit which is less than κ by regularity (this is what fails if α ≥ κ)). It is closed, so it is club in κ. So, by κ's Mahlo-ness, it contains an inaccessible. That inaccessible is actually an α-inaccessible. So κ is α+1-inaccessible. If λ ≤ κ is a limit ordinal and κ is α-inaccessible for all α < λ, then every β < λ is also less than α for some α < λ. So this case is trivial. In particular, κ is κ-inaccessible and thus hyper-inaccessible. To show that κ is a limit of hyper-inaccessibles and thus 1-hyper-inaccessible, we need to show that the diagonal set of cardinals μ < κ which are α-inaccessible for every α < μ is club in κ. Choose a 0-inaccessible above the threshold, call it α0. Then pick an α0-inaccessible, call it α1. Keep repeating this and taking limits at limits until you reach a fixed point, call it μ. Then μ has the required property (being a simultaneous limit of α-inaccessibles for all α < μ) and is less than κ by regularity. Limits of such cardinals also have the property, so the set of them is club in κ. By Mahlo-ness of κ, there is an inaccessible in this set and it is hyper-inaccessible. So κ is 1-hyper-inaccessible. We can intersect this same club set with the stationary set less than κ to get a stationary set of hyper-inaccessibles less than κ. The rest of the proof that κ is α-hyper-inaccessible mimics the proof that it is α-inaccessible. So κ is hyper-hyper-inaccessible, etc..


α-Mahlo, hyper-Mahlo and greatly Mahlo cardinals

The term α-Mahlo is ambiguous and different authors give inequivalent definitions. One definition is that a cardinal κ is called α-Mahlo for some ordinal α if κ is strongly inaccessible and for every ordinal β<α, the set of β-Mahlo cardinals below κ is stationary in κ. However the condition "κ is strongly inaccessible" is sometimes replaced by other conditions, such as "κ is regular" or "κ is weakly inaccessible" or "κ is Mahlo". We can define "hyper-Mahlo", "α-hyper-Mahlo", "hyper-hyper-Mahlo", "weakly α-Mahlo", "weakly hyper-Mahlo", "weakly α-hyper-Mahlo", and so on, by analogy with the definitions for inaccessibles, so for example a cardinal κ is called hyper-Mahlo if it is κ-Mahlo. A cardinal κ is greatly Mahlo or κ+-Mahlo if and only if it is inaccessible and there is a normal (i.e. nontrivial and closed under
diagonal intersection Diagonal intersection is a term used in mathematics, especially in set theory. If \displaystyle\delta is an ordinal number and \displaystyle\langle X_\alpha \mid \alpha<\delta\rangle is a
s) κ-complete
filter Filter, filtering or filters may refer to: Science and technology Computing * Filter (higher-order function), in functional programming * Filter (software), a computer program to process a data stream * Filter (video), a software component tha ...
on the power set of κ that is closed under the Mahlo operation, which maps the set of ordinals ''S'' to The properties of being inaccessible, Mahlo, weakly Mahlo, α-Mahlo, greatly Mahlo, etc. are preserved if we replace the universe by an
inner model In set theory, a branch of mathematical logic, an inner model for a theory ''T'' is a substructure of a model ''M'' of a set theory that is both a model for ''T'' and contains all the ordinals of ''M''. Definition Let L = \langle \in \rangle be ...
. Every reflecting cardinal has strictly more consistency strength than a greatly Mahlo, but inaccessible reflecting cardinals aren't in general Mahlo -- see https://mathoverflow.net/q/212597


The Mahlo operation

If ''X'' is a class of ordinals, them we can form a new class of ordinals ''M''(''X'') consisting of the ordinals α of uncountable cofinality such that α∩''X'' is stationary in α. This operation ''M'' is called the Mahlo operation. It can be used to define Mahlo cardinals: for example, if ''X'' is the class of regular cardinals, then ''M''(''X'') is the class of weakly Mahlo cardinals. The condition that α has uncountable cofinality ensures that the closed unbounded subsets of α are closed under intersection and so form a filter; in practice the elements of ''X'' often already have uncountable cofinality in which case this condition is redundant. Some authors add the condition that α is in ''X'', which in practice usually makes little difference as it is often automatically satisfied. For a fixed regular uncountable cardinal κ, the Mahlo operation induces an operation on the Boolean algebra of all subsets of κ modulo the non-stationary ideal. The Mahlo operation can be iterated transfinitely as follows: *''M''0(''X'') = ''X'' *''M''α+1(''X'') = ''M''(''M''α(''X'')) *If α is a limit ordinal then ''M''α(''X'') is the intersection of ''M''β(''X'') for β<α These iterated Mahlo operations produce the classes of α-Mahlo cardinals starting with the class of strongly inaccessible cardinals. It is also possible to diagonalize this process by defining *''M''Δ(''X'') is the set of ordinals α that are in ''M''β(''X'') for β<α. And of course this diagonalization process can be iterated too. The diagonalized Mahlo operation produces the hyper-Mahlo cardinals, and so on.


Mahlo cardinals and reflection principles

Axiom F is the statement that every normal function on the ordinals has a regular fixed point. (This is not a first-order axiom as it quantifies over all normal functions, so it can be considered either as a second-order axiom or as an axiom scheme.) A cardinal is called Mahlo if every normal function on it has a regular fixed point, so axiom F is in some sense saying that the class of all ordinals is Mahlo. A cardinal κ is Mahlo if and only if a second-order form of axiom F holds in ''V''κ. Axiom F is in turn equivalent to the statement that for any formula φ with parameters there are arbitrarily large inaccessible ordinals α such that ''V''α reflects φ (in other words φ holds in ''V''α if and only if it holds in the whole universe) .


Appearance in Borel diagonalization

has shown that existence of Mahlo cardinals is a necessary assumption in a sense to prove certain theorems about Borel functions on products of the closed unit interval. Let Q be ,1\omega, the \omega-fold iterated Cartesian product of the closed unit interval with itself. The group (H,\cdot) of all permutations of \mathbb N that move only finitely many natural numbers can be seen as acting on Q by permuting coordinates. The group action \cdot also acts diagonally on any of the products Q^n, by defining an abuse of notation g\cdot(x_1,\ldots,x_n)=(g\cdot x_1,\ldots, g\cdot x_n). For x,y\in Q^n, let x\sim y if x and y are in the same orbit under this diagonal action. Let F:Q\times Q^n\to ,1/math> be a Borel function such that for any x\in Q^n and y,z\in Q, if y\sim z then F(x,y)=F(x,z). Then there is a sequence (x_k)_ such that for all sequences of indices s, F(x_s,(x_,\ldots,x_)) is the first coordinate of x_. This theorem is provable in ZFC+\forall(n<\omega)\exists\kappa(\kappa\; \textrm\; n\textrm), but not in any theory ZFC+\exists\kappa(\kappa\; \textrm\; n\textrm) for some fixed n<\omega.


See also

*
Inaccessible cardinal In set theory, an uncountable cardinal is inaccessible if it cannot be obtained from smaller cardinals by the usual operations of cardinal arithmetic. More precisely, a cardinal is strongly inaccessible if it is uncountable, it is not a sum of ...
*
Stationary set In mathematics, specifically set theory and model theory, a stationary set is a set that is not too small in the sense that it intersects all club sets, and is analogous to a set of non-zero measure in measure theory. There are at least three close ...
*
Inner model In set theory, a branch of mathematical logic, an inner model for a theory ''T'' is a substructure of a model ''M'' of a set theory that is both a model for ''T'' and contains all the ordinals of ''M''. Definition Let L = \langle \in \rangle be ...


Notes


References

* * * * * *{{Citation , last1=Mahlo , first1=Paul , authorlink=Paul Mahlo , title=Zur Theorie und Anwendung der Ï0-Zahlen II, year=1913 , journal=Berichte über die Verhandlungen der Königlich Sächsischen Gesellschaft der Wissenschaften zu Leipzig. Mathematisch-Physische Klasse , volume=65 , pages=268–282 , jfm =44.0092.02 Large cardinals