HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

Logical consequence (also entailment) is a fundamental
concept Concepts are defined as abstract ideas. They are understood to be the fundamental building blocks of the concept behind principles, thoughts and beliefs. They play an important role in all aspects of cognition. As such, concepts are studied by s ...
in logic, which describes the relationship between statements that hold true when one statement logically ''follows from'' one or more statements. A
valid Validity or Valid may refer to: Science/mathematics/statistics: * Validity (logic), a property of a logical argument * Scientific: ** Internal validity, the validity of causal inferences within scientific studies, usually based on experiments ** ...
logical argument is one in which the conclusion is entailed by the premises, because the conclusion is the consequence of the premises. The philosophical analysis of logical consequence involves the questions: In what sense does a conclusion follow from its premises? and What does it mean for a conclusion to be a consequence of premises?Beall, JC and Restall, Greg,
Logical Consequence
' The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2009 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.).
All of
philosophical logic Understood in a narrow sense, philosophical logic is the area of logic that studies the application of logical methods to philosophical problems, often in the form of extended logical systems like modal logic. Some theorists conceive philosophical ...
is meant to provide accounts of the nature of logical consequence and the nature of logical truth. Logical consequence is necessary and
formal Formal, formality, informal or informality imply the complying with, or not complying with, some set of requirements (forms, in Ancient Greek). They may refer to: Dress code and events * Formal wear, attire for formal events * Semi-formal attire ...
, by way of examples that explain with formal proof and models of interpretation. A sentence is said to be a logical consequence of a set of sentences, for a given
language Language is a structured system of communication. The structure of a language is its grammar and the free components are its vocabulary. Languages are the primary means by which humans communicate, and may be conveyed through a variety of ...
, if and only if, using only logic (i.e., without regard to any ''personal'' interpretations of the sentences) the sentence must be true if every sentence in the set is true. McKeon, Matthew,
Logical Consequence
' Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
Logicians make precise accounts of logical consequence regarding a given
language Language is a structured system of communication. The structure of a language is its grammar and the free components are its vocabulary. Languages are the primary means by which humans communicate, and may be conveyed through a variety of ...
\mathcal, either by constructing a deductive system for \mathcal or by formal intended semantics for language \mathcal. The Polish logician Alfred Tarski identified three features of an adequate characterization of entailment: (1) The logical consequence relation relies on the logical form of the sentences: (2) The relation is a priori, i.e., it can be determined with or without regard to empirical evidence (sense experience); and (3) The logical consequence relation has a modal component.


Formal accounts

The most widely prevailing view on how best to account for logical consequence is to appeal to formality. This is to say that whether statements follow from one another logically depends on the structure or logical form of the statements without regard to the contents of that form. Syntactic accounts of logical consequence rely on schemes using inference rules. For instance, we can express the logical form of a valid argument as: : All ''X'' are ''Y'' : All ''Y'' are ''Z'' : Therefore, all ''X'' are ''Z''. This argument is formally valid, because every
instance Instantiation or instance may refer to: Philosophy * A modern concept similar to ''participation'' in classical Platonism; see the Theory of Forms * The instantiation principle, the idea that in order for a property to exist, it must be had by ...
of arguments constructed using this scheme is valid. This is in contrast to an argument like "Fred is Mike's brother's son. Therefore Fred is Mike's nephew." Since this argument depends on the meanings of the words "brother", "son", and "nephew", the statement "Fred is Mike's nephew" is a so-called material consequence of "Fred is Mike's brother's son", not a formal consequence. A formal consequence must be true ''in all cases'', however this is an incomplete definition of formal consequence, since even the argument "''P'' is ''Q'''s brother's son, therefore ''P'' is ''Q'''s nephew" is valid in all cases, but is not a ''formal'' argument.


A priori property of logical consequence

If it is known that Q follows logically from P, then no information about the possible interpretations of P or Q will affect that knowledge. Our knowledge that Q is a logical consequence of P cannot be influenced by empirical knowledge. Deductively valid arguments can be known to be so without recourse to experience, so they must be knowable a priori. However, formality alone does not guarantee that logical consequence is not influenced by empirical knowledge. So the a priori property of logical consequence is considered to be independent of formality.


Proofs and models

The two prevailing techniques for providing accounts of logical consequence involve expressing the concept in terms of ''proofs'' and via ''models''. The study of the syntactic consequence (of a logic) is called (its)
proof theory Proof theory is a major branchAccording to Wang (1981), pp. 3–4, proof theory is one of four domains mathematical logic, together with model theory, axiomatic set theory, and recursion theory. Jon Barwise, Barwise (1978) consists of four correspo ...
whereas the study of (its) semantic consequence is called (its)
model theory In mathematical logic, model theory is the study of the relationship between formal theories (a collection of sentences in a formal language expressing statements about a mathematical structure), and their models (those structures in which the s ...
.


Syntactic consequence

A formula A is a syntactic consequenceS. C. Kleene,
Introduction to Metamathematics
' (1952), Van Nostrand Publishing. p.88.
within some formal system \mathcal of a set \Gamma of formulas if there is a formal proof in \mathcal of A from the set \Gamma. This is denoted \Gamma \vdash_ A. The turnstile symbol \vdash was originally introduced by Frege in 1879, but its current use only dates back to Rosser and Kleene (1934--1935). Syntactic consequence does not depend on any
interpretation Interpretation may refer to: Culture * Aesthetic interpretation, an explanation of the meaning of a work of art * Allegorical interpretation, an approach that assumes a text should not be interpreted literally * Dramatic Interpretation, an event ...
of the formal system.


Semantic consequence

A formula A is a semantic consequence within some formal system \mathcal of a set of statements \Gamma if and only if there is no model \mathcal in which all members of \Gamma are true and A is false. Etchemendy, John, ''Logical consequence'', The Cambridge Dictionary of Philosophy This is denoted \Gamma \models_ A,. Or, in other words, the set of the interpretations that make all members of \Gamma true is a subset of the set of the interpretations that make A true.


Modal accounts

Modal accounts of logical consequence are variations on the following basic idea: :\Gamma \vdash A is true if and only if it is ''necessary'' that if all of the elements of \Gamma are true, then A is true. Alternatively (and, most would say, equivalently): :\Gamma \vdash A is true if and only if it is ''impossible'' for all of the elements of \Gamma to be true and A false. Such accounts are called "modal" because they appeal to the modal notions of logical necessity and logical possibility. 'It is necessary that' is often expressed as a
universal quantifier In mathematical logic, a universal quantification is a type of quantifier, a logical constant which is interpreted as "given any" or "for all". It expresses that a predicate can be satisfied by every member of a domain of discourse. In other w ...
over possible worlds, so that the accounts above translate as: :\Gamma \vdash A is true if and only if there is no possible world at which all of the elements of \Gamma are true and A is false (untrue). Consider the modal account in terms of the argument given as an example above: :All frogs are green. :Kermit is a frog. :Therefore, Kermit is green. The conclusion is a logical consequence of the premises because we can't imagine a possible world where (a) all frogs are green; (b) Kermit is a frog; and (c) Kermit is not green.


Modal-formal accounts

Modal-formal accounts of logical consequence combine the modal and formal accounts above, yielding variations on the following basic idea: :\Gamma \vdash A if and only if it is impossible for an argument with the same logical form as \Gamma/A to have true premises and a false conclusion.


Warrant-based accounts

The accounts considered above are all "truth-preservational", in that they all assume that the characteristic feature of a good inference is that it never allows one to move from true premises to an untrue conclusion. As an alternative, some have proposed " warrant-preservational" accounts, according to which the characteristic feature of a good inference is that it never allows one to move from justifiably assertible premises to a conclusion that is not justifiably assertible. This is (roughly) the account favored by intuitionists such as Michael Dummett.


Non-monotonic logical consequence

The accounts discussed above all yield monotonic consequence relations, i.e. ones such that if A is a consequence of \Gamma, then A is a consequence of any superset of \Gamma. It is also possible to specify non-monotonic consequence relations to capture the idea that, e.g., 'Tweety can fly' is a logical consequence of : but not of :.


See also

* Abstract algebraic logic * Ampheck * Boolean algebra (logic) * Boolean domain * Boolean function * Boolean logic * Causality *
Deductive reasoning Deductive reasoning is the mental process of drawing deductive inferences. An inference is deductively valid if its conclusion follows logically from its premises, i.e. if it is impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion to be fals ...
*
Logic gate A logic gate is an idealized or physical device implementing a Boolean function, a logical operation performed on one or more binary inputs that produces a single binary output. Depending on the context, the term may refer to an ideal logic gate, ...
* Logical graph *
Peirce's law In logic, Peirce's law is named after the philosopher and logician Charles Sanders Peirce. It was taken as an axiom in his first axiomatisation of propositional logic. It can be thought of as the law of excluded middle written in a form tha ...
* Probabilistic logic * Propositional calculus * Sole sufficient operator * Strict conditional * Tautology (logic) * Tautological consequence * Therefore sign * Turnstile (symbol) * Double turnstile *
Validity Validity or Valid may refer to: Science/mathematics/statistics: * Validity (logic), a property of a logical argument * Scientific: ** Internal validity, the validity of causal inferences within scientific studies, usually based on experiments ...


Notes


Resources

* . * London: College Publications. Series
Mathematical logic and foundations
* . * 1st edition, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Norwell, MA. 2nd edition, Dover Publications, Mineola, NY, 2003. * . Papers include those by Gödel, Church, Rosser, Kleene, and Post. * . * in Lou Goble (ed.), ''The Blackwell Guide to Philosophical Logic''. * in Edward N. Zalta (ed.), ''The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy''. * . * . * 365–409. * * in Goble, Lou, ed., ''The Blackwell Guide to Philosophical Logic''. Blackwell. * (1st ed. 1950), (2nd ed. 1959), (3rd ed. 1972), (4th edition, 1982). * in D. Jacquette, ed., ''A Companion to Philosophical Logic''. Blackwell. * Reprinted in Tarski, A., 1983. ''Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics'', 2nd ed.
Oxford University Press Oxford University Press (OUP) is the university press of the University of Oxford. It is the largest university press in the world, and its printing history dates back to the 1480s. Having been officially granted the legal right to print book ...
. Originally published in Polish and German. * * A paper on 'implication' from math.niu.edu
Implication
* A definition of 'implicant


External links

* * * * * {{Authority control Philosophical logic Metalogic Propositional calculus Deductive reasoning Concepts in logic Syntax (logic) Binary operations