Leon Henkin
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

Leon Albert Henkin (April 19, 1921,
Brooklyn, New York Brooklyn () is a borough of New York City, coextensive with Kings County, in the U.S. state of New York. Kings County is the most populous county in the State of New York, and the second-most densely populated county in the United States, be ...
- November 1, 2006,
Oakland, California Oakland is the largest city and the county seat of Alameda County, California, United States. A major West Coast of the United States, West Coast port, Oakland is the largest city in the East Bay region of the San Francisco Bay Area, the third ...
) was an American logician, whose works played a strong role in the development of logic, particularly in the
theory of types In mathematics, logic, and computer science, a type theory is the formal presentation of a specific type system, and in general type theory is the academic study of type systems. Some type theories serve as alternatives to set theory as a founda ...
. He was an active scholar at the
University of California The University of California (UC) is a public land-grant research university system in the U.S. state of California. The system is composed of the campuses at Berkeley, Davis, Irvine, Los Angeles, Merced, Riverside, San Diego, San Franci ...
, Berkeley, where he made great contributions as a researcher, teacher, as well as in administrative positions. At this university he directed, together with
Alfred Tarski Alfred Tarski (, born Alfred Teitelbaum;School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews ''School of Mathematics and Statistics, University of St Andrews''. January 14, 1901 – October 26, 1983) was a Polish-American logician a ...
, the
Group in Logic and the Methodology of Science
',Manzano, María; Alonso, Enrique (2014). «Leon Henkin». In Manzano et al., María, ed. ''The Life and Work of Leon Henkin''. Springer International Publishing. pp. 3-22. . doi:10.1007/978-3-319-09719-0_11. from which many important logicians and philosophers emerged. He had a strong sense of social commitment and was a passionate defensor of his pacifist and progressive ideas. He took part in many social projects aimed at teaching mathematics, as well as projects aimed at supporting women's and minority groups to pursue careers in mathematics and related fields. A lover of dance and literature, he appreciated life in all its facets: art, culture, science and, above all, the warmth of human relations. He is remembered by his students for his great kindness, as well as for his academic and teaching excellence. Henkin is mainly known for his completeness proofs of diverse
formal system A formal system is an abstract structure used for inferring theorems from axioms according to a set of rules. These rules, which are used for carrying out the inference of theorems from axioms, are the logical calculus of the formal system. A form ...
s, such as type theory and
first-order logic First-order logic—also known as predicate logic, quantificational logic, and first-order predicate calculus—is a collection of formal systems used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. First-order logic uses quantifie ...
(the completeness of the latter, in its weak version, had been proven by Kurt Gödel in 1929). To prove the completeness of Type Theory, Henkin introduces new semantics, based on certain structures, called general models (also known as ''
Henkin models Henkin is a Jewish last name and may refer to the following people: * Leon Henkin, logician and mathematician ** Henkin quantifier, a concept he pioneered * Gennadi Henkin, mathematician * William A. Henkin, psychotherapist and sex therapist * Y ...
''). The change of semantics that he proposed permits to provide a complete deductive calculus for Type Theory and for
Second-Order Logic In logic and mathematics, second-order logic is an extension of first-order logic, which itself is an extension of propositional logic. Second-order logic is in turn extended by higher-order logic and type theory. First-order logic quantifies on ...
, amongst other logics. Henkin methods have aided to prove various model theory results, both in classical and non-classical logics. Besides logic, the other branch on which his investigations were centered was
algebra Algebra () is one of the broad areas of mathematics. Roughly speaking, algebra is the study of mathematical symbols and the rules for manipulating these symbols in formulas; it is a unifying thread of almost all of mathematics. Elementary ...
; he specialized in
cylindric algebra In mathematics, the notion of cylindric algebra, invented by Alfred Tarski, arises naturally in the algebraization of first-order logic with equality. This is comparable to the role Boolean algebras play for propositional logic. Cylindric algebra ...
s, in which he worked together with A. Tarski and D. Monk.Monk, Donald (2014). «Leon Henkin and Cylindric Algebras.». In Manzano et al., ed. ''The Life and Work of Leon Henkin, Essays on His Contributions'' (en inglés). Springer International Publishing. pp. 59-66. . doi:10.1007/978-3-319-09719-0_11. As for the philosophy of mathematics, although the works in which he explicitly approaches it are scarce, he can be considered to have a
nominalist In metaphysics, nominalism is the view that universals and abstract objects do not actually exist other than being merely names or labels. There are at least two main versions of nominalism. One version denies the existence of universalsthings th ...
position.Manzano, María (2014). «Henkin on Completeness». In Manzano et al., ed. ''The Life and Work of Leon Henkin, Essays on His Contributions''. Springer International Publishing. pp. 149-173. . doi:10.1007/978-3-319-09719-0_11.


Life


Childhood and first youth

Leon Albert Henkin was born on April 19, 1921, in Brooklyn, New York, to a Jewish family that had emigrated from Russia a generation earlier. The first of the family to emigrate was Abraham Henkin, the eldest of the brothers of Leon's father. According to Leon,Henkin, Leon (1996-06). «The Discovery of My Completeness Proofs». ''Bulletin of Symbolic Logic'' 2 (2): 127-158. ISSN 1079-8986. doi:10.2307/421107. his father had been extremely proud of him since he was just a boy. His high expectations were evident in the name he gave him: he chose to name his son Albert after a series of articles on Einstein's
theory of relativity The theory of relativity usually encompasses two interrelated theories by Albert Einstein: special relativity and general relativity, proposed and published in 1905 and 1915, respectively. Special relativity applies to all physical phenomena in ...
that the ''New York Times'' published shortly before Henkin's birth. His family was sympathetic with pacifist and progressive ideas, and although he was not religious, he had deeply rooted Jewish traditions. Leon grew up surrounded by tight family ties; he was very close to his cousins, with whom he lived during his childhood in Brooklyn. Henkin studied primarily in New York City public schools; he attended Lincoln High School, where he graduated at age 16 to enter
Columbia University Columbia University (also known as Columbia, and officially as Columbia University in the City of New York) is a private research university in New York City. Established in 1754 as King's College on the grounds of Trinity Church in Manhatt ...
. Both in college and high school he was a member of the chess teams; he always preferred games that involved rational thinking to games of chance. In the years of his high school education, Henkin considered becoming a math teacher and also came to desire to become a writer (as he later expressed in a personal letter). Although he dedicated himself to university academic life, he never abandoned his interest in teaching elementary mathematics, to which he later actively contributed.


The first university studies

In 1937 Leon entered Columbia University as a mathematics student. It was during his time at this institution that he developed an interest in logic, which would determine the course of his academic career. His first contact with logic was through B. Russell's book, "''Mysticism and Mathematics''", which drew his interest during a visit to the library.Henkin, Leon (1962). «Are Logic and Mathematics Identical?». ''Science'' 138 (3542): 788-794. ISSN 0036-8075. This interest was increased and cultivated by some courses. Although the mathematics department of the University did not offer courses in Logic (these were offered by the Philosophy department), Leon was one of the few mathematics students interested in that discipline and he decided to attend them. In the fall of 1938, in his second year as a Columbia University student, he participated in a first course in Logic taught by
Ernest Nagel Ernest Nagel (November 16, 1901 – September 20, 1985) was an American philosopher of science. Suppes, Patrick (1999)Biographical memoir of Ernest Nagel In '' American National Biograph''y (Vol. 16, pp. 216-218). New York: Oxford University Pr ...
, who had contributed to the creation of the ''Association of Symbolic Logic'' two years earlier. This course brought him closer to Russell's book "''Principles of Mathematics''", where he first encountered the
axiom of choice In mathematics, the axiom of choice, or AC, is an axiom of set theory equivalent to the statement that ''a Cartesian product of a collection of non-empty sets is non-empty''. Informally put, the axiom of choice says that given any collection ...
; Russell's presentation made a strong impression on him and led him to explore the
Principia Mathematica The ''Principia Mathematica'' (often abbreviated ''PM'') is a three-volume work on the foundations of mathematics written by mathematician–philosophers Alfred North Whitehead and Bertrand Russell and published in 1910, 1912, and 1913. ...
that Russell wrote with Whitehead a few years later. He was struck by the general ideas of Type Theory and by the mysterious
axiom of reducibility The axiom of reducibility was introduced by Bertrand Russell in the early 20th century as part of his ramified theory of types. Russell devised and introduced the axiom in an attempt to manage the contradictions he had discovered in his analysis ...
. Both the axiom of choice and Type Theory later played an important role in his doctoral dissertation. The following year, in the fall semester of 1939, Henkin took a second course of Logic with Nagel, in which
formal system A formal system is an abstract structure used for inferring theorems from axioms according to a set of rules. These rules, which are used for carrying out the inference of theorems from axioms, are the logical calculus of the formal system. A form ...
s of
propositional logic Propositional calculus is a branch of logic. It is also called propositional logic, statement logic, sentential calculus, sentential logic, or sometimes zeroth-order logic. It deals with propositions (which can be true or false) and relations b ...
and First-Order Logic were addressed. These constituted his first experience with the mathematical treatment of deductive systems. The course did not go into metalogical results that established a relationship between the semantics and syntactics, and the issue of completeness was not addressed at all. However, Nagel proposed to Henkin as an independent project the reading of the proof of the completeness of propositional logic given by Quine, which had appeared a few months before in the ''
Journal of Symbolic Logic The '' Journal of Symbolic Logic'' is a peer-reviewed mathematics journal published quarterly by Association for Symbolic Logic. It was established in 1936 and covers mathematical logic. The journal is indexed by '' Mathematical Reviews'', Zentra ...
''. This reading was highly significant for Henkin, not so much because of the content itself, but because with it he discovered that he could understand the research on logic and mathematics that was taking place at the time. According to Henkin, although he managed to follow Quine's demonstration, he did not manage to capture the idea of the proof: "''I simply noted that the aim of the paper was to show that every tautology had a formal proof in the system of axioms presented, and I expended my utmost effort to check Quine's reasoning that this was so, without ever reflecting on why author and reader were making this effort. This strictly limited objective also kept me from wondering how the author thought of putting the steps of the proof together; the result was that I failed to get 'the idea of the proof', the essential ingredient needed for discovery.''" Just before Henkin began his second year at Columbia, World War II broke out. This had several repercussions on his life. One of them had a positive effect on his education. Days before the war broke out, the Polish mathematician and logician Alfred Tarski had come to Harvard, at Quine's invitation, to give a series of lectures on logic. With the invasion of Poland by Germany, Tarski found it impossible to return to Poland and he had to remain in the United States. Tarski visited several cities giving lectures on logic. One of these lectures was at Columbia, and Henkin, like the rest of the logic students, attended it with great enthusiasm. In it Tarski spoke of Gödel's work on undecidable propositions in Type Theory and on the existence of decision algorithms for formal systems, a subject that Henkin found extremely stimulating. In his last year at Columbia, in 1941, Professor F. J. Murray, knowing that Henkin was a mathematics student interested in Logic, suggested that they review together the monograph by Gödel recently published at Princeton on the consistency of the axiom of choice with the generalized
continuum hypothesis In mathematics, the continuum hypothesis (abbreviated CH) is a hypothesis about the possible sizes of infinite sets. It states that or equivalently, that In Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC), this is equivalent to ...
. Although the meetings they had to discuss it were scarce and Leon ended up revising this monograph practically alone, the experience was considered by him as the most enriching one in his formation at Columbia. According to Henkin, then began to take form some of the ideas that became the starting-point of his doctoral dissertation. In 1940, Henkin decided to apply for admission to a doctoral program, without having fully defined what path to follow in his research. He was accepted to three universities, from which he chose
Princeton Princeton University is a private research university in Princeton, New Jersey. Founded in 1746 in Elizabeth as the College of New Jersey, Princeton is the fourth-oldest institution of higher education in the United States and one of the ni ...
, since the renowned logician
Alonzo Church Alonzo Church (June 14, 1903 – August 11, 1995) was an American mathematician, computer scientist, logician, philosopher, professor and editor who made major contributions to mathematical logic and the foundations of theoretical computer scien ...
was there, although at the time Henkin was unaware of his work.


Postgraduate Studies

Henkin began his graduate studies at Princeton in 1941, studying under the direction of Church. The Ph.D. program he attended consisted of two years of mathematics courses, after which he was to take a "qualifying" oral examination to show he was well educated in at least three branches of mathematics; with this he would receive a M.A. degree. He would then have another two years to write a doctoral dissertation containing an original research, after which he would get the degree of Ph.D. The first two years he took courses in logic -taught by Church-, analysis and general topology. In the first logic course with Church were studied several formal systems of Propositional Logic and First-Order Logic; some proofs of completeness and discussed part of the Löwenheim-Skolem theorems were revised, as well as a presentation of Gödel's proof on the completeness of First-Order Logic. In the second one they dealt in great detail with a Second-Order system for Peano Arithmetic, as well as with the incompleteness of this axiomatic theory and the consequent incompleteness of Second-Order Logic. In 1941 the United States entered the Second World War, altering Henkin's plans. He had to rush his oral qualification exam, with which he obtained the degree of M. A. and left Princeton to take part in the
Manhattan Project The Manhattan Project was a research and development undertaking during World War II that produced the first nuclear weapons. It was led by the United States with the support of the United Kingdom and Canada. From 1942 to 1946, the project w ...
. This interruption would last four years, during which he contributed his mathematical knowledge working on radar problems and in the design of a plant to separate uranium isotopes. Most of his work required numerical analysis to solve partial differential equations. During this period, all of his work and readings on logic were completely suspended. Once the war was over, Henkin returned to Princeton in 1946, where he was still required to write a dissertation to complete his Ph.D. studies. Upon his return he joined the logic course that Church had begun a month earlier on
Frege Friedrich Ludwig Gottlob Frege (; ; 8 November 1848 – 26 July 1925) was a German philosopher, logician, and mathematician. He was a mathematics professor at the University of Jena, and is understood by many to be the father of analytic ph ...
's theory of "
sense and reference In the philosophy of language, the distinction between sense and reference was an idea of the German philosopher and mathematician Gottlob Frege in 1892 (in his paper "On Sense and Reference"; German: "Über Sinn und Bedeutung"), reflecting the ...
". In this course he discovered Church's theory of types, which he found extremely interesting. The questions he asked about it eventually led him to give his proof of the completeness of the theory of types, which he was able to adapt to also give a new proof of the completeness of First-Order Logic. These results, as well as others that other that emerged from the same ideas, came to take part in Henkin's doctoral dissertation, which was titled "''The completeness of formal systems''", with which he graduated in June 1947. The dissertation itself was not published, although parts of it were rewritten and published in articles, and. Many years later, Henkin wrote the article "''The discovery of my completeness proofs''", which contains a detailed review of the contents of his dissertation. The procedures used in it have become frequent methods of proofs in various branches of logic.


After the graduation

Having obtained his Ph.D. degree, Henkin spent two more years at Princeton working on post-doctoral studies. During this time, in 1948, he met Ginette Potvin, during a trip to Montreal with his sister Estelle and Princeton mathematics graduate student Harold Kuhn. Ginette would become his wife in 1950, a half year after Estelle married Harold. After completing his second year of postdoctoral studies at Princeton in 1949, Leon returned to California, where he entered the mathematics department at the
University of Southern California The University of Southern California (USC, SC, or Southern Cal) is a Private university, private research university in Los Angeles, California, United States. Founded in 1880 by Robert M. Widney, it is the oldest private research university in C ...
. There he held the position of assistant professor until 1953. In 1952 Tarski had managed to obtain a permanent position at
Berkeley Berkeley most often refers to: *Berkeley, California, a city in the United States **University of California, Berkeley, a public university in Berkeley, California * George Berkeley (1685–1753), Anglo-Irish philosopher Berkeley may also refer ...
for Henkin. However, Henkin did not want to accept it, as he was sympathetic to the protests recently raised by the controversial oath of allegiance that had been required of university professors since 1950.  Once the oath requirement disappeared, Henkin accepted Tarski's offer and settled in Berkeley in 1953. 


His life in Berkeley

From 1953, most of Henkin's academic activity revolved around Berkeley, where he collaborated with a solid research group in Logic. He remained there for almost all his academic life, except for some periods in which he traveled abroad with scholarships and grants of diverse institutes, like the one-year stay he had in Amsterdam or the one in Israel with the Fulbright Research Grants he was awarded (in 1954 and 1979 respectively).Manzano et al (Eds.) (2014). ''The Life and Work of Leon Henkin, Essays on His Contributions,'' Springer International Publishing. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-09719-0. Henkin was always grateful to Tarski, as it was thanks to him that he was able to settle in Berkeley. After Tarski's death in 1983, he wrote in a personal letter: “I write to tell you that Alfred Tarski, who came to Berkeley in 1942 and founded our great Center for the Study of Logic and Foundations, died Wednesday night, at age 82 .. It was he who brought me to Berkeley in 1953, so I owe much to him personally as well as scientifically.” Tarski not only offered Henkin a job opportunity, but also provided him with a very fertile interdisciplinary collaborative environment for the development of Logic. Tarski had founded the ''Center for the Study of Logic and Foundations'' in Berkeley, but with Henkin's help he was able to bring together a group of logicians, mathematicians and philosophers who formed the ''Group in Logic and the Methodology of Science'', which is still active today.See Mancosu, Paolo (2018-01). «The Origin of the Group in Logic and the Methodology of Science». ''Journal of Humanistic Mathematics'' 8 (1): 371-413. doi:10.5642/jhummath.201801.19. As part of this project they created an interdisciplinary postgraduate program culminating in a Ph.D. Tarski and Henkin boosted the project by organizing important congresses and conferences on Logic, following Tarski's conception of "logic as a common basis for the whole of human knowledge". The intense activity that took place in Berkeley in the 1950s and 1960s on metalogic was largely due to the activity of Tarski and Henkin, both in teaching and research. Many results of what are today crucial to Model Theory came as a result of the academic activity in Berkeley that took place in those years. Among the research trips that Henkin did throughout the years are his visits to universities in Hanover, Princeton, Colorado, as well as to several European Universities, such as Oxford (in the United Kingdom), and others in Yugoslavia, Spain, Portugal and France. In 1979, with his second Fulbright Grant, Henkin spent a year in Israel, in Haifa, at the Department of Science Education of the Technion University. On this occasion he also visited two universities in Egypt. In 1982 he first visited Spain. He gave conferences at several universities, including those in Barcelona, Madrid and Seville. Henkin had an active role in research and teaching, but his activities at the university went far beyond that. In addition to the dedication he put in his teaching as well as and in guiding the ''Group in Logic and the Methodology of Science'', he held some administrative positions; he was director of the Department of Mathematics from 1966 to 1968, and subsequently from 1983 to 1985. One of the activities to which he devoted most energy was the teaching of mathematics, on which he also did some research.   On some occasions Henkin attended to his children's schools to talk to elementary school children about maths, talking to them about "''the negative numbers''", or "''how to subtract by addition''". Around that time (about 1960), Henkin began to alternate his research work in mathematics with research work in teaching mathematics; the latter became increasingly frequent. In 1991 he was granted the title of Professor Emeritus at the University of Berkeley and retired.


Retirement and death

After he retired, Henkin continued to work on math teaching projects. From 1991, he took part on a summer courses program at Mills College intended to give talented women from across the nation education in mathematics in order to prepare them for college. Finally, Ginette and Henkin moved to Oakland, where Henkin died a few years later, in November 2006. Always kind to his students and colleagues, whom he frequently invited to his home to enjoy evenings with Ginette, he is remembered as a brilliant researcher, a teacher committed to his discipline and a person who showed solidarity with his community. One of the phrases that best captures the sentiment expressed in various testimonies of his students is that given by Douglas Hofstadter: "I feel very fortunate to have been his graduate student since I learned from him much more than logic. It is his humanity that conquered my heart. I always wish I am not less kind to my graduate students and no less eager to follow their professional growth after graduation than he was to me".


Legacy


Algebra

Henkin's work on algebra focused on
cylindric algebra In mathematics, the notion of cylindric algebra, invented by Alfred Tarski, arises naturally in the algebraization of first-order logic with equality. This is comparable to the role Boolean algebras play for propositional logic. Cylindric algebra ...
s, a subject he investigated together with Alfred Tarski and Donald Monk. Cylindric Algebra provides structures that are to first-order logic what
Boolean algebra In mathematics and mathematical logic, Boolean algebra is a branch of algebra. It differs from elementary algebra in two ways. First, the values of the variables are the truth values ''true'' and ''false'', usually denoted 1 and 0, whereas i ...
is to propositional logic. One of the purposes of Henkin and Tarski in promoting algebraic logic was to attract the interest of mathematicians to logic, convinced as they were that logic could provide unifying principles to mathematics:  "In fact we would go so far as to venture a prediction that through logical research there may emerge important unifying principles which will help to give coherence to a mathematics which sometimes seems in danger of becoming infinitely divisible". According to Monk, Henkin's research on cylindrical algebra can be divided into the following parts: Algebraic Theory, Algebraic Set Theory, Representation Theorems, Non-representable Algebraic Constructions and Applications to Logic.


Completeness Theorems

In 1949 "''The completeness of the first order functional calculus''" was published, as well as "''Completeness in the theory of types''" in 1950. Both presented part of the results exposed in the dissertation "''The completeness of formal systems''" with which Henkin received his Ph.D. degree at Princeton in 1947. One of Henkin's best known results is that of the completeness of First-Order Logic, published in the above-mentioned 1949 article, which appears as the first theorem of the 1947 dissertation. It states the following:
Any set S of sentences of L formally consistent in the deductive system of L is satisfiable by a numerable structure M.
This theorem is nowadays called the 'completeness theorem', since from it the following easily follows:
If S is a set of sentences of L and \phi is semantic consequence of S (S \models \phi), then \phi is deducible from S (S \vdash \phi).
This is the strong version of the completeness theorem, from which the weak version is obtained as a corollary. The latter states the result for the particular case in which S is the empty set, this is to say, the deductive calculus of first order logic is capable of deriving all valid formulas. The weak version, known as
Gödel's completeness theorem Gödel's completeness theorem is a fundamental theorem in mathematical logic that establishes a correspondence between semantic truth and syntactic provability in first-order logic. The completeness theorem applies to any first-order theory: ...
, had been proved by Gödel in 1929, in his own doctoral thesis. Henkin's proof is more general, more accessible than Gödel's and more easily generalizable to languages of any cardinality. It approaches completeness from a new and fruitful perspective and its greatest quality is perhaps that its proof can be easily adapted to prove the completeness of other deductive systems. Other results central to model theory are obtained as corollaries of the strong completeness of the first order logic proved by Henkin. From it follows, for example, the following result for a first order language  L:
Every set of well-formed formulas of L that is satisfiable in a L−structure is satisfiable in an infinite numerable structure.
This result is known as the "downwards" Löwenheim-Skolem theorem. One other result obtained from the completeness theorem is:
A set S of well-formed formulas of L has a model if and only if each finite subset of it has a model.
The latter is known as the "
compactness theorem In mathematical logic, the compactness theorem states that a set of first-order sentences has a model if and only if every finite subset of it has a model. This theorem is an important tool in model theory, as it provides a useful (but generally ...
" of first-order logic, which can also be phrased as: "Any set of well formed formulas of L that is finitely satisfiable is satisfiable". This is to say, if for each of the finite subsets of \Delta there is a structure in which all of its formulas are true, then there is also a structure in which all the formulas of \Delta are true. It is known as "compactness theorem" because it corresponds to the compactness of a certain topological space, defined from semantic notions. Among the other theorems of completeness given by Henkin, the most relevant is perhaps that of the completeness of Church's Theory of Types, which is the first of the completeness theorems Henkin proved. Then, he adapted the method developed in that proof to prove the completeness of other deductive systems. This method has continued to be used to give proofs of completeness in both classical and non-classical logics, and it has become the usual proof of completeness for First-Order Logic in Logic textbooks. When Henkin published this result in 1949, completeness was not even part of the canonical subjects covered by the textbooks; some twenty years later, this theorem, along with its proof and corollaries, was part of virtually every Logic textbook. As for non-classical logics, Henkin's method can be used, among other things, to extend the completeness of Fuzzy Logic from first order to higher order, producing a complete Fuzzy Type Theory; it also offers a way to obtain results that link classical logic with
intuitionist logic Intuitionistic logic, sometimes more generally called constructive logic, refers to systems of symbolic logic that differ from the systems used for classical logic by more closely mirroring the notion of constructive proof. In particular, systems o ...
; and it allows one to test results of completeness in other non-classical logics, as in the cases of Hybrid Type Theory and Equational Hybrid Propositional Type Theory.


The Discovery of the Completeness Theorems

Despite being one of his best known results, Henkin got to the proof of the completeness of first-order logic "accidentally", trying to prove a completely different result. The order of publication of his articles and even the order of presentation of the theorems in his 1947 dissertation does not reflect the evolution that followed the ideas that led him to his completeness results. However, Henkin simplifies the difficult task of tracing the development and shaping of his ideas by his article "''The discovery of my completeness proofs''", published in 1996. In it, he describes the process of the development of his dissertation. He doesn't only explain the content of his work, but he also explains the ideas that led to it, from his first logic courses in College until the end of the writing of his thesis. At the end of the war, Henkin returned to Princeton to complete his doctoral studies, for which he still had to write a dissertation containing an original research. As soon as he arrived at Princeton, he attended Church's course in logic that had begun one month earlier, which dealt with Frege's theory of "sense and reference". Motivated by Frege's ideas, Church wanted to put them into practice through a formal axiomatic theory. To do so, he took the simple Theory of Types he had published a few years earlier, and supplied it with a hierarchy of types, inspired by the idea of "sense" exposed by Frege. It was in this course that Henkin became acquainted with Church's Theory of Types, which he found of great interest. He immediately made a conjecture about it, whose proof he hoped could become his doctoral dissertation. One of the attributes that drew Henkin's attention to Church's Theory of Types was that the \lambda-operator allowed to name many objects in the type hierarchy. As he explains in "''The discovery of my completeness proofs''", he set out to find out which elements had names in this theory. He began by exploring the elements that were named in the two domains at the base of the type hierarchy. He took \N as the universe of individuals, and added a constant for each the number 0 and the successor function s, so that each element in the domain was named from 0 and repeated occurrences of s. Going up through the hierarchy, he tried to specify which functions over those elements were nameable. The set of them was supernumerable, so there had to be some without a name, since there is only a numerable number of expressions. How could be said which elements were the nameable ones? To make each expression correspond to the element it denotated, he needed a
choice function A choice function (selector, selection) is a mathematical function ''f'' that is defined on some collection ''X'' of nonempty sets and assigns some element of each set ''S'' in that collection to ''S'' by ''f''(''S''); ''f''(''S'') maps ''S'' to ...
, in whose search Henkin invested many efforts. Finally, he realized that by means of the deductive calculus he could form equivalence classes of expressions whose equality could be derived by the calculus, and form with these classes a model isomorphic to the new hierarchy of types formed by the named elements. He had been focusing on the interpretations of the formal language, when the key to solving the problem lied on the deductive system. It remained to make the universe of the objects named by the propositions a set of two elements: the truth values. This could be achieved by expanding the axioms to form a maximally consistent set. Once this was achieved, it could be proved that every consistent set of formulas T has a model that satisfies exactly the formulas of T –the elements of such model are the equivalence classes of the expressions themselves–. That is, he would have managed to give a proof of the completeness of the deductive calculus. The same method used to prove the completeness of Church's Theory of Types could easily be adapted to give a proof of (strong) completeness of First-Order Logic, and of others that followed later on. The ideas on the ''nameable'' elements in the hierarchy of types underlying the discovery of Henkin's completeness proofs led to the successful introduction of new semantics, called ''general semantics'', which are based on general models (or Henkin models).


Henkin's method

Henkin's method to give the completeness proofs consists on building a certain model: it starts with a set of formulas \Delta, of which the consistency is assumed. A model is then constructed, which satisfies exactly the formulas of \Delta. Henkin's idea to build a suitable model relies on obtaining a sufficiently detailed description of such model using the sentences of the formal language, and to establish which objects could be the elements of such model. If it were known, for each formula of the language of \Delta, if it should be satisfied or not by the model, we would have a comprehensive description of the model that would allow its construction. This is exactly what is being looked for: a set of sentences \Gamma containing \Delta for which it holds that every sentence of the language or its negation belongs to Gamma. In the case of first order logic one more thing is required: that the set \Gamma be exemplified, this is, for all existential formula there is a constant that acts as a witness of it. On the other hand, since the nature of the objects that make up the model's universe is irrelevant, no objection arises against taking as individuals the terms of the language themselves –or classes of equivalence of them–. The first step that must be taken is to extend the language of \Delta adding an infinite collection of new individual constants, and then to order the formulas of the language (which are infinite). Once this is done, the aim is to inductively construct an infinite chain of consistent and exemplified sets: we start from \Delta, systematically adding to this set every formula that doesn't make the resulting set inconsistent, adding also exemplifications of the existential formulas. Thus, an infinite chain of consistent and exemplified sets is built, whose union is a maximally consistent and exemplified set; this will be the required set \Gamma. Having achieved to construct this maximally consistent and exemplified set, the model described by it can be constructed. Which individuals constitute the model's universe? In the case of First-Order Logic without equality, the elements of the domain will be the terms of the formal language. To construct the functions and relations of the model we follow thoroughly what \Gamma dictates: if the language contains a n-relator R, its interpretation in the model will be a relationship formed by all the n-tuples of terms in the model's universe such that the formula that says they are related belongs to \Gamma. If the language includes equality, the domain of the model are classes of equivalence of the terms of the language instead. The equivalence relation is established by the formulas of the maximally consistent set: two terms are equal if there is in \Gamma a formula stating they are. Summarizing, the demonstration in the case of a numerable language has two parts: # Extending the set \Delta to a maximally consistent and exemplified set. # Constructing the model described by the formulae of this set using the terms of the language –or its equivalence classes– as objects of the model's universe.


General models

The simple Theory of Types, with the \lambda-calculus and the standard semantics is sufficiently rich to express arithmetic categorically, from where it follows, by Gödel's incompleteness theorem, that it is incomplete. Following the idea of identifying the namable elements in the hierarchy of types, Henkin proposed a change in the interpretation of the language, accepting as types hierarchies some that  previously were not admitted. If it was asked from each level of the hierarchy not that there must be all the corresponding functions, but only those that are definable, then a new semantics is obtained, and with it a new logic. The resulting semantics is known as general semantics. In it the structures that are admissible as models are those known as 'general models'. These can be used not only in Type Theory, but also, for instance, to obtain complete (and compact) Higher-Order Logics. Obtaining complete Higher-Order Logics by the use of general semantics meets the expected balance between the expressive power of a logic and the power of its deductive calculus. In Second-Order Logic with standard semantics it is known that quantifying over predicative variables gives the language an immense expressive power, in exchange for which the power of deductive calculus is lost: the latter is not enough to produce the extense set of valid formulas of this logic (with standard semantics). Changing the calculus does not solve anything, since Gödel's incompleteness theorem ensures that no deductive calculus could achieve completeness. On the contrary, by changing the semantics, that is, by changing the sets that form the universes in which the predicative variables and constants are interpreted, the logic turns out to be complete, at the cost of losing expressive capacity. In Second-Order Logic the set of valid formulas is so large because the concept of standard structure is too restrictive and there are not enough of them to find models that refute the formulas. By relaxing the conditions we ask of the structures on which the language is interpreted, there are more models in which the formulas must be true to be valid and therefore the set of valid formulas is reduced; it does so in such a way that it coincides with the set produced by a deductive calculus, giving rise to completeness.Manzano, María (1993). ''Extensions of First-Order Logic''. Cambridge University Press.


Towards a translation between logics

One of the areas in which the foundations laid by Henkin's work have proved fruitful is in the search for a logic that works as a common framework for translation between logics. This framework is intended to be used as a metalogical tool; its purpose is not to choose "one logic" above the others, which would suppress the richness provided by the diversity of them, but to provide the adequate context to contrast them, understand them and thus make the best use of the qualities of each one. A research that takes Henkin's ideas in this direction is that of María Manzano, one of his students, whose proposal is to use
Many-Sorted Logic Many-sorted logic can reflect formally our intention not to handle the universe as a homogeneous collection of objects, but to partition it in a way that is similar to types in typeful programming. Both functional and assertive " parts of speech ...
as a common framework for the translation of logics. The aims of this proposal can be synthesized into two: 1) to use a single deductive calculus for all of them; and 2) to use the metaproperties of Many-Sorted Logic in order to more easily proof metaproperties of other logics. In addition, having a logical framework is useful for comparing different logics by comparing the theories that represent them. Although Henkin does not speak of formulae translation, nor does he make explicit a Many-Sorted Language or calculus, the ideas he uses in two of his articles serve as a basis for the approach to translation: "''Completeness in the theory of types''" and "''Banishing the Rule of Substitution for Functional Variables''".


Mathematical Induction

The topic of
mathematical induction Mathematical induction is a method for proving that a statement ''P''(''n'') is true for every natural number ''n'', that is, that the infinitely many cases ''P''(0), ''P''(1), ''P''(2), ''P''(3), ...  all hold. Informal metaphors help ...
was frequently addressed in Henkin's activities on teaching. Probably his experience in this field was the result of his article "''On mathematical induction''". This was Henkin's favorite article of his own, of which he even wrote that he considered it his best expository article. In it he defined Peano Models as those that fulfill Peano's three Second-Order Axioms and Induction Models as those that satisfy the third of them: the
induction axiom Induction, Inducible or Inductive may refer to: Biology and medicine * Labor induction (birth/pregnancy) * Induction chemotherapy, in medicine * Induced stem cells, stem cells derived from somatic, reproductive, pluripotent or other cell ty ...
. He demonstrated that although all recursive operations can be introduced in the Peano models, this is not the case in the Induction Models. Concretely, there are Induction Models in which the exponentiation operation cannot be defined. In this article, Henkin also presents the mathematical structure that Induction models can have, which is quite simple: they can either be the standard model, that is, isomorphic to natural numbers, or in two more ways; isomorphic to cycles –which correspond to the \Z integers module n; or isomorphsicn to what Henkin called "spoons," which is a combination of a finite list followed by a cycle.


Philosophical position

Of the articles published by Henkin, the most philosophical is "''Some Notes on Nominalism''", which he wrote in response to two articles on nominalism, one by Quine and the other jointly written by Quine and Goodman. The discussions relevant to this philosophical doctrine arise naturally in the proofs of completeness given by Henkin, as well as in his proposal for a change in semantics through general models. Both from the content of his works and from his own statements it is considered that his position was nominalist.


Teaching

Henkin's activity as a university professor was vigorous. He taught at all levels, putting the same care and dedication into each of them. Some of the courses he taught were directly related to his research area, such as "''Mathematical Logic''", "''Metamathematics''" or "''Cylindric Algebra''", but others extended to a great diversity of areas, including, among others, "''Fundaments of Geometry''", "''Algebra and Trigonometry''", "''Finite Mathematics''", "''Calculus with Analytic Geometry''" or "''Mathematical Concepts for Elementary School Teachers''". His students agree that his explanations were extremely clear and caught the listener's attention.Resek, Diane (2014). «Lessons from Leon». In Manzano et at. (Eds.) ''The Life and Work of Leon Henkin, Essays on His Contributions''. Springer International Publishing. . doi:10.1007/978-3-319-09719-0_11. In the words of one of his students, "''part of his magic was his elegant expression of the mathematics, but he also worked hard to engage his audience in conjecturing and seeing the next step or in being surprised by it. He certainly captured the interest of his audiences''." One of the aspects of his lectures in which he put special care was in finding an appropriate pace, facing the constant dilemma of how to find the optimal speed for learning. He considered it important that the students could follow the rhythm of the class, even if this meant that some would found it slow –they could continue at their own pace with the readings. However, he also considered that what was easily learned was easily forgotten, so he sought a balance between making his classes accessible and challenging for students, so that they would make the effort to learn more deeply. About his own experience as a student, he commented in an interview: "''That easy way in which ideas came made it too easy to forget them. I probably learned more densely condensed material in what we called the 'seminar for babies in conjunctive topology', conducted by Arthure Stone. I learned more because it forced us to do all the work.''" In addition to his courses and supervision of graduate students, Henkin's role in the scholars education was significant. Tarski had invited him to Berkeley with a clear purpose. As a mathematician, Henkin had a key role in Tarski's project to make Berkeley a center of development of logic, bringing together mathematicians, logicians and philosophers. Henkin aided him to carry out the project, helping him in the creation of the interdisciplinary ''Group in Logic and the Methodology of Science'', whose successful performance was largely due to Henkin's drive. Part of this project was the creation of an interdisciplinary university program that culminated in a Ph.D. in "''Logic, Methodology and Philosophy of Science''". He also collaborated in organising important meetings and conferences that promoted interdisciplinary collaboration united by logic. The outcome was that in the 1950s and 1960s there was a vibrant development of logic in Berkeley, from which many advances in Model Theory emerged. Although Henkin's first encounter with teaching mathematics was as a professor, later in life he began to do research in mathematics' teaching as well. Some of his writings in this field are: "''Retracing Elementary Mathematics''", "''New directions in secondary school mathematics''" or "''The roles of action and of thought in mathematics education''". From 1979 onwards he put special emphasis on this facet of his research and the last doctoral theses he directed are related to the teaching of mathematics or the integration of minority groups in research. Henkin liked to write expository articles, for some of which he received awards such as the Chauvenet Prize (1964), for the article "''Are Logic and Mathematics Identical?'' " or the Lester R. Ford Award, for the article "''Mathematical Foundations of Mathematics''".


Social Projects

Throughout his life, Leon Henkin showed a deep commitment to society and was often called a social activist. Many of his mathematics teaching projects sought to bring minority or socially disadvantaged groups closer to mathematics and related areas. He was aware that we are part of history and the context around us, as one of his writings records:
"''Waves of history wash over our nation, stirring up our society and our institutions. Soon we see changes in the way that all of us do things, including our mathematics and our teaching. These changes form themselves into rivulets and streams that merge at various angles with those arising in parts of our society quite different from education, mathematics, or science. Rivers are formed, contributing powerful currents that will produce future waves of history.'' ''The Great Depression and World War II formed the background of my years of study; the Cold War and the Civil Rights Movement were the backdrop against which I began my career as a research mathematician, and later began to involve myself with mathematics education''."
Henkin was convinced that changes could be achieved through education and, true to his idea, he committed himself to both elementary mathematics education programs and to programs whose aim was to combat exclusion. He showed a political commitment to society, defending progressive ideas. He inspired many of his students to become involved in mathematics education. Diane Resek, one of his students with an affinity for teaching, described him as follows:
"''Leon was committed to work toward equity in society. He was able to see that profes- sional mathematicians could make a difference, particularly regarding racial inequities in the United States. He was one of the first people to say that one thing holding back racial minorities and poorer people in America was their low participation rates in math/science careers. He believed that there were ways of teaching and new programs that could correct this problem.''"
Aware of the contributions that mathematicians could make through teaching, Henkin defended that teaching should be valued in the academy environment, as he expressed in a personal letter: "''In these times when our traditionally trained mathematics Ph.D.’s are finding rough going in the marketplace, it seems to me that we on the faculty should particularly seek new realms wherein mathematics training can make a substantial contribution to the basic aims of society.''" Some of the social projects he formed or participated in are the following. Between 1957 and 1959 he was part of the Summer Institutes, aimed at mathematics teachers and dedicated to improving high school and college education. In 1958 the National Science Foundation authorized the committee of the American Mathematical Society –which had been interested for some years in the use of films and visual material for mathematics education– to produce experimental films for this purpose, accompanied by printed manuals with appendices that would go deeper into the content and problems to be solved. Henkin participated in this project with a film on mathematical induction, whose supplementary manual was printed by the American Mathematical Society. The film was broadcast in the series "''Mathematics Today''". Between 1961 and 1964, he participated in a series of courses for elementary school teachers, organized by the Committee on the Undergraduate Program in Mathematics. Also around that time, he promoted the Activities to Broaden Opportunity initiative, which sought to provide opportunities for promising students from ethnic minority groups by offering them summer courses and scholarships. He took part in the SEED (Special Elementary Education for the Disadvantaged) program, which encouraged college students to participate in elementary education, as well as in SESAME (Special Excellence in Science and Mathematics Education), the interdisciplinary doctoral program created by members of various science departments, whose purpose was to research teaching and learning of science, engineering, and mathematics. Between 1960 and 1968 he participated in a series of conferences in mathematics schools, and was involved in the development of several films produced by the National Council of Teachers of Mathematics (NCTM). These films dealt with topics such as the integer system and the rational number system. He also participated in support courses for female calculus students and convinced the mathematics department to allow graduate students to receive the same financial support for working as elementary school teachers as they did for working as assistant teachers in college. "''He not only believed in equality, but also worked actively to see that it was brought about''."


Henkin's Main Articles

* Henkin, L. (1949). The completeness of the first-order functional calculus. ''The Journal of Symbolic Logic'', 14(3), 159-166. * Henkin, L. (1950). Completeness in the theory of types. ''The Journal of Symbolic Logic'', 15(2), 81-91. * Henkin, L. (1953). Banishing the Rule of Substitution for Functional Variables. ''The Journal of Symbolic Logic'', 18(3), 201-208. * Henkin, L. (1953). Some interconnections between modern algebra and mathematical logic. ''Transactions of the American Mathematical Society'', 74, 410-427. * Henkin, L. (1953). Some notes on nominalism, ''The Journal of Symbolic Logic'', 18(1), 19-29. * Henkin, L. (1954) A generalization of the concept of $\omega$-consistency. ''The Journal of Symbolic Logic''. 19(3), 183-196. * Henkin, L. (1955) The nominalistic interpretation of mathematical language. ''Bulletin of the Belgian Mathematical Society''. 7, 137-141. * Henkin, L. (1955) The representation theorem for cylindrical algebras. En Skolem, Th., Hasenjaeger, G., Kreisel, G., Robinson, A. (Eds.) ''Mathematical Interpretation of Formal Systems'', pp. 85–97. * Henkin, L. (1957) A generalization of the concept of -completeness. ''The Journal of Symbolic Logic''. 22(1), 1-14. * Henkin, L. (1960). On mathematical induction. ''The American Mathematical Monthly''. 67(4), 323-338. * Henkin, L. (1961). Mathematical Induction. En ''MAA Film Manual No.1'' The Mathematical Association of America, University of Buffalo, Nueva York. * Henkin, L., Tarski, A. (1961) Cylindric algebras. En Dilworth, R.P. (Ed.) ''Lattice Theory. Proceedings of Symposia in Pure Mathematics. American Mathematical Society'', 2, 83-113. * Henkin, L. Smith, W. N., Varineau, V. J., Walsh, M. J. (1962) ''Retracing Elementary Mathematics''. Macmillan, New York. * Henkin, L. (1962). Are logic and mathematics identical?, ''Science,'' vol.138, 788-794. * Henkin, L. (1963). New directions in secondary school mathematics. En Ritchie, R. W. (Ed.) ''New Directions in Mathematics'', 1-6. Prentice Hall, New York. * Henkin, L. (1963). An Extension of the Craig-Lyndon Interpolation theorem. ''The Journal of Symbolic Logic''. 28(3), 201-216. * Henkin, L. (1963). A theory of propositional types. ''Fundamenta mathematicae''. 52, 323-344. * Henkin, L. (1971). Mathematical foundations for mathematics. ''The American Mathematical Monthly''. 78(5), 463-487. * Henkin, L. (1975). Identity as a logical primitive. ''Philosophia'' 5, 31-45. * Henkin, L. (1977). The logic of equality.''The American Mathematical Monthly''. 84(8), 597-612. * Henkin, L. (1995). The roles of action and of thought in mathematics education –one mathematician's passage. Fisher, N.D., Keynes, H.B., Wagreich, Ph.D. (Eds.), ''Changing the Culture: Mathematics Education in the Research Community'', CBMS Issues in Mathematics Education, vol. 5, pp. 3–16. American Mathematical Society in cooperation with Mathematical Association of America, Providence. * Henkin, L. (1996). The discovery of my completeness proofs, ''Bulletin of Symbolic Logic'', vol. 2(2), 127-158.


Awards received

*1964 — The
Chauvenet Prize The Chauvenet Prize is the highest award for mathematical expository writing. It consists of a prize of $1,000 and a certificate, and is awarded yearly by the Mathematical Association of America in recognition of an outstanding expository article ...
, Mathematical Association of America award to the author of an outstanding expository article on a mathematical topic by a member of the Association.''Award of the 1964 Chauvenet Prize to Professor Leon A. Henkin''.
The American Mathematical Monthly, vol. 71 (1964), no. 1, p. 3
*1972 —
Lester R. Ford Award Lester is an ancient Anglo-Saxon surname and given name. Notable people and characters with the name include: People Given name * Lester Bangs (1948–1982), American music critic * Lester W. Bentley (1908–1972), American artist from Wisc ...
— fo
Mathematical foundations for mathematics
American Mathematical Monthly 78 (1971), 463–487. *1990 — First recipient of the Gung and Hu Award for Distinguished Service to Mathematics. *1991 — Berkeley Citation — the highest honor/award bestowed by the University of California. *2000 — Leon Henkin Citation — for Distinguished Service, which is presented to a (UC) faculty member for "exceptional commitment to the educational development of students from groups who are underrepresented in the academy."


See also

*
Branching quantifier In logic a branching quantifier, also called a Henkin quantifier, finite partially ordered quantifier or even nonlinear quantifier, is a partial ordering :\langle Qx_1\dots Qx_n\rangle of quantifiers for ''Q'' ∈ . It is a special case ...


References


Further reading

* * *Henkin, Leon (1949). "The Completeness of the First-Order Functional Calculus", ''
Journal of Symbolic Logic The '' Journal of Symbolic Logic'' is a peer-reviewed mathematics journal published quarterly by Association for Symbolic Logic. It was established in 1936 and covers mathematical logic. The journal is indexed by '' Mathematical Reviews'', Zentra ...
''. 14: 159–166. *Henkin, Leon (1949). "Fragments of the propositional calculus", ''The Journal of Symbolic Logic'' 14: 42–48. *Henkin, Leon (1950)
"Completeness in the theory of types"
''Journal of Symbolic Logic'' 15: 81–91. *Henkin, Leon (1996). «The Discovery of My Completeness Proofs». ''Bulletin of Symbolic Logic'' 2 (2): 127-158. ISSN 1079-8986. doi:10.2307/421107. * Manzano, María, Sain, Ildikó, Alonso, Enrique (Eds.). (2014)
"The Life and Work of Leon Henkin"
Birkhauser.


External links

*
Berkeley Citation Award


* ttps://web.archive.org/web/20150310073356/http://www.princeton.edu/~mudd/finding_aids/mathoral/pmc19.htm An interview with Henkin about his experience at Princeton
Leon Henkin, advocate for diversity in math & science, has died
by Robert Sanders, UC Berkeley News press release, November 9, 2006.

by Valerie J. Nelson, ''Los Angeles Times,'' November 16, 2006, p. B-6. * ttp://www.sfgate.com/cgi-bin/article.cgi?f=/c/a/2006/11/20/BAGI9MGAJI1.DTL Leon A. Henkin—Cal math educatorby Rick DelVecchio, ''San Francisco Chronicle,'' November 20, 2006, p. B-3.

by John Addison, William Craig, Carolyn Kane, and Alan Schoenfeld (University of California Academic Senate memorial).
In Memoriam: Leon Albert Henkin, 1921–2006
by J. Donald Monk, ''The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic,'' vol. 15, no. 3 (Sept. 2009), pp. 326–331. {{DEFAULTSORT:Henkin, Leon 1921 births 2006 deaths 20th-century American mathematicians 21st-century American mathematicians Columbia College (New York) alumni Princeton University alumni University of California, Berkeley College of Letters and Science faculty Henkin, Henkin, Leon American people of Russian-Jewish descent Manhattan Project people People from Brooklyn Mathematicians from New York (state)