Moral sense theory (also known as moral sentimentalism) is a theory in moral
epistemology
Epistemology (; ), or the theory of knowledge, is the branch of philosophy concerned with knowledge. Epistemology is considered a major subfield of philosophy, along with other major subfields such as ethics, logic, and metaphysics.
Episte ...
and
meta-ethics
In metaphilosophy and ethics, meta-ethics is the study of the nature, scope, and meaning of moral judgment. It is one of the three branches of ethics generally studied by philosophers, the others being normative ethics (questions of how one ou ...
concerning the discovery of moral truths. Moral sense theory typically holds that distinctions between
morality
Morality () is the differentiation of intentions, decisions and actions between those that are distinguished as proper (right) and those that are improper (wrong). Morality can be a body of standards or principles derived from a code of cond ...
and
immorality
Immorality is the violation of moral laws, norms or standards. It refers to an agent doing or thinking something they know or believe to be wrong. Immorality is normally applied to people or actions, or in a broader sense, it can be applied t ...
are discovered by emotional responses to experience. Some take it to be primarily a view about the nature of moral facts or moral beliefs (a primarily metaphysical view)—this form of the view more often goes by the name "sentimentalism". Others take the view to be primarily about the nature of justifying moral beliefs (a primarily epistemological view)—this form of the view more often goes by the name "moral sense theory". However, some theorists take the view to be one which claims that both moral facts and how one comes to be justified in believing them are necessarily bound up with human emotions.
Popular historical advocates of some version of the moral sense theory or sentimentalism include the
3rd Earl of Shaftesbury
Anthony Ashley Cooper, 3rd Earl of Shaftesbury (26 February 1671 – 16 February 1713) was an English politician, philosopher, and writer.
Early life
He was born at Exeter House in London, the son of the future Anthony Ashley Cooper, 2nd Earl ...
(1671–1713),
Francis Hutcheson (1694–1746),
David Hume
David Hume (; born David Home; 7 May 1711 NS (26 April 1711 OS) – 25 August 1776) Cranston, Maurice, and Thomas Edmund Jessop. 2020 999br>David Hume" ''Encyclopædia Britannica''. Retrieved 18 May 2020. was a Scottish Enlightenment phil ...
(1711–1776), and
Adam Smith (1723–1790). Some contemporary advocates include
Michael Slote
Michael A. Slote is a professor of ethics at the University of Miami and an author of a number of books.
He was previously professor of philosophy at the University of Maryland, and at Trinity College Dublin. He received his Ph.D. from H ...
, Justin D'Arms, Daniel Jacobson,
Jesse Prinz
Jesse J. Prinz is a Distinguished Professor of philosophy and Director of the Committee for Interdisciplinary Science Studies at the Graduate Center of the City University of New York.
Prinz works primarily in the philosophy of psychology and ...
,
Jonathan Haidt
Jonathan David Haidt (; born October 19, 1963) is an American social psychologist and author. He is the Thomas Cooley Professor of Ethical Leadership at New York University Stern School of Business. His main areas of study are the psychology of ...
, and perhaps
John McDowell
John Henry McDowell, FBA (born 7 March 1942) is a South African philosopher, formerly a fellow of University College, Oxford, and now university professor at the University of Pittsburgh. Although he has written on metaphysics, epistemology ...
.
Simon Blackburn and
Allan Gibbard endorse a
non-cognitivist form of sentimentalism.
Intuition versus moral sense
Some use the term "
ethical intuitionism" in
moral philosophy
Ethics or moral philosophy is a branch of philosophy that "involves systematizing, defending, and recommending concepts of right and wrong behavior".''Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' The field of ethics, along with aesthetics, concerns ...
to refer to the general position that we have some non-inferential moral knowledge (that is, basic moral knowledge that is not inferred from or based on any proposition). On this definition, moral sense theory is a form of ethical intuitionism.
However, it is important to distinguish between
empiricist versus
rationalist models of this. One may thus distinguish between
rationalist ethical intuitionism for the rationalist version and "moral sense theory" for the empiricist version. (This will be the use of the terms here. However, the terminology is not ultimately important, so long as one keeps in mind the relevant differences between these two models of non-inferential moral knowledge.)
History
The first prominent moral sense theory (especially using the term "sense") is found in
Mencius
Mencius ( ); born Mèng Kē (); or Mèngzǐ (; 372–289 BC) was a Chinese Confucian philosopher who has often been described as the "second Sage", that is, second to Confucius himself. He is part of Confucius' fourth generation of disciple ...
(372–289 BCE). The eponymous text deals with an innate moral sense possessed by all human beings. All orthodox interpretations of
Confucianism
Confucianism, also known as Ruism or Ru classicism, is a system of thought and behavior originating in ancient China. Variously described as tradition, a philosophy, a religion, a humanistic or rationalistic religion, a way of governing, or ...
accept this view, several unorthodox groups make a point of refuting it (see:
Xunzi). This line of thinking reached its most extreme iteration in
xinxue, a form of
Neo-Confucianism associated with the
Ming Dynasty
The Ming dynasty (), officially the Great Ming, was an Dynasties in Chinese history, imperial dynasty of China, ruling from 1368 to 1644 following the collapse of the Mongol Empire, Mongol-led Yuan dynasty. The Ming dynasty was the last ort ...
and
Wang Yangming
Wang Shouren (, 26 October 1472 – 9 January 1529), courtesy name Bo'an (), art name Yangmingzi (), usually referred to as Wang Yangming (), was a Chinese calligrapher, general, philosopher, politician, and writer during the Ming dynast ...
.
In the west, the first prominent moral sense theory is found in
Anthony Ashley-Cooper, 3rd Earl of Shaftesbury
Anthony Ashley Cooper, 3rd Earl of Shaftesbury (26 February 1671 – 16 February 1713) was an English politician, philosopher, and writer.
Early life
He was born at Exeter House in London, the son of the future Anthony Ashley Cooper, 2nd ...
(1671–1713). His major work espousing a form of moral sense theory is ''An Inquiry Concerning Virtue, or Merit'' (first published in an unauthorized edition in 1699).
Subsequently,
Francis Hutcheson (1694–1746) developed a version of moral sense theory. The chief statements of his theory occur in ''An Inquiry Concerning the Original of Our Ideas of Virtue or Moral Good'' (1725; Treatise II of ''An Inquiry Into the Original of Our Ideas of Beauty and Virtue'') and ''An Essay On the Nature and Conduct of the Passions and Affections, With Illustrations Upon the Moral Sense'' (1728).
Arguably the most prominent defender of moral sense theory in the history of philosophy is
David Hume
David Hume (; born David Home; 7 May 1711 NS (26 April 1711 OS) – 25 August 1776) Cranston, Maurice, and Thomas Edmund Jessop. 2020 999br>David Hume" ''Encyclopædia Britannica''. Retrieved 18 May 2020. was a Scottish Enlightenment phil ...
(1711–1776). While he discusses morality in Book 3 of his ''
Treatise of Human Nature'' (1739–40), Hume's most mature, positive account of the moral sense is found in ''
An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals
''An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals'' (''EPM'') is a book by Scottish enlightenment philosopher David Hume. In it, Hume argues (among other things) that the foundations of morals lie with sentiment, not reason.
''An Enquiry Concern ...
'' (1751).
Adam Smith also advanced a form of moral sense theory in his ''
The Theory of Moral Sentiments
''The Theory of Moral Sentiments'' is a 1759 book by Adam Smith. It provided the ethical, philosophical, economic, and methodological underpinnings to Smith's later works, including ''The Wealth of Nations'' (1776), '' Essays on Philosophical ...
'' (1759). Smith focused less on a single faculty of the moral sense and more on the various sentiments that make up the moral feelings that ground moral judgments.
Thomas Reid
Thomas Reid (; 7 May ( O.S. 26 April) 1710 – 7 October 1796) was a religiously trained Scottish philosopher. He was the founder of the Scottish School of Common Sense and played an integral role in the Scottish Enlightenment. In 1783 he w ...
(1710–1796) defends moral sense theory in his ''Essays on the Active Powers of the Human Mind''. He compares the moral sense to sight and hearing, and defends its veridicality on the same ground as those.
The introduction of
Herbert Spencer
Herbert Spencer (27 April 1820 – 8 December 1903) was an English philosopher, psychologist, biologist, anthropologist, and sociologist famous for his hypothesis of social Darwinism. Spencer originated the expression "survival of the fittest ...
's ''
Social Statics'' argued on behalf of moral sense theory.
Overview
The moral sense is often described as providing information in a way analogous to other sensory modalities, such as sight in the perception of colors. It is contrasted with the way in which one acquires ''a priori'', non-empirical knowledge, such as mathematical knowledge for example.
One way to understand the moral sense is to draw an analogy between it and other kinds of senses. Beauty is something we see in some faces, artworks and landscapes. We can also hear it in some pieces of music. We clearly do not need an independent aesthetic sense faculty to perceive beauty in the world. Our ordinary five senses are quite enough to observe it, though merely observing something beautiful is not by itself enough to appreciate its beauty. Suppose we give a name to this ability to appreciate the beauty in things we see: let's call it the aesthetic sense.
This aesthetic sense does not come automatically to all people with perfect vision and hearing, so it is fair to describe it as something extra, something not wholly reducible to vision and hearing. As the aesthetic sense informs us about what is beautiful, we can
analogically understand the ''moral sense'' as informing us of what is good. People with a functioning moral sense get a clear impression of wrongness when they see (or perhaps even imagine) someone being mugged, for example.
However, though the wrongness is obvious, we may find it very difficult to list the features of the scene which account for the wrongness. We discover wrongness through observing natural properties with our five senses. Can we list the necessary and sufficient conditions such that any action which satisfies these conditions is wrong?
The
Ethical Naturalist thinks that in principle, we can. For naturalists, rightness and wrongness are nothing more than certain combinations of natural, non-evaluative properties. Since we can in principle build mechanical detectors for all these natural properties, the
Ethical Naturalist thinks wrongness is something that a machine could eventually detect.
The ethical intuitionist typically disagrees (although, it is not essential to the view): they see a wide conceptual gap between
natural facts and evaluations. There seem to be no valid arguments in which purely descriptive/factual premises entail a prescriptive/evaluative conclusion.
Ethical intuitionists claim that only an agent with a moral sense can observe natural properties and through them discover the moral properties of the situation. Without the moral sense, you might see and hear all the colors and yelps, but the moral properties would remain hidden, and there would be in principle no way to ever discover them (except, of course, via testimony from someone else with a moral sense).
Criticisms
The key opponents of moral sense theory (as a primarily epistemological view) are rationalist
ethical intuitionists—such as
G.E. Moore (1903),
W.D. Ross (1930), and
Michael Huemer (2005), and other
moral rationalists, such as
Immanuel Kant
Immanuel Kant (, , ; 22 April 1724 – 12 February 1804) was a German philosopher and one of the central Enlightenment thinkers. Born in Königsberg, Kant's comprehensive and systematic works in epistemology, metaphysics, ethics, and aes ...
and
Samuel Clarke.
For a recent criticism of sentimentalism (as a primarily metaphysical thesis), see François Schroeter (2006). D'Arms and Jacobson (2000) also provide a recent critique; however, they criticize "simple sentimentalism" and defend a more "sophisticated sentimentalism".
Joshua Greene criticizes the epistemic basis of moral sentimentalism because of beliefs formed in response to morally irrelevant factors. These factors change our moral decisions, but they should not because they do not have a bearing on the morality of the decision. The example he uses is the
trolley problem
The trolley problem is a series of thought experiments in ethics and psychology, involving stylized ethical dilemmas of whether to sacrifice one person to save a larger number. The series usually begins with a scenario in which a runaway tram o ...
and compares it to the
fat man rendition of it. Empirical data shows that people chose differently between the two scenarios, despite them being the same moral dilemma, the only difference being pulling a switch in the former and pushing the man in the latter.
See also
*
Ethical intuitionism
References and further reading
* Campbell, Richmond (2003). "Moral Epistemology", ''The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' Edward N. Zalta (ed.).
link
* Cohon, Rachel (2004). "Hume's Moral Philosophy", ''The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'', E. Zalta (ed.).
link
* D'Arms, J. & Jacobson, D. (2000). "Sentiment and Value", ''Ethics'', Vol. 110, No. 4, pp. 722–748.
* Fieser, James (2006). "David Hume (1711-1776) - Moral Theory", ''The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy'', J. Fieser and B.H. Dowden (eds.) U. Tennessee/Martin.
* Gill, Michael B. (2006). "Lord Shaftesbury
nthony Ashley Cooper, 3rd Earl of Shaftesbury, ''The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' (Winter 2006 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.).
link
* Kauppinan, Antii (2014). " Moral Sentimentalism", ''The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2018 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.).
'
*Moore, G.E. (1903). ''Principia Ethica'', Cambridge University Press.
* Prinz, Jesse (2006). "The Emotional Basis of Moral Judgments", ''Philosophical Explorations'', vol. 9, no. 1.
* Ross, W.D. (1930). ''The Right and the Good'', Oxford: Clarendon Press.
* Huemer, Michael (2005). ''Ethical Intuitionism'', Palgrave Macmillan.
* Raphael, D.D. (ed.) (1991). ''British Moralists: 1650-1800'', 2 Vols., Indianapolis, IN: Hackett Publishing. Company.
* Schroeter, François (2006). "The Limits of Sentimentalism", ''Ethics'', Vol. 116, pp. 337–361.
* Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter (2006a). "Moral Skepticism", ''The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'', Edward N. Zalta (ed.).
link
* Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter (2006b). ''Moral Skepticisms'', Oxford University Press.
* Kane, Robert H. Quest for Meaning: Values, Ethics, and the Modern Experience. Lecture 6, "Hume and the Challenge of Relativism"and Lecture 7, "Cultural Diversity, Human Nature, and the Social Sciences". The Teaching Company
References
{{Reflist
External links
Hume's Moral Philosophy ''Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy''
Concepts in epistemology
Concepts in ethics
Concepts in logic
Concepts in metaphilosophy
Concepts in metaphysics
Concepts in the philosophy of mind
Meta-ethics