The
language of mathematics has a vast
vocabulary of specialist and technical terms. It also has a certain amount of
jargon: commonly used phrases which are part of the culture of mathematics, rather than of the subject. Jargon often appears in lectures, and sometimes in print, as informal shorthand for
rigorous arguments or precise ideas. Much of this is common English, but with a specific non-obvious meaning when used in a mathematical sense.
Some phrases, like "in general", appear below in more than one section.
Philosophy of mathematics
;
abstract nonsense:A
tongue-in-cheek reference to
category theory
Category theory is a general theory of mathematical structures and their relations that was introduced by Samuel Eilenberg and Saunders Mac Lane in the middle of the 20th century in their foundational work on algebraic topology. Nowadays, cate ...
, using which one can employ arguments that establish a (possibly concrete) result without reference to any specifics of the present problem. For that reason, it's also known as ''general abstract nonsense'' or ''generalized abstract nonsense''.
;
canonical:A reference to a standard or choice-free presentation of some
mathematical object (e.g., canonical map, canonical form, or canonical ordering). The same term can also be used more informally to refer to something "standard" or "classic". For example, one might say that
Euclid's proof is the "canonical proof" of
the infinitude of primes.
; deep:A result is called "deep" if its proof requires concepts and methods that are advanced beyond the concepts needed to formulate the result. For example, the
prime number theorem
In mathematics, the prime number theorem (PNT) describes the asymptotic distribution of the prime numbers among the positive integers. It formalizes the intuitive idea that primes become less common as they become larger by precisely quantifying ...
— originally proved using techniques of
complex analysis
Complex analysis, traditionally known as the theory of functions of a complex variable, is the branch of mathematical analysis that investigates Function (mathematics), functions of complex numbers. It is helpful in many branches of mathemati ...
— was once thought to be a deep result until
elementary proofs were found. On the other hand, the fact that
π is irrational is usually known to be a deep result, because it requires a considerable development of
real analysis before the proof can be established — even though the claim itself can be stated in terms of simple
number theory and
geometry.
;
elegant:An aesthetic term referring to the ability of an idea to provide insight into mathematics, whether by unifying disparate fields, introducing a new perspective on a single field, or by providing a technique of proof which is either particularly simple, or which captures the intuition or imagination as to why the result it proves is true. In some occasions, the term "beautiful" can also be used to the same effect, though
Gian-Carlo Rota distinguished between ''elegance of presentation'' and ''beauty of concept'', saying that for example, some topics could be written about elegantly although the mathematical content is not beautiful, and some
theorems or proofs are beautiful but may be written about inelegantly.
;
elementary:A proof or a result is called "elementary" if it only involves basic concepts and methods in the field, and is to be contrasted with
deep results which require more development within or outside the field. The concept of "elementary proof" is used specifically in
number theory, where it usually refers to a proof that does not resort to methods from
complex analysis
Complex analysis, traditionally known as the theory of functions of a complex variable, is the branch of mathematical analysis that investigates Function (mathematics), functions of complex numbers. It is helpful in many branches of mathemati ...
.
;
folklore :A result is called "folklore" if it is non-obvious, non-published, yet somehow generally known to the specialists within a field. In many scenarios, it is unclear as to who first obtained the result, though if the result is significant, it may eventually find its way into the textbooks, whereupon it ceases to be folklore.
;
natural:Similar to "canonical" but more specific, and which makes reference to a description (almost exclusively in the context of
transformations) which holds independently of any choices. Though long used informally, this term has found a formal definition in category theory.
;
pathological:An object behaves pathologically (or, somewhat more broadly used, in a ''degenerated'' way) if it either fails to conform to the generic behavior of such objects, fails to satisfy certain context-dependent regularity properties, or simply disobeys
mathematical intuition. In many occasions, these can be and often are contradictory requirements, while in other occasions, the term is more deliberately used to refer to an object artificially constructed as a counterexample to these properties. A simple example is that from the definition of a
triangle having
angles which sum to π radians, a single straight line conforms to this definition pathologically.
:Note for that latter quote that as the differentiable functions are
meagre in the space of continuous functions, as
Banach found out in 1931, differentiable functions are colloquially speaking a rare exception among the continuous ones. Thus it can hardly be defended any-more to call non-differentiable continuous functions pathological.
;
rigor (rigour):The act of establishing a mathematical result using indisputable logic, rather than informal descriptive argument. Rigor is a cornerstone quality of mathematics, and can play an important role in preventing mathematics from degenerating into fallacies.
;
well-behaved:An object is well-behaved (in contrast with being ''
pathological'') if it satisfies certain prevailing regularity properties, or if it conforms to mathematical intuition (even though intuition can often suggest opposite behaviors as well). In some occasions (e.g.,
analysis), the term "
smooth''"'' can also be used to the same effect.
Descriptive informalities
Although ultimately every mathematical argument must meet a high standard of precision, mathematicians use descriptive but informal statements to discuss recurring themes or concepts with unwieldy formal statements. Note that many of the terms are completely rigorous in context.
;
almost all
In mathematics, the term "almost all" means "all but a negligible amount". More precisely, if X is a set, "almost all elements of X" means "all elements of X but those in a negligible subset of X". The meaning of "negligible" depends on the math ...
: A shorthand term for "all except for a
set of
measure zero", when there is a
measure
Measure may refer to:
* Measurement, the assignment of a number to a characteristic of an object or event
Law
* Ballot measure, proposed legislation in the United States
* Church of England Measure, legislation of the Church of England
* Mea ...
to speak of. For example, "almost all
real numbers are
transcendental
Transcendence, transcendent, or transcendental may refer to:
Mathematics
* Transcendental number, a number that is not the root of any polynomial with rational coefficients
* Algebraic element or transcendental element, an element of a field exten ...
" because the
algebraic real numbers form a
countable subset
In mathematics, Set (mathematics), set ''A'' is a subset of a set ''B'' if all Element (mathematics), elements of ''A'' are also elements of ''B''; ''B'' is then a superset of ''A''. It is possible for ''A'' and ''B'' to be equal; if they are ...
of the real numbers with measure zero. One can also speak of "almost all"
integers having a property to mean "all except finitely many", despite the integers not admitting a measure for which this agrees with the previous usage. For example, "almost all prime numbers are
odd". There is a more complicated meaning for integers as well, discussed in the main article. Finally, this term is sometimes used synonymously with ''generic'', below.
;
arbitrarily large: Notions which arise mostly in the context of
limits, referring to the recurrence of a phenomenon as the limit is approached. A statement such as that predicate ''P'' is satisfied by arbitrarily large values, can be expressed in more formal notation by . See also ''frequently''. The statement that quantity ''f''(''x'') depending on ''x'' "can be made" arbitrarily large, corresponds to .
;
arbitrary: A shorthand for the
universal quantifier
In mathematical logic, a universal quantification is a type of quantifier, a logical constant which is interpreted as "given any" or "for all". It expresses that a predicate can be satisfied by every member of a domain of discourse. In other w ...
. An arbitrary choice is one which is made unrestrictedly, or alternatively, a statement holds of an arbitrary element of a set if it holds of any element of that set. Also much in general-language use among mathematicians: "Of course, this problem can be arbitrarily complicated".
;
eventually:In the context of limits, this is shorthand meaning ''for sufficiently large arguments''; the relevant argument(s) are implicit in the context. As an example, the function log(log(''x'')) ''eventually'' becomes larger than 100"; in this context, "eventually" means "for
sufficiently large
In the mathematical areas of number theory and analysis, an infinite sequence or a function is said to eventually have a certain property, if it doesn't have the said property across all its ordered instances, but will after some instances have pas ...
''x''."
;
factor through: A term in
category theory
Category theory is a general theory of mathematical structures and their relations that was introduced by Samuel Eilenberg and Saunders Mac Lane in the middle of the 20th century in their foundational work on algebraic topology. Nowadays, cate ...
referring to composition of
morphism
In mathematics, particularly in category theory, a morphism is a structure-preserving map from one mathematical structure to another one of the same type. The notion of morphism recurs in much of contemporary mathematics. In set theory, morphisms a ...
s. If for three
objects ''A'', ''B'', and ''C'' a map
can be written as a composition
with
and
, then ''f'' is said to ''factor through'' any (and all) of
,
, and
.
; finite: "Not infinite". For example, if the
variance of a random variable is said to be finite, this implies it is a non-negative real number.
; frequently: In the context of limits, this is shorthand for ''
arbitrarily large arguments'' and its relatives; as with ''eventually'', the intended variant is implicit. As an example, the
sequence is frequently in the
interval (1/2, 3/2), because there are arbitrarily large ''n'' for which the value of the sequence is in the interval.
;
; formal, formally: Qualifies anything that is sufficiently precise to be translated straightforwardly in a
formal system. For example. a
formal proof, a formal definition.
;
;
generic: This term has similar connotations as ''almost all'' but is used particularly for concepts outside the purview of
measure theory
In mathematics, the concept of a measure is a generalization and formalization of geometrical measures ( length, area, volume) and other common notions, such as mass and probability of events. These seemingly distinct concepts have many simil ...
. A property holds "generically" on a set if the set satisfies some (context-dependent) notion of density, or perhaps if its
complement satisfies some (context-dependent) notion of smallness. For example, a property which holds on a
dense G
δ (
intersection
In mathematics, the intersection of two or more objects is another object consisting of everything that is contained in all of the objects simultaneously. For example, in Euclidean geometry, when two lines in a plane are not parallel, their i ...
of countably many
open sets) is said to hold generically. In
algebraic geometry
Algebraic geometry is a branch of mathematics, classically studying zeros of multivariate polynomials. Modern algebraic geometry is based on the use of abstract algebraic techniques, mainly from commutative algebra, for solving geometrical ...
, one says that a property of points on an
algebraic variety that holds on a dense
Zariski open
In algebraic geometry and commutative algebra, the Zariski topology is a topology which is primarily defined by its closed sets. It is very different from topologies which are commonly used in the real or complex analysis; in particular, it is ...
set is true generically; however, it is usually not said that a property which holds merely on a dense set (which is not Zariski open) is generic in this situation.
; in general: In a descriptive context, this phrase introduces a simple characterization of a broad class of objects, with an eye towards identifying a unifying principle. This term introduces an "elegant" description which holds for "
arbitrary" objects. Exceptions to this description may be mentioned explicitly, as "
pathological" cases.
;
left-hand side, right-hand side (LHS, RHS): Most often, these refer simply to the left-hand or the right-hand side of an
equation
In mathematics, an equation is a formula that expresses the equality of two expressions, by connecting them with the equals sign . The word ''equation'' and its cognates in other languages may have subtly different meanings; for example, in ...
; for example,
has
on the LHS and
on the RHS. Occasionally, these are used in the sense of
lvalue and rvalue: an RHS is primitive, and an LHS is derivative.
; nice: A mathematical object is colloquially called ''nice'' or ''sufficiently nice'' if it satisfies hypotheses or properties, sometimes unspecified or even unknown, that are especially desirable in a given context. It is an informal antonym for
pathological. For example, one might conjecture that a
differential operator
In mathematics, a differential operator is an operator defined as a function of the differentiation operator. It is helpful, as a matter of notation first, to consider differentiation as an abstract operation that accepts a function and return ...
ought to satisfy a certain boundedness condition "for nice test functions," or one might state that some interesting
topological invariant should be computable "for nice
spaces Spaces may refer to:
* Google Spaces (app), a cross-platform application for group messaging and sharing
* Windows Live Spaces, the next generation of MSN Spaces
* Spaces (software), a virtual desktop manager implemented in Mac OS X Leopard
* Spac ...
''X''."
; onto: A function (which in mathematics is generally defined as mapping the elements of one set ''A'' to elements of another ''B'') is called "''A'' onto ''B''" (instead of "''A'' to ''B''" or "''A'' into ''B''") only if it is
surjective
In mathematics, a surjective function (also known as surjection, or onto function) is a function that every element can be mapped from element so that . In other words, every element of the function's codomain is the image of one element of i ...
; it may even be said that "''f'' is onto" (i. e. surjective). Not translatable (without circumlocutions) to some languages other than English.
; proper: If, for some notion of substructure, objects are substructures of themselves (that is, the relationship is
reflexive), then the qualification ''proper'' requires the objects to be different. For example, a ''proper'' subset of a set ''S'' is a subset of ''S'' that is different from ''S'', and a ''proper''
divisor of a number ''n'' is a divisor of ''n'' that is different from ''n''. This
overloaded word is also non-jargon for a
proper morphism.
; regular : A function is called ''regular'' if it satisfies satisfactory continuity and differentiability properties, which are often context-dependent. These properties might include possessing a specified number of
derivatives, with the function and its derivatives exhibiting some ''nice'' property (see ''nice'' above), such as
Hölder continuity. Informally, this term is sometimes used synonymously with ''smooth'', below. These imprecise uses of the word ''regular'' are not to be confused with the notion of a
regular topological space, which is rigorously defined.
; resp.: (Respectively) A convention to shorten parallel expositions. "''A'' (resp. ''B'')
as some relationship to
As, AS, A. S., A/S or similar may refer to:
Art, entertainment, and media
* A. S. Byatt (born 1936), English critic, novelist, poet and short story writer
* "As" (song), by Stevie Wonder
* , a Spanish sports newspaper
* , an academic male voice ...
''X'' (resp. ''Y'')" means that ''A''
as some relationship to
As, AS, A. S., A/S or similar may refer to:
Art, entertainment, and media
* A. S. Byatt (born 1936), English critic, novelist, poet and short story writer
* "As" (song), by Stevie Wonder
* , a Spanish sports newspaper
* , an academic male voice ...
''X'' and also that ''B''
as (the same) relationship to
As, AS, A. S., A/S or similar may refer to:
Art, entertainment, and media
* A. S. Byatt (born 1936), English critic, novelist, poet and short story writer
* "As" (song), by Stevie Wonder
* , a Spanish sports newspaper
* , an academic male voice ...
''Y''. For example,
squares (resp. triangles) have 4 sides (resp. 3 sides); or
compact (resp.
Lindelöf) spaces are ones where every open
cover has a finite (resp. countable) open subcover.
; sharp: Often, a mathematical theorem will establish constraints on the behavior of some object; for example, a function will be shown to have an
upper or lower bound. The constraint is ''sharp'' (sometimes ''optimal'') if it cannot be made more restrictive without failing in some cases. For example, for
arbitrary non-negative real numbers ''x'', the
exponential function ''e
x'', where
''e'' = 2.7182818..., gives an upper bound on the values of the
quadratic function
In mathematics, a quadratic polynomial is a polynomial of degree two in one or more variables. A quadratic function is the polynomial function defined by a quadratic polynomial. Before 20th century, the distinction was unclear between a polynomial ...
''x''
2. This is not sharp; the gap between the functions is everywhere at least 1. Among the exponential functions of the form α
''x'', setting α = ''e''
2/''e'' = 2.0870652... results in a sharp upper bound; the slightly smaller choice α = 2 fails to produce an upper bound, since then α
3 = 8 < 3
2. In applied fields the word "tight" is often used with the same meaning.
;
smooth: ''Smoothness'' is a concept which mathematics has endowed with many meanings, from simple differentiability to infinite differentiability to
analyticity, and still others which are more complicated. Each such usage attempts to invoke the physically intuitive notion of smoothness.
; strong, stronger: A theorem is said to be ''strong'' if it deduces restrictive results from general hypotheses. One celebrated example is
Donaldson's theorem, which puts tight restraints on what would otherwise appear to be a large class of manifolds. This (informal) usage reflects the opinion of the mathematical community: not only should such a theorem be strong in the descriptive sense (below) but it should also be definitive in its area. A theorem, result, or condition is further called ''stronger'' than another one if a proof of the second can be easily obtained from the first but not conversely. An example is the sequence of theorems:
Fermat's little theorem
Fermat's little theorem states that if ''p'' is a prime number, then for any integer ''a'', the number a^p - a is an integer multiple of ''p''. In the notation of modular arithmetic, this is expressed as
: a^p \equiv a \pmod p.
For example, if = ...
,
Euler's theorem
In number theory, Euler's theorem (also known as the Fermat–Euler theorem or Euler's totient theorem) states that, if and are coprime positive integers, and \varphi(n) is Euler's totient function, then raised to the power \varphi(n) is congru ...
,
Lagrange's theorem, each of which is stronger than the last; another is that a sharp upper bound (see ''sharp'' above) is a stronger result than a non-sharp one. Finally, the adjective ''strong'' or the adverb ''strongly'' may be added to a mathematical notion to indicate a related stronger notion; for example, a
strong antichain In order theory, a subset ''A'' of a partially ordered set ''P'' is a strong downwards antichain if it is an antichain in which no two distinct elements have a common lower bound in ''P'', that is,
:\forall x, y \in A \; forcing,_authors_will_som ...
is an
antichain
In mathematics, in the area of order theory, an antichain is a subset of a partially ordered set such that any two distinct elements in the subset are incomparable.
The size of the largest antichain in a partially ordered set is known as its w ...
satisfying certain additional conditions, and likewise a
strongly regular graph is a
regular graph meeting stronger conditions. When used in this way, the stronger notion (such as "strong antichain") is a technical term with a precisely defined meaning; the nature of the extra conditions cannot be derived from the definition of the weaker notion (such as "antichain").
;
sufficiently large
In the mathematical areas of number theory and analysis, an infinite sequence or a function is said to eventually have a certain property, if it doesn't have the said property across all its ordered instances, but will after some instances have pas ...
, suitably small, sufficiently close: In the context of limits, these terms refer to some (unspecified, even unknown) point at which a phenomenon prevails as the limit is approached. A statement such as that predicate ''P'' holds for sufficiently large values, can be expressed in more formal notation by ∃''x'' : ∀''y'' ≥ ''x'' : ''P''(''y''). See also ''eventually''.
; upstairs, downstairs: A descriptive term referring to notation in which two objects are written one above the other; the upper one is ''upstairs'' and the lower, ''downstairs''. For example, in a
fiber bundle
In mathematics, and particularly topology, a fiber bundle (or, in Commonwealth English: fibre bundle) is a space that is a product space, but may have a different topological structure. Specifically, the similarity between a space E and a p ...
, the total space is often said to be ''upstairs'', with the base space ''downstairs''. In a
fraction
A fraction (from la, fractus, "broken") represents a part of a whole or, more generally, any number of equal parts. When spoken in everyday English, a fraction describes how many parts of a certain size there are, for example, one-half, eight ...
, the
numerator is occasionally referred to as ''upstairs'' and the
denominator ''downstairs'', as in "bringing a term upstairs".
;
up to Two Mathematical object, mathematical objects ''a'' and ''b'' are called equal up to an equivalence relation ''R''
* if ''a'' and ''b'' are related by ''R'', that is,
* if ''aRb'' holds, that is,
* if the equivalence classes of ''a'' and ''b'' wi ...
, modulo, mod out by: An extension to mathematical discourse of the notions of
modular arithmetic. A statement is true ''up to'' a condition if the establishment of that condition is the only impediment to the truth of the statement. Also used when working with members of
equivalence classes, especially in
category theory
Category theory is a general theory of mathematical structures and their relations that was introduced by Samuel Eilenberg and Saunders Mac Lane in the middle of the 20th century in their foundational work on algebraic topology. Nowadays, cate ...
, where the
equivalence relation
In mathematics, an equivalence relation is a binary relation that is reflexive, symmetric and transitive. The equipollence relation between line segments in geometry is a common example of an equivalence relation.
Each equivalence relation ...
is (categorical) isomorphism; for example, "The tensor product in a weak
monoidal category is associative and unital up to a
natural isomorphism."
; vanish: To assume the value 0. For example, "The function sin(''x'') vanishes for those values of ''x'' that are integer multiples of π." This can also apply to limits: see
Vanish at infinity In mathematics, a function is said to vanish at infinity if its values approach 0 as the input grows without bounds. There are two different ways to define this with one definition applying to functions defined on normed vector spaces and the other ...
.
; weak, weaker: The converse of
strong
Strong may refer to:
Education
* The Strong, an educational institution in Rochester, New York, United States
* Strong Hall (Lawrence, Kansas), an administrative hall of the University of Kansas
* Strong School, New Haven, Connecticut, United Sta ...
.
; well-defined: Accurately and precisely described or specified. For example, sometimes a definition relies on a choice of some object; the result of the definition must then be independent of this choice.
Proof terminology
The formal language of
proof
Proof most often refers to:
* Proof (truth), argument or sufficient evidence for the truth of a proposition
* Alcohol proof, a measure of an alcoholic drink's strength
Proof may also refer to:
Mathematics and formal logic
* Formal proof, a con ...
draws repeatedly from a small pool of ideas, many of which are invoked through various lexical shorthands in practice.
; aliter: An obsolescent term which is used to announce to the reader an alternative method, or proof of a result. In a proof, it therefore flags a piece of reasoning that is superfluous from a logical point of view, but has some other interest.
;
by way of contradiction (BWOC), or "for, if not, ...": The rhetorical prelude to a
proof by contradiction, preceding the
negation
In logic, negation, also called the logical complement, is an operation that takes a proposition P to another proposition "not P", written \neg P, \mathord P or \overline. It is interpreted intuitively as being true when P is false, and false ...
of the statement to be proved.
;
if and only if (iff): An abbreviation for
logical equivalence of statements.
; in general: In the context of proofs, this phrase is often seen in
induction arguments when passing from the base case to the induction step, and similarly, in the definition of sequences whose first few terms are exhibited as examples of the formula giving every term of the sequence.
;
necessary and sufficient: A minor variant on "if and only if"; "''A'' is ''necessary'' (''sufficient'') for ''B''" means "''A'' if (only if) ''B''". For example, "For a
field ''K'' to be
algebraically closed it is necessary and sufficient that it have no finite
field extension
In mathematics, particularly in algebra, a field extension is a pair of fields E\subseteq F, such that the operations of ''E'' are those of ''F'' restricted to ''E''. In this case, ''F'' is an extension field of ''E'' and ''E'' is a subfield of ...
s" means "''K'' is algebraically closed if and only if it has no finite extensions". Often used in lists, as in "The following conditions are necessary and sufficient for a field to be algebraically closed...".
; need to show (NTS), required to prove (RTP), wish to show, want to show (WTS): Proofs sometimes proceed by enumerating several conditions whose satisfaction will together imply the desired theorem; thus, one ''needs to show'' just these statements.
;
one and only one: A statement of the
existence and uniqueness of an object; the object exists, and furthermore, no other such object exists.
;
Q.E.D.
Q.E.D. or QED is an initialism of the Latin phrase , meaning "which was to be demonstrated". Literally it states "what was to be shown". Traditionally, the abbreviation is placed at the end of mathematical proofs and philosophical arguments in pri ...
: (''Quod erat demonstrandum''): A Latin abbreviation, meaning "which was to be demonstrated", historically placed at the end of proofs, but less common currently, having been supplanted by the
Halmos end-of-proof mark, a square sign ∎.
; sufficiently nice: A condition on objects in the scope of the discussion, to be specified later, that will guarantee that some stated property holds for them. When
working out a theorem, the use of this expression in the statement of the theorem indicates that the conditions involved may be not yet known to the speaker, and that the intent is to collect the conditions that will be found to be needed in order for the proof of the theorem to go through.
; the following are equivalent (TFAE): Often several equivalent conditions (especially for a definition, such as
normal subgroup
In abstract algebra, a normal subgroup (also known as an invariant subgroup or self-conjugate subgroup) is a subgroup that is invariant under conjugation by members of the group of which it is a part. In other words, a subgroup N of the group G i ...
) are equally useful in practice; one introduces a theorem stating an equivalence of more than two statements with TFAE.
;
transport of structure
In mathematics, particularly in universal algebra and category theory, transport of structure refers to the process whereby a mathematical object acquires a new structure and its canonical definitions, as a result of being isomorphic to (or ot ...
: It is often the case that two objects are shown to be equivalent in some way, and that one of them is endowed with additional structure. Using the equivalence, we may define such a structure on the second object as well, via ''transport of structure''. For example, any two
vector spaces of the same
dimension are
isomorphic
In mathematics, an isomorphism is a structure-preserving mapping between two structures of the same type that can be reversed by an inverse mapping. Two mathematical structures are isomorphic if an isomorphism exists between them. The word is ...
; if one of them is given an
inner product and if we fix a particular isomorphism, then we may define an inner product on the other space by ''factoring through'' the isomorphism.
;
without (any) loss of generality (WLOG, WOLOG, WALOG), we may assume (WMA): Sometimes a
proposition can be more easily proved with additional assumptions on the objects it concerns. If the proposition as stated follows from this modified one with a simple and minimal explanation (for example, if the remaining special cases are identical but for notation), then the modified assumptions are introduced with this phrase and the altered proposition is proved.
Proof techniques
Mathematicians have several phrases to describe proofs or proof techniques. These are often used as hints for filling in tedious details.
; angle chasing: Used to describe a geometrical proof that involves finding relationships between the various angles in a diagram.
;
back-of-the-envelope calculation: An informal computation omitting much rigor without sacrificing correctness. Often this computation is "proof of concept" and treats only an accessible special case.
; brute force: Rather than finding underlying principles or patterns, this is a method where one would evaluate as many cases as needed to sufficiently prove or provide convincing evidence that the thing in question is true. Sometimes this involves evaluating every possible case (where it is also known as
proof by exhaustion).
; by example: A ''proof by example'' is an argument whereby a statement is not proved but instead illustrated by an example. If done well, the specific example would easily generalize to a general proof.
; by inspection: A rhetorical shortcut made by authors who invite the reader to verify, at a glance, the correctness of a proposed expression or deduction. If an expression can be evaluated by straightforward application of simple techniques and without recourse to extended calculation or general theory, then it can be evaluated ''by inspection''. It is also applied to solving equations; for example to find roots of a
quadratic equation by inspection is to 'notice' them, or mentally check them. 'By inspection' can play a kind of ''
gestalt'' role: the answer or solution simply clicks into place.
;
by intimidation: Style of proof where claims believed by the author to be easily verifiable are labelled as 'obvious' or 'trivial', which often results in the reader being confused.
; clearly, can be easily shown: A term which shortcuts around calculation the mathematician perceives to be tedious or routine, accessible to any member of the audience with the necessary expertise in the field;
Laplace
Pierre-Simon, marquis de Laplace (; ; 23 March 1749 – 5 March 1827) was a French scholar and polymath whose work was important to the development of engineering, mathematics, statistics, physics, astronomy, and philosophy. He summarized ...
used ''obvious'' (
French
French (french: français(e), link=no) may refer to:
* Something of, from, or related to France
** French language, which originated in France, and its various dialects and accents
** French people, a nation and ethnic group identified with Franc ...
: ''évident'').
; complete intuition : commonly reserved for jokes (puns on
complete induction).
;
diagram chasing:
[Numerous examples can be found in , for example on p. 100.] Given a
commutative diagram
350px, The commutative diagram used in the proof of the five lemma.
In mathematics, and especially in category theory, a commutative diagram is a diagram such that all directed paths in the diagram with the same start and endpoints lead to the s ...
of objects and morphisms between them, if one wishes to prove some property of the morphisms (such as
injectivity) which can be stated in terms of
elements, then the proof can proceed by tracing the path of elements of various objects around the diagram as successive morphisms are applied to it. That is, one ''chases'' elements around the diagram, or does a ''diagram chase''.
;
handwaving: A non-technique of proof mostly employed in lectures, where formal argument is not strictly necessary. It proceeds by omission of details or even significant ingredients, and is merely a plausibility argument.
; in general: In a context not requiring rigor, this phrase often appears as a labor-saving device when the technical details of a complete argument would outweigh the conceptual benefits. The author gives a proof in a simple enough case that the computations are reasonable, and then indicates that "in general" the proof is similar.
; index battle: for proofs involving objects with multiple indices which can be solved by going to the bottom (if anyone wishes to take up the effort). Similar to diagram chasing.
; left as an exercise to the student: Usually reserved for shortcuts which can be ''clearly'' filled-in by any member of the audience with the necessary expertise, but are not so ''trivial'' as to be solvable ''by inspection''.
;
trivial: Similar to ''clearly''. A concept is trivial if it holds by definition, is an immediate
corollary
In mathematics and logic, a corollary ( , ) is a theorem of less importance which can be readily deduced from a previous, more notable statement. A corollary could, for instance, be a proposition which is incidentally proved while proving another ...
to a known statement, or is a simple special case of a more general concept.
See also
*
Glossary of mathematics
This is a glossary featuring terms used across different areas in mathematics, or terms that do not typically appear in more specialized glossaries. For the terms used only in some specific areas of mathematics, see glossaries in :Glossaries of ...
Notes
References
*.
* .
* (Part
Ian
II.
*.
*.
*.
*.
*.
* .
*.
*{{citation
, title = The Seventeen Provers of the World
, editor-last = Wiedijk
, editor-first = Freek
, year = 2006
, publisher = Birkhäuser
, isbn = 978-3-540-30704-4
, url-access = registration
, url = https://archive.org/details/seventeenprovers00free
.
Jargon