HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In the mathematical discipline of
set theory Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory, as a branch of mathematics, is mostly conce ...
, there are many ways of describing specific
countable In mathematics, a set is countable if either it is finite or it can be made in one to one correspondence with the set of natural numbers. Equivalently, a set is ''countable'' if there exists an injective function from it into the natural numbers; ...
ordinals. The smallest ones can be usefully and non-circularly expressed in terms of their
Cantor normal form In the mathematical field of set theory, ordinal arithmetic describes the three usual operations on ordinal numbers: addition, multiplication, and exponentiation. Each can be defined in essentially two different ways: either by constructing an e ...
s. Beyond that, many ordinals of relevance to
proof theory Proof theory is a major branchAccording to Wang (1981), pp. 3–4, proof theory is one of four domains mathematical logic, together with model theory, axiomatic set theory, and recursion theory. Jon Barwise, Barwise (1978) consists of four correspo ...
still have
computable Computability is the ability to solve a problem in an effective manner. It is a key topic of the field of computability theory within mathematical logic and the theory of computation within computer science. The computability of a problem is close ...
ordinal notation In mathematical logic and set theory, an ordinal notation is a partial function mapping the set of all finite sequences of symbols, themselves members of a finite alphabet, to a countable set of ordinals. A Gödel numbering is a function mapping t ...
s (see
ordinal analysis In proof theory, ordinal analysis assigns ordinals (often large countable ordinals) to mathematical theories as a measure of their strength. If theories have the same proof-theoretic ordinal they are often equiconsistent, and if one theory has ...
). However, it is not possible to decide effectively whether a given putative ordinal notation is a notation or not (for reasons somewhat analogous to the unsolvability of the
halting problem In computability theory, the halting problem is the problem of determining, from a description of an arbitrary computer program and an input, whether the program will finish running, or continue to run forever. Alan Turing proved in 1936 that a g ...
); various more-concrete ways of defining ordinals that definitely have notations are available. Since there are only countably many notations, all ordinals with notations are exhausted well below the first uncountable ordinal ω1; their
supremum In mathematics, the infimum (abbreviated inf; plural infima) of a subset S of a partially ordered set P is a greatest element in P that is less than or equal to each element of S, if such an element exists. Consequently, the term ''greatest l ...
is called ''Church–Kleene'' ω1 or ω1CK (not to be confused with the first uncountable ordinal, ω1), described
below Below may refer to: *Earth *Ground (disambiguation) *Soil *Floor *Bottom (disambiguation) Bottom may refer to: Anatomy and sex * Bottom (BDSM), the partner in a BDSM who takes the passive, receiving, or obedient role, to that of the top or ...
. Ordinal numbers below ω1CK are the recursive ordinals (see
below Below may refer to: *Earth *Ground (disambiguation) *Soil *Floor *Bottom (disambiguation) Bottom may refer to: Anatomy and sex * Bottom (BDSM), the partner in a BDSM who takes the passive, receiving, or obedient role, to that of the top or ...
). Countable ordinals larger than this may still be defined, but do not have notations. Due to the focus on countable ordinals,
ordinal arithmetic In the mathematical field of set theory, ordinal arithmetic describes the three usual operations on ordinal numbers: addition, multiplication, and exponentiation. Each can be defined in essentially two different ways: either by constructing an expl ...
is used throughout, except where otherwise noted. The ordinals described here are not as large as the ones described in
large cardinals In the mathematical field of set theory, a large cardinal property is a certain kind of property of Transfinite number, transfinite cardinal numbers. Cardinals with such properties are, as the name suggests, generally very "large" (for example, big ...
, but they are large among those that have constructive notations (descriptions). Larger and larger ordinals can be defined, but they become more and more difficult to describe.


Generalities on recursive ordinals


Ordinal notations

Recursive ordinal In mathematics, specifically computability and set theory, an ordinal \alpha is said to be computable or recursive if there is a computable well-ordering of a subset of the natural numbers having the order type \alpha. It is easy to check that \om ...
s (or computable ordinals) are certain countable ordinals: loosely speaking those represented by a
computable function Computable functions are the basic objects of study in computability theory. Computable functions are the formalized analogue of the intuitive notion of algorithms, in the sense that a function is computable if there exists an algorithm that can do ...
. There are several equivalent definitions of this: the simplest is to say that a computable ordinal is the order-type of some recursive (i.e., computable) well-ordering of the natural numbers; so, essentially, an ordinal is recursive when we can present the set of smaller ordinals in such a way that a computer (
Turing machine A Turing machine is a mathematical model of computation describing an abstract machine that manipulates symbols on a strip of tape according to a table of rules. Despite the model's simplicity, it is capable of implementing any computer algori ...
, say) can manipulate them (and, essentially, compare them). A different definition uses
Kleene Stephen Cole Kleene ( ; January 5, 1909 – January 25, 1994) was an American mathematician. One of the students of Alonzo Church, Kleene, along with Rózsa Péter, Alan Turing, Emil Post, and others, is best known as a founder of the branch of ...
's system of
ordinal notation In mathematical logic and set theory, an ordinal notation is a partial function mapping the set of all finite sequences of symbols, themselves members of a finite alphabet, to a countable set of ordinals. A Gödel numbering is a function mapping t ...
s. Briefly, an ordinal notation is either the name zero (describing the ordinal 0), or the successor of an ordinal notation (describing the successor of the ordinal described by that notation), or a Turing machine (computable function) that produces an increasing sequence of ordinal notations (that describe the ordinal that is the limit of the sequence), and ordinal notations are (partially) ordered so as to make the successor of ''o'' greater than ''o'' and to make the limit greater than any term of the sequence (this order is computable; however, the set O of ordinal notations itself is highly non-recursive, owing to the impossibility of deciding whether a given Turing machine does indeed produce a sequence of notations); a recursive ordinal is then an ordinal described by some ordinal notation. Any ordinal smaller than a recursive ordinal is itself recursive, so the set of all recursive ordinals forms a certain (countable) ordinal, the
Church–Kleene ordinal In mathematics, particularly set theory, non-recursive ordinals are large countable ordinals greater than all the recursive ordinals, and therefore can not be expressed using ordinal collapsing functions. The Church–Kleene ordinal and varian ...
(see below). It is tempting to forget about ordinal notations, and only speak of the recursive ordinals themselves: and some statements are made about recursive ordinals which, in fact, concern the notations for these ordinals. This leads to difficulties, however, as even the smallest infinite ordinal, ω, has many notations, some of which cannot be proved to be equivalent to the obvious notation (the simplest program that enumerates all natural numbers).


Relationship to systems of arithmetic

There is a relation between computable ordinals and certain
formal system A formal system is an abstract structure used for inferring theorems from axioms according to a set of rules. These rules, which are used for carrying out the inference of theorems from axioms, are the logical calculus of the formal system. A form ...
s (containing
arithmetic Arithmetic () is an elementary part of mathematics that consists of the study of the properties of the traditional operations on numbers— addition, subtraction, multiplication, division, exponentiation, and extraction of roots. In the 19th ...
, that is, at least a reasonable fragment of
Peano arithmetic In mathematical logic, the Peano axioms, also known as the Dedekind–Peano axioms or the Peano postulates, are axioms for the natural numbers presented by the 19th century Italian mathematician Giuseppe Peano. These axioms have been used nearly u ...
). Certain computable ordinals are so large that while they can be given by a certain ordinal notation ''o'', a given formal system might not be sufficiently powerful to show that ''o'' is, indeed, an ordinal notation: the system does not show
transfinite induction Transfinite induction is an extension of mathematical induction to well-ordered sets, for example to sets of ordinal numbers or cardinal numbers. Its correctness is a theorem of ZFC. Induction by cases Let P(\alpha) be a property defined for a ...
for such large ordinals. For example, the usual
first-order In mathematics and other formal sciences, first-order or first order most often means either: * "linear" (a polynomial of degree at most one), as in first-order approximation and other calculus uses, where it is contrasted with "polynomials of high ...
Peano axioms In mathematical logic, the Peano axioms, also known as the Dedekind–Peano axioms or the Peano postulates, are axioms for the natural numbers presented by the 19th century Italian mathematician Giuseppe Peano. These axioms have been used nearly ...
do not prove transfinite induction for (or beyond) ε0: while the ordinal ε0 can easily be arithmetically described (it is countable), the Peano axioms are not strong enough to show that it is indeed an ordinal; in fact, transfinite induction on ε0 proves the consistency of Peano's axioms (a theorem by
Gentzen Gerhard Karl Erich Gentzen (24 November 1909 – 4 August 1945) was a German mathematician and logician. He made major contributions to the foundations of mathematics, proof theory, especially on natural deduction and sequent calculus. He died o ...
), so by Gödel's second incompleteness theorem, Peano's axioms cannot formalize that reasoning. (This is at the basis of the
Kirby–Paris theorem In mathematical logic, Goodstein's theorem is a statement about the natural numbers, proved by Reuben Goodstein in 1944, which states that every ''Goodstein sequence'' eventually terminates at 0. Kirby and Paris showed that it is unprovable in Pe ...
on Goodstein sequences.) Since Peano arithmetic ''can'' prove that any ordinal less than ε0 is well ordered, we say that ε0 measures the
proof-theoretic strength In proof theory, ordinal analysis assigns ordinals (often large countable ordinals) to mathematical theories as a measure of their strength. If theories have the same proof-theoretic ordinal they are often equiconsistent, and if one theory h ...
of Peano's axioms. But we can do this for systems far beyond Peano's axioms. For example, the proof-theoretic strength of
Kripke–Platek set theory The Kripke–Platek set theory (KP), pronounced , is an axiomatic set theory developed by Saul Kripke and Richard Platek. The theory can be thought of as roughly the predicative part of ZFC and is considerably weaker than it. Axioms In its fo ...
is the
Bachmann–Howard ordinal In mathematics, the Bachmann–Howard ordinal (also known as the Howard ordinal, or Howard-Bachmann ordinal) is a large countable ordinal. It is the ordinal analysis, proof-theoretic ordinal of several mathematical theory (logic), theories, such as ...
, and, in fact, merely adding to Peano's axioms the axioms that state the well-ordering of all ordinals below the Bachmann–Howard ordinal is sufficient to obtain all arithmetical consequences of Kripke–Platek set theory.


Specific recursive ordinals


Predicative definitions and the Veblen hierarchy

We have already mentioned (see
Cantor normal form In the mathematical field of set theory, ordinal arithmetic describes the three usual operations on ordinal numbers: addition, multiplication, and exponentiation. Each can be defined in essentially two different ways: either by constructing an e ...
) the ordinal ε0, which is the smallest satisfying the equation \omega^\alpha = \alpha, so it is the limit of the sequence 0, 1, \omega, \omega^\omega, \omega^, ... The next ordinal satisfying this equation is called ε1: it is the limit of the sequence :\varepsilon_0+1, \qquad \omega^=\varepsilon_0\cdot\omega,\qquad\omega^=(\varepsilon_0)^\omega,\qquad\text More generally, the \iota-th ordinal such that \omega^\alpha = \alpha is called \varepsilon_\iota. We could define \zeta_0 as the smallest ordinal such that \varepsilon_\alpha=\alpha, but since the Greek alphabet does not have transfinitely many letters it is better to use a more robust notation: define ordinals \varphi_\gamma(\beta) by transfinite induction as follows: let \varphi_0(\beta) = \omega^\beta and let \varphi_(\beta) be the \beta-th fixed point of \varphi_\gamma (i.e., the \beta-th ordinal such that \varphi_\gamma(\alpha)=\alpha; so for example, \varphi_1(\beta) = \varepsilon_\beta), and when \delta is a limit ordinal, define \varphi_\delta(\alpha) as the \alpha-th common fixed point of the \varphi_\gamma for all \gamma<\delta. This family of functions is known as the
Veblen hierarchy In mathematics, the Veblen functions are a hierarchy of normal functions (continuous function (set theory), continuous strictly increasing function, strictly increasing function (mathematics), functions from ordinal number, ordinals to ordinals), i ...
(there are inessential variations in the definition, such as letting, for \delta a limit ordinal, \varphi_\delta(\alpha) be the limit of the \varphi_\gamma(\alpha) for \gamma<\delta: this essentially just shifts the indices by 1, which is harmless). \varphi_\gamma is called the \gamma^
Veblen function In mathematics, the Veblen functions are a hierarchy of normal functions ( continuous strictly increasing functions from ordinals to ordinals), introduced by Oswald Veblen in . If φ0 is any normal function, then for any non-zero ordinal α, φ ...
(to the base \omega). Ordering: \varphi_\alpha(\beta) < \varphi_\gamma(\delta) if and only if either (\alpha = \gamma and \beta < \delta) or (\alpha < \gamma and \beta < \varphi_\gamma(\delta)) or (\alpha > \gamma and \varphi_\alpha(\beta) < \delta).


The Feferman–Schütte ordinal and beyond

The smallest ordinal such that \varphi_\alpha(0) = \alpha is known as the
Feferman–Schütte ordinal In mathematics, the Feferman–Schütte ordinal Γ0 is a large countable ordinal. It is the proof-theoretic ordinal of several mathematical theories, such as arithmetical transfinite recursion. It is named after Solomon Feferman and Kurt Schütte, ...
and generally written \Gamma_0. It can be described as the set of all ordinals that can be written as finite expressions, starting from zero, using only the Veblen hierarchy and addition. The Feferman–Schütte ordinal is important because, in a sense that is complicated to make precise, it is the smallest (infinite) ordinal that cannot be (" predicatively") described using smaller ordinals. It measures the strength of such systems as "
arithmetical transfinite recursion Reverse mathematics is a program in mathematical logic that seeks to determine which axioms are required to prove theorems of mathematics. Its defining method can briefly be described as "going backwards from the theorems to the axioms", in cont ...
". More generally, Γ''α'' enumerates the ordinals that cannot be obtained from smaller ordinals using addition and the Veblen functions. It is, of course, possible to describe ordinals beyond the Feferman–Schütte ordinal. One could continue to seek fixed points in a more and more complicated manner: enumerate the fixed points of \alpha\mapsto\Gamma_\alpha, then enumerate the fixed points of ''that'', and so on, and then look for the first ordinal ''α'' such that ''α'' is obtained in ''α'' steps of this process, and continue diagonalizing in this ''ad hoc'' manner. This leads to the definition of the "
small Small may refer to: Science and technology * SMALL, an ALGOL-like programming language * Small (anatomy), the lumbar region of the back * ''Small'' (journal), a nano-science publication * <small>, an HTML element that defines smaller text ...
" and "
large Large means of great size. Large may also refer to: Mathematics * Arbitrarily large, a phrase in mathematics * Large cardinal, a property of certain transfinite numbers * Large category, a category with a proper class of objects and morphisms (or ...
" Veblen ordinals.


Impredicative ordinals

To go far beyond the Feferman–Schütte ordinal, one needs to introduce new methods. Unfortunately there is not yet any standard way to do this: every author in the subject seems to have invented their own system of notation, and it is quite hard to translate between the different systems. The first such system was introduced by Bachmann in 1950 (in an ''ad hoc'' manner), and different extensions and variations of it were described by Buchholz, Takeuti (ordinal diagrams), Feferman (θ systems), Aczel, Bridge, Schütte, and Pohlers. However most systems use the same basic idea, of constructing new countable ordinals by using the existence of certain uncountable ordinals. Here is an example of such a definition, described in much greater detail in the article on
ordinal collapsing function In mathematical logic and set theory, an ordinal collapsing function (or projection function) is a technique for defining ( notations for) certain recursive large countable ordinals, whose principle is to give names to certain ordinals much larger ...
: *ψ(''α'') is defined to be the smallest ordinal that cannot be constructed by starting with 0, 1, ω and Ω, and repeatedly applying addition, multiplication and exponentiation, and ψ to previously constructed ordinals (except that ψ can only be applied to arguments less than ''α'', to ensure that it is well defined). Here Ω = ω1 is the first uncountable ordinal. It is put in because otherwise the function ψ gets "stuck" at the smallest ordinal ''σ'' such that ε''σ''=''σ'': in particular ψ(''α'')=''σ'' for any ordinal α satisfying ''σ''≤''α''≤Ω. However the fact that we included Ω allows us to get past this point: ψ(Ω+1) is greater than ''σ''. The key property of Ω that we used is that it is greater than any ordinal produced by ψ. To construct still larger ordinals, we can extend the definition of ψ by throwing in more ways of constructing uncountable ordinals. There are several ways to do this, described to some extent in the article on
ordinal collapsing function In mathematical logic and set theory, an ordinal collapsing function (or projection function) is a technique for defining ( notations for) certain recursive large countable ordinals, whose principle is to give names to certain ordinals much larger ...
. The
Bachmann–Howard ordinal In mathematics, the Bachmann–Howard ordinal (also known as the Howard ordinal, or Howard-Bachmann ordinal) is a large countable ordinal. It is the ordinal analysis, proof-theoretic ordinal of several mathematical theory (logic), theories, such as ...
(sometimes just called the Howard ordinal, ψ0(εΩ+1) with the notation above) is an important one, because it describes the proof-theoretic strength of
Kripke–Platek set theory The Kripke–Platek set theory (KP), pronounced , is an axiomatic set theory developed by Saul Kripke and Richard Platek. The theory can be thought of as roughly the predicative part of ZFC and is considerably weaker than it. Axioms In its fo ...
. Indeed, the main importance of these large ordinals, and the reason to describe them, is their relation to certain formal systems as explained above. However, such powerful formal systems as full
second-order arithmetic In mathematical logic, second-order arithmetic is a collection of axiomatic systems that formalize the natural numbers and their subsets. It is an alternative to axiomatic set theory as a foundation for much, but not all, of mathematics. A precurs ...
, let alone
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory In set theory, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, named after mathematicians Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, is an axiomatic system that was proposed in the early twentieth century in order to formulate a theory of sets free of paradoxes such as ...
, seem beyond reach for the moment.


Beyond even the Bachmann-Howard ordinal

Beyond this, there are multiple recursive ordinals which aren't as well known as the previous ones. The first of these is Buchholz's ordinal, defined as \psi_0(\Omega_\omega), abbreviated as just \psi(\Omega_\omega), using the previous notation. It is the proof-theoretic ordinal of \Pi_1^1-CA_0, a first-order theory of arithmetic allowing quantification over the natural numbers as well as ''sets'' of natural numbers, and ID_, the "formal theory of finitely iterated inductive definitions". Next is the Takeuti-Feferman-Buchholz ordinal, the proof-theoretic ordinal of \Pi_1^1 -CA + BI; and another subsystem of second-order arithmetic: \Pi_1^1 - comprehension + transfinite induction, and ID_\omega, the "formal theory of \omega-times iterated inductive definitions". In this notation, it is defined as \psi_0(\varepsilon_). It is the supremum of the range of Buchholz's psi functions. It was first named by David Madore. The next ordinal is mentioned in a piece of code describin
large countable ordinals and numbers in Agda
and defined by "AndrasKovacs" as \psi_0(\Omega_ \cdot \varepsilon_0). The next ordinal is mentioned in the same piece of code as earlier, and defined as \psi_0(\Omega_). It is the proof-theoretic ordinal of ID_. This next ordinal is, once again, mentioned in this same piece of code, defined as \psi_0(\Omega_), is the proof-theoretic ordinal of ID_. In general, the proof-theoretic ordinal of ID_ is equal to \psi_0(\Omega_) — note that in this certain instance, \Omega_0 represents 1, the first nonzero ordinal. Most ordinals up to this point can be expressed using the Buchholz hydra game (e.g. \psi(\Omega_\omega) = +(0(\omega))) Next is an unnamed ordinal, referred by David Madore as the "countable" collapse of \varepsilon_, where I is the first inaccessible (=\Pi^1_0-indescribable) cardinal. This is the proof-theoretic ordinal of Kripke-Platek set theory augmented by the recursive inaccessibility of the class of ordinals (KPi), or, on the arithmetical side, of \Delta^1_2 -comprehension + transfinite induction. Its value is equal to \psi(\varepsilon_) using an unknown function. Next is another unnamed ordinal, referred by David Madore as the "countable" collapse of \varepsilon_, where M is the first Mahlo cardinal. This is the proof-theoretic ordinal of KPM, an extension of Kripke-Platek set theory based on a Mahlo cardinal. Its value is equal to \psi(\varepsilon_) using one of Buchholz's various psi functions. Next is another unnamed ordinal, referred by David Madore as the "countable" collapse of \varepsilon_, where K is the first weakly compact (=\Pi^1_1-indescribable) cardinal. This is the proof-theoretic ordinal of Kripke-Platek set theory + Π3 - Ref. Its value is equal to \Psi(\varepsilon_) using Rathjen's Psi function. Next is another unnamed ordinal, referred by David Madore as the "countable" collapse of \varepsilon_, where \Xi is the first \Pi^2_0-indescribable cardinal. This is the proof-theoretic ordinal of Kripke-Platek set theory + Πω-Ref. Its value is equal to \Psi^_X using Stegert's Psi function, where X = (\omega^+; P_0; \epsilon, \epsilon, 0). Next is the last unnamed ordinal, referred by David Madore as the proof-theoretic ordinal of Stability. This is the proof-theoretic ordinal of Stability, an extension of Kripke-Platek set theory. Its value is equal to \Psi^_X using Stegert's Psi function, where X = (\omega^+; P_0; \epsilon, \epsilon, 0). Next is a group of ordinals which not that much are known about, but are still fairly significant (in ascending order): * The proof-theoretic ordinal of
second-order arithmetic In mathematical logic, second-order arithmetic is a collection of axiomatic systems that formalize the natural numbers and their subsets. It is an alternative to axiomatic set theory as a foundation for much, but not all, of mathematics. A precurs ...
. * A possible limit of Taranovsky's C ordinal notation. (Conjectural, assuming well-foundedness of the notation system) * The proof-theoretic ordinal of ZFC.


"Unrecursable" recursive ordinals

By dropping the requirement of having a concrete description, even larger recursive countable ordinals can be obtained as the ordinals measuring the strengths of various strong theories; roughly speaking, these ordinals are the smallest ordinals that the theories cannot prove are well ordered. By taking stronger and stronger theories such as
second-order arithmetic In mathematical logic, second-order arithmetic is a collection of axiomatic systems that formalize the natural numbers and their subsets. It is an alternative to axiomatic set theory as a foundation for much, but not all, of mathematics. A precurs ...
,
Zermelo set theory Zermelo set theory (sometimes denoted by Z-), as set out in a seminal paper in 1908 by Ernst Zermelo, is the ancestor of modern Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (ZF) and its extensions, such as von Neumann–Bernays–Gödel set theory (NBG). It be ...
,
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory In set theory, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, named after mathematicians Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, is an axiomatic system that was proposed in the early twentieth century in order to formulate a theory of sets free of paradoxes such as ...
, or Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with various
large cardinal In the mathematical field of set theory, a large cardinal property is a certain kind of property of transfinite cardinal numbers. Cardinals with such properties are, as the name suggests, generally very "large" (for example, bigger than the least Î ...
axioms, one gets some extremely large recursive ordinals. (Strictly speaking it is not known that all of these really are ordinals: by construction, the ordinal strength of a theory can only be proved to be an ordinal from an even stronger theory. So for the large cardinal axioms this becomes quite unclear.)


Beyond recursive ordinals


The Church–Kleene ordinal

The supremum of the set of
recursive ordinal In mathematics, specifically computability and set theory, an ordinal \alpha is said to be computable or recursive if there is a computable well-ordering of a subset of the natural numbers having the order type \alpha. It is easy to check that \om ...
s is the smallest ordinal that ''cannot'' be described in a recursive way. (It is not the order type of any recursive well-ordering of the integers.) That ordinal is a countable ordinal called the
Church–Kleene ordinal In mathematics, particularly set theory, non-recursive ordinals are large countable ordinals greater than all the recursive ordinals, and therefore can not be expressed using ordinal collapsing functions. The Church–Kleene ordinal and varian ...
, \omega_1^. Thus, \omega_1^ is the smallest non-recursive ordinal, and there is no hope of precisely "describing" any ordinals from this point on—we can only ''define'' them. But it is still far less than the first uncountable ordinal, \omega_1. However, as its symbol suggests, it behaves in many ways rather like \omega_1. For instance, one can define ordinal collapsing functions using \omega_1^ instead of \omega_1.


Admissible ordinals

The Church–Kleene ordinal is again related to
Kripke–Platek set theory The Kripke–Platek set theory (KP), pronounced , is an axiomatic set theory developed by Saul Kripke and Richard Platek. The theory can be thought of as roughly the predicative part of ZFC and is considerably weaker than it. Axioms In its fo ...
, but now in a different way: whereas the Bachmann–Howard ordinal (described above) was the smallest ordinal for which KP does not prove transfinite induction, the Church–Kleene ordinal is the smallest ''α'' such that the construction of the Gödel universe, ''L'', up to stage ''α'', yields a model L_\alpha of KP. Such ordinals are called admissible, thus \omega_1^ is the smallest admissible ordinal (beyond ω in case the axiom of infinity is not included in KP). By a theorem of Sacks, the countable admissible ordinals are exactly those constructed in a manner similar to the Church–Kleene ordinal but for Turing machines with
oracles An oracle is a person or agency considered to provide wise and insightful counsel or prophetic predictions, most notably including precognition of the future, inspired by deities. As such, it is a form of divination. Description The word '' ...
. One sometimes writes \omega_\alpha^ for the \alpha-th ordinal that is either admissible or a limit of smaller admissibles.


Beyond admissible ordinals

\omega_\omega^ is the smallest limit of admissible ordinals (mentioned later), yet the ordinal itself is not admissible. It is also the smallest \alpha such that L_\alpha \cap P(\omega) is a model of \Pi^1_1-comprehension. An ordinal that is both admissible and a limit of admissibles, or equivalently such that \alpha is the \alpha-th admissible ordinal, is called ''recursively inaccessible''. An ordinal that is both recursively inaccessible and a limit of recursively inaccessibles is called ''recursively hyperinaccessible''. There exists a theory of large ordinals in this manner that is highly parallel to that of (small)
large cardinals In the mathematical field of set theory, a large cardinal property is a certain kind of property of Transfinite number, transfinite cardinal numbers. Cardinals with such properties are, as the name suggests, generally very "large" (for example, big ...
. For example, we can define ''recursively Mahlo ordinals'': these are the \alpha such that every \alpha-recursive closed unbounded subset of \alpha contains an admissible ordinal (a recursive analog of the definition of a
Mahlo cardinal In mathematics, a Mahlo cardinal is a certain kind of large cardinal number. Mahlo cardinals were first described by . As with all large cardinals, none of these varieties of Mahlo cardinals can be proven to exist by ZFC (assuming ZFC is consist ...
). But note that we are still talking about possibly countable ordinals here. (While the existence of inaccessible or Mahlo cardinals cannot be proved in
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory In set theory, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, named after mathematicians Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, is an axiomatic system that was proposed in the early twentieth century in order to formulate a theory of sets free of paradoxes such as ...
, that of recursively inaccessible or recursively Mahlo ordinals is a theorem of ZFC: in fact, any
regular cardinal In set theory, a regular cardinal is a cardinal number that is equal to its own cofinality. More explicitly, this means that \kappa is a regular cardinal if and only if every unbounded subset C \subseteq \kappa has cardinality \kappa. Infinite ...
is recursively Mahlo and more, but even if we limit ourselves to countable ordinals, ZFC proves the existence of recursively Mahlo ordinals. They are, however, beyond the reach of Kripke–Platek set theory.)


Reflection and nonprojectibility

For a set of formulae \Gamma, a limit ordinal \alpha is called ''\Gamma-reflecting'' if the rank L_\alpha satisfies a certain reflection property for each \Gamma-formula \phi. These ordinals appear in ordinal analysis of theories such as ''KP+Π3-ref'', a theory augmenting Kripke-Platek set theory by a \Pi_3-reflection schema. They can also be considered "recursive analogues" of some uncountable cardinals such as weakly compact cardinals and indescribable cardinals. For example, an ordinal which \Pi_3-reflecting is called ''recursively weakly compact''. For finite n, the least \Pi_n-reflecting ordinal is also the supremum of the closure ordinals of monotonic inductive definitions whose graphs are Πm+10. In particular, \Pi_3-reflecting ordinals also have a characterization using higher-type functionals on ordinal functions, lending them the name ''2-admissible ordinals''. An unpublished paper by
Solomon Feferman Solomon Feferman (December 13, 1928 – July 26, 2016) was an American philosopher and mathematician who worked in mathematical logic. Life Solomon Feferman was born in The Bronx in New York City to working-class parents who had immigrated to th ...
supplies, for each finite n, a similar property corresponding to \Pi_n-reflection. An admissible ordinal \alpha is called ''nonprojectible'' if there is no total \alpha-recursive injective function mapping \alpha into a smaller ordinal. (This is trivially true for regular cardinals; however, we are mainly interested in countable ordinals.) Being nonprojectible is a much stronger condition than being admissible, recursively inaccessible, or even recursively Mahlo. By Jensen's method of projecta, this statement is equivalent to the statement that the Gödel universe, ''L'', up to stage α, yields a model L_\alpha of KP + \Sigma_1-separation. However, \Sigma_1-separation on its own (not in the presence of V=L) is not a strong enough axiom schema to imply nonprojectibility, in fact there are transitive models of KP+\Sigma_1-separation of any admissible height >\omega.


"Unprovable" ordinals

We can imagine even larger ordinals that are still countable. For example, if ZFC has a
transitive model In mathematical set theory, a transitive model is a model of set theory that is standard and transitive. Standard means that the membership relation is the usual one, and transitive means that the model is a transitive set or class. Examples *An i ...
(a hypothesis stronger than the mere hypothesis of consistency, and implied by the existence of an inaccessible cardinal), then there exists a countable \alpha such that L_\alpha is a model of ZFC. Such ordinals are beyond the strength of ZFC in the sense that it cannot (by construction) prove their existence. Even larger countable ordinals, called the '' stable ordinals'', can be defined by indescribability conditions or as those \alpha such that L_\alpha is a Σ1-elementary submodel of ''L''; the existence of these ordinals can be proved in ZFC, and they are closely related to the nonprojectible ordinals from a model-theoretic perspective.D. Madore
A Zoo of Ordinals
(2017) (p.6). Accessed 2021-05-06.


Variants of stable ordinals

These are weakened variants of stable ordinals. * A countable ordinal \alpha is called (+\beta)-stable
iff In logic and related fields such as mathematics and philosophy, "if and only if" (shortened as "iff") is a biconditional logical connective between statements, where either both statements are true or both are false. The connective is bicon ...
L_\alpha \prec_ L_D. Madore
A Zoo of Ordinals
Accessed 2022-12-04.
* A countable ordinal \alpha is called (^+)-stable
iff In logic and related fields such as mathematics and philosophy, "if and only if" (shortened as "iff") is a biconditional logical connective between statements, where either both statements are true or both are false. The connective is bicon ...
L_\alpha \prec_ L_, where \beta is the least
admissible ordinal In set theory, an ordinal number ''α'' is an admissible ordinal if L''α'' is an admissible set (that is, a transitive model of Kripke–Platek set theory); in other words, ''α'' is admissible when ''α'' is a limit ordinal and L''α'' ⊧ Σ0- ...
larger than \alpha. * A countable ordinal \alpha is called (^)-stable
iff In logic and related fields such as mathematics and philosophy, "if and only if" (shortened as "iff") is a biconditional logical connective between statements, where either both statements are true or both are false. The connective is bicon ...
L_\alpha \prec_ L_, where \beta is the least
admissible ordinal In set theory, an ordinal number ''α'' is an admissible ordinal if L''α'' is an admissible set (that is, a transitive model of Kripke–Platek set theory); in other words, ''α'' is admissible when ''α'' is a limit ordinal and L''α'' ⊧ Σ0- ...
larger than an admissible ordinal larger than \alpha. * A countable ordinal \alpha is called inaccessibly-stable
iff In logic and related fields such as mathematics and philosophy, "if and only if" (shortened as "iff") is a biconditional logical connective between statements, where either both statements are true or both are false. The connective is bicon ...
L_\alpha \prec_ L_, where \beta is the least recursively inaccessible ordinal larger than \alpha. * A countable ordinal \alpha is called Mahlo-stable
iff In logic and related fields such as mathematics and philosophy, "if and only if" (shortened as "iff") is a biconditional logical connective between statements, where either both statements are true or both are false. The connective is bicon ...
L_\alpha \prec_ L_, where \beta is the least recursively Mahlo ordinal larger than \alpha. * A countable ordinal \alpha is called doubly (+1)-stable
iff In logic and related fields such as mathematics and philosophy, "if and only if" (shortened as "iff") is a biconditional logical connective between statements, where either both statements are true or both are false. The connective is bicon ...
there is a (+1)-stable ordinal \beta > \alpha such that L_\alpha \prec_ L_.


A pseudo-well-ordering

Within the scheme of notations of Kleene some represent ordinals and some do not. One can define a recursive total ordering that is a subset of the Kleene notations and has an initial segment which is well-ordered with order-type \omega_1^. Every recursively enumerable (or even hyperarithmetic) nonempty subset of this total ordering has a least element. So it resembles a well-ordering in some respects. For example, one can define the arithmetic operations on it. Yet it is not possible to effectively determine exactly where the initial well-ordered part ends and the part lacking a least element begins. For an example of a recursive pseudo-well-ordering, let S be ATR0 or another recursively axiomatizable theory that has an ω-model but no hyperarithmetical ω-models, and (if needed) conservatively extend S with
Skolem function In mathematical logic, a formula of first-order logic is in Skolem normal form if it is in prenex normal form with only universal first-order quantifiers. Every first-order formula may be converted into Skolem normal form while not changing its ...
s. Let T be the tree of (essentially) finite partial ω-models of S: A sequence of natural numbers x_1,x_2,...,x_n is in T iff S plus ∃m φ(m) ⇒ φ(x⌈φ⌉) (for the first n formulas φ with one numeric free variable; ⌈φ⌉ is the Gödel number) has no inconsistency proof shorter than n. Then the
Kleene–Brouwer order In descriptive set theory, the Kleene–Brouwer order or Lusin–Sierpiński order is a linear order on finite sequences over some linearly ordered set (X, <), that differs from the more commonly used
The countable admissible ordinal equivalence relation
(2017), p.1233. Accessed 28 December 2022.


References

Most books describing large countable ordinals are on proof theory, and unfortunately tend to be out of print.


On recursive ordinals

* Wolfram Pohlers, ''Proof theory'', Springer 1989 (for Veblen hierarchy and some impredicative ordinals). This is probably the most readable book on large countable ordinals (which is not saying much). *
Gaisi Takeuti was a Japanese mathematician, known for his work in proof theory. After graduating from Tokyo University, he went to Princeton to study under Kurt Gödel. He later became a professor at the University of Illinois at Urbana–Champaign. Takeu ...
, ''Proof theory'', 2nd edition 1987 (for ordinal diagrams) *
Kurt Schütte Kurt Schütte (14 October 1909, Salzwedel – 18 August 1998, Munich) was a German mathematician who worked on proof theory and ordinal analysis. The Feferman–Schütte ordinal, which he showed to be the precise ordinal bound for predicativi ...
, ''Proof theory'', Springer 1977 (for Veblen hierarchy and some impredicative ordinals) *
Craig Smorynski __NOTOC__ Craig may refer to: Geology *Craig (landform), a rocky hill or mountain often having large casims or sharp intentations. People (and fictional characters) *Craig (surname) *Craig (given name) Places Scotland *Craig, Angus, aka Barony of ...
, ''The varieties of arboreal experience'' Math. Intelligencer 4 (1982), no. 4, 182–189; contains an informal description of the Veblen hierarchy. * Hartley Rogers Jr., ''Theory of Recursive Functions and Effective Computability'' McGraw-Hill (1967) (describes recursive ordinals and the Church–Kleene ordinal) * Larry W. Miller, ''Normal Functions and Constructive Ordinal Notations'', ''
The Journal of Symbolic Logic ''The'' () is a grammatical article in English, denoting persons or things already mentioned, under discussion, implied or otherwise presumed familiar to listeners, readers, or speakers. It is the definite article in English. ''The'' is the m ...
'', volume 41, number 2, June 1976, pages 439 to 459, , *
Hilbert Levitz David Hilbert (; ; 23 January 1862 – 14 February 1943) was a German mathematician, one of the most influential mathematicians of the 19th and early 20th centuries. Hilbert discovered and developed a broad range of fundamental ideas in many a ...
,
Transfinite Ordinals and Their Notations: For The Uninitiated
', expository article (8 pages, in
PostScript PostScript (PS) is a page description language in the electronic publishing and desktop publishing realm. It is a dynamically typed, concatenative programming language. It was created at Adobe Systems by John Warnock, Charles Geschke, Doug Br ...
) *
Herman Ruge Jervell Herman may refer to: People * Herman (name), list of people with this name * Saint Herman (disambiguation) * Peter Noone (born 1947), known by the mononym Herman Places in the United States * Herman, Arkansas * Herman, Michigan * Herman, Minneso ...

Truth and provability
manuscript in progress.


Beyond recursive ordinals

* *


Both recursive and nonrecursive ordinals

*
Michael Rathjen Michael may refer to: People * Michael (given name), a given name * Michael (surname), including a list of people with the surname Michael Given name "Michael" * Michael (archangel), ''first'' of God's archangels in the Jewish, Christian and ...
, "The realm of ordinal analysis." in S. B. Cooper and J. Truss (eds.): ''Sets and Proofs''. (Cambridge University Press, 1999) 219–279. A
Postscript file


Inline references

{{countable ordinals Ordinal numbers Proof theory