HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In the mathematical discipline of
set theory Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies Set (mathematics), sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory – as a branch of mathema ...
, there are many ways of describing specific
countable In mathematics, a Set (mathematics), set is countable if either it is finite set, finite or it can be made in one to one correspondence with the set of natural numbers. Equivalently, a set is ''countable'' if there exists an injective function fro ...
ordinals. The smallest ones can be usefully and non-circularly expressed in terms of their Cantor normal forms. Beyond that, many ordinals of relevance to
proof theory Proof theory is a major branchAccording to , proof theory is one of four domains mathematical logic, together with model theory, axiomatic set theory, and recursion theory. consists of four corresponding parts, with part D being about "Proof The ...
still have
computable Computability is the ability to solve a problem by an effective procedure. It is a key topic of the field of computability theory within mathematical logic and the theory of computation within computer science. The computability of a problem is cl ...
ordinal notations (see
ordinal analysis In proof theory, ordinal analysis assigns ordinals (often large countable ordinals) to mathematical theories as a measure of their strength. If theories have the same proof-theoretic ordinal they are often equiconsistent, and if one theory ha ...
). However, it is not possible to decide effectively whether a given putative ordinal notation is a notation or not (for reasons somewhat analogous to the unsolvability of the
halting problem In computability theory (computer science), computability theory, the halting problem is the problem of determining, from a description of an arbitrary computer program and an input, whether the program will finish running, or continue to run for ...
); various more-concrete ways of defining ordinals that definitely have notations are available. Since there are only countably many notations, all ordinals with notations are exhausted well below the first uncountable ordinal ω1; their
supremum In mathematics, the infimum (abbreviated inf; : infima) of a subset S of a partially ordered set P is the greatest element in P that is less than or equal to each element of S, if such an element exists. If the infimum of S exists, it is unique, ...
is called ''Church–Kleene'' ω1 or ω (not to be confused with the first uncountable ordinal, ω1), described below. Ordinal numbers below ω are the ''recursive'' ordinals (see below). Countable ordinals larger than this may still be defined, but do not have notations. Due to the focus on countable ordinals,
ordinal arithmetic In the mathematical field of set theory, ordinal arithmetic describes the three usual operations on ordinal numbers: addition, multiplication, and exponentiation. Each can be defined in essentially two different ways: either by constructing an expl ...
is used throughout, except where otherwise noted. The ordinals described here are not as large as the ones described in large cardinals, but they are large among those that have constructive notations (descriptions). Larger and larger ordinals can be defined, but they become more and more difficult to describe.


Generalities on recursive ordinals


Ordinal notations

Computable ordinals (or recursive ordinals) are certain countable ordinals: loosely speaking those represented by a
computable function Computable functions are the basic objects of study in computability theory. Informally, a function is ''computable'' if there is an algorithm that computes the value of the function for every value of its argument. Because of the lack of a precis ...
. There are several equivalent definitions of this: the simplest is to say that a computable ordinal is the order-type of some recursive (i.e., computable) well-ordering of the natural numbers; so, essentially, an ordinal is recursive when we can present the set of smaller ordinals in such a way that a computer (
Turing machine A Turing machine is a mathematical model of computation describing an abstract machine that manipulates symbols on a strip of tape according to a table of rules. Despite the model's simplicity, it is capable of implementing any computer algori ...
, say) can manipulate them (and, essentially, compare them). A different definition uses
Kleene Stephen Cole Kleene ( ; January 5, 1909 – January 25, 1994) was an American mathematician. One of the students of Alonzo Church, Kleene, along with Rózsa Péter, Alan Turing, Emil Post, and others, is best known as a founder of the branch of ...
's system of ordinal notations. Briefly, an ordinal notation is either the name zero (describing the ordinal 0), or the successor of an ordinal notation (describing the successor of the ordinal described by that notation), or a Turing machine (computable function) that produces an increasing sequence of ordinal notations (that describe the ordinal that is the limit of the sequence), and ordinal notations are (partially) ordered so as to make the successor of ''o'' greater than ''o'' and to make the limit greater than any term of the sequence (this order is computable; however, the set O of ordinal notations itself is highly non-recursive, owing to the impossibility of deciding whether a given Turing machine does indeed produce a sequence of notations); a recursive ordinal is then an ordinal described by some ordinal notation. Any ordinal smaller than a recursive ordinal is itself recursive, so the set of all recursive ordinals forms a certain (countable) ordinal, the Church–Kleene ordinal (see below). It is tempting to forget about ordinal notations, and only speak of the recursive ordinals themselves: and some statements are made about recursive ordinals which, in fact, concern the notations for these ordinals. This leads to difficulties, however, as even the smallest infinite ordinal, ω, has many notations, some of which cannot be proved to be equivalent to the obvious notation (the simplest program that enumerates all natural numbers).


Relationship to systems of arithmetic

There is a relation between computable ordinals and certain
formal system A formal system is an abstract structure and formalization of an axiomatic system used for deducing, using rules of inference, theorems from axioms. In 1921, David Hilbert proposed to use formal systems as the foundation of knowledge in ma ...
s (containing
arithmetic Arithmetic is an elementary branch of mathematics that deals with numerical operations like addition, subtraction, multiplication, and division. In a wider sense, it also includes exponentiation, extraction of roots, and taking logarithms. ...
, that is, at least a reasonable fragment of
Peano arithmetic In mathematical logic, the Peano axioms (, ), also known as the Dedekind–Peano axioms or the Peano postulates, are axioms for the natural numbers presented by the 19th-century Italian mathematician Giuseppe Peano. These axioms have been used nea ...
). Certain computable ordinals are so large that while they can be given by a certain ordinal notation ''o'', a given formal system might not be sufficiently powerful to show that ''o'' is, indeed, an ordinal notation: the system does not show
transfinite induction Transfinite induction is an extension of mathematical induction to well-ordered sets, for example to sets of ordinal numbers or cardinal numbers. Its correctness is a theorem of ZFC. Induction by cases Let P(\alpha) be a property defined for a ...
for such large ordinals. For example, the usual first-order
Peano axioms In mathematical logic, the Peano axioms (, ), also known as the Dedekind–Peano axioms or the Peano postulates, are axioms for the natural numbers presented by the 19th-century Italian mathematician Giuseppe Peano. These axioms have been used nea ...
do not prove transfinite induction for (or beyond) ε0: while the ordinal ε0 can easily be arithmetically described (it is countable), the Peano axioms are not strong enough to show that it is indeed an ordinal; in fact, transfinite induction on ε0 proves the consistency of Peano's axioms (a theorem by Gentzen), so by Gödel's second incompleteness theorem, Peano's axioms cannot formalize that reasoning. (This is at the basis of the Kirby–Paris theorem on Goodstein sequences.) Since Peano arithmetic ''can'' prove that any ordinal less than ε0 is well ordered, we say that ε0 measures the proof-theoretic strength of Peano's axioms. But we can do this for systems far beyond Peano's axioms. For example, the proof-theoretic strength of
Kripke–Platek set theory The Kripke–Platek set theory (KP), pronounced , is an axiomatic set theory developed by Saul Kripke and Richard Platek. The theory can be thought of as roughly the predicative part of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (ZFC) and is considerably weak ...
is the Bachmann–Howard ordinal, and, in fact, merely adding to Peano's axioms the axioms that state the well-ordering of all ordinals below the Bachmann–Howard ordinal is sufficient to obtain all arithmetical consequences of Kripke–Platek set theory.


Specific recursive ordinals


Predicative definitions and the Veblen hierarchy

We have already mentioned (see Cantor normal form) the ordinal ε0, which is the smallest satisfying the equation \omega^\alpha = \alpha, so it is the limit of the sequence 0, 1, \omega, \omega^\omega, \omega^, ... The next ordinal satisfying this equation is called ε1: it is the limit of the sequence :\varepsilon_0+1, \qquad \omega^=\varepsilon_0\cdot\omega,\qquad\omega^=(\varepsilon_0)^\omega,\qquad\text More generally, the \iota-th ordinal such that \omega^\alpha = \alpha is called \varepsilon_\iota. We could define \zeta_0 as the smallest ordinal such that \varepsilon_\alpha=\alpha, but since the Greek alphabet does not have transfinitely many letters it is better to use a more robust notation: define ordinals \varphi_\gamma(\beta) by transfinite induction as follows: let \varphi_0(\beta) = \omega^\beta and let \varphi_(\beta) be the \beta-th fixed point of \varphi_\gamma (i.e., the \beta-th ordinal such that \varphi_\gamma(\alpha)=\alpha; so for example, \varphi_1(\beta) = \varepsilon_\beta), and when \delta is a limit ordinal, define \varphi_\delta(\alpha) as the \alpha-th common fixed point of the \varphi_\gamma for all \gamma<\delta. This family of functions is known as the '' Veblen hierarchy'' (there are inessential variations in the definition, such as letting, for \delta a limit ordinal, \varphi_\delta(\alpha) be the limit of the \varphi_\gamma(\alpha) for \gamma<\delta: this essentially just shifts the indices by 1, which is harmless). \varphi_\gamma is called the \gamma^ ''
Veblen function In mathematics, the Veblen functions are a hierarchy of normal functions ( continuous strictly increasing functions from ordinals to ordinals), introduced by Oswald Veblen in . If ''φ''0 is any normal function, then for any non-zero ordinal '' ...
'' (to the base \omega). Ordering: \varphi_\alpha(\beta) < \varphi_\gamma(\delta) if and only if either (\alpha = \gamma and \beta < \delta) or (\alpha < \gamma and \beta < \varphi_\gamma(\delta)) or (\alpha > \gamma and \varphi_\alpha(\beta) < \delta).


The Feferman–Schütte ordinal and beyond

The smallest ordinal such that \varphi_\alpha(0) = \alpha is known as the Feferman–Schütte ordinal and generally written \Gamma_0. It can be described as the set of all ordinals that can be written as finite expressions, starting from zero, using only the Veblen hierarchy and addition. The Feferman–Schütte ordinal is important because, in a sense that is complicated to make precise, it is the smallest (infinite) ordinal that cannot be (" predicatively") described using smaller ordinals. It measures the strength of such systems as " arithmetical transfinite recursion". More generally, Γ''α'' enumerates the ordinals that cannot be obtained from smaller ordinals using addition and the Veblen functions. It is, of course, possible to describe ordinals beyond the Feferman–Schütte ordinal. One could continue to seek fixed points in a more and more complicated manner: enumerate the fixed points of \alpha\mapsto\Gamma_\alpha, then enumerate the fixed points of ''that'', and so on, and then look for the first ordinal ''α'' such that ''α'' is obtained in ''α'' steps of this process, and continue diagonalizing in this ''ad hoc'' manner. This leads to the definition of the "
small Small means of insignificant size Size in general is the Magnitude (mathematics), magnitude or dimensions of a thing. More specifically, ''geometrical size'' (or ''spatial size'') can refer to three geometrical measures: length, area, or ...
" and "
large Large means of great size. Large may also refer to: Mathematics * Arbitrarily large, a phrase in mathematics * Large cardinal, a property of certain transfinite numbers * Large category, a category with a proper class of objects and morphisms (o ...
" Veblen ordinals.


Impredicative ordinals

To go far beyond the Feferman–Schütte ordinal, one needs to introduce new methods. Unfortunately there is not yet any standard way to do this: every author in the subject seems to have invented their own system of notation, and it is quite hard to translate between the different systems. The first such system was introduced by Bachmann in 1950 (in an ''ad hoc'' manner), and different extensions and variations of it were described by Buchholz, Takeuti (ordinal diagrams), Feferman (θ systems), Aczel, Bridge, Schütte, and Pohlers. However most systems use the same basic idea, of constructing new countable ordinals by using the existence of certain uncountable ordinals. Here is an example of such a definition, described in much greater detail in the article on
ordinal collapsing function In mathematical logic and set theory, an ordinal collapsing function (or projection function) is a technique for defining (Ordinal notation, notations for) certain Recursive ordinal, recursive large countable ordinals, whose principle is to give n ...
: *ψ(''α'') is defined to be the smallest ordinal that cannot be constructed by starting with 0, 1, ω and Ω, and repeatedly applying addition, multiplication and exponentiation, and ψ to previously constructed ordinals (except that ψ can only be applied to arguments less than ''α'', to ensure that it is well defined). Here Ω = ω1 is the first uncountable ordinal. It is put in because otherwise the function ψ gets "stuck" at the smallest ordinal ''σ'' such that ε''σ''=''σ'': in particular ψ(''α'')=''σ'' for any ordinal α satisfying ''σ''≤''α''≤Ω. However the fact that we included Ω allows us to get past this point: ψ(Ω+1) is greater than ''σ''. The key property of Ω that we used is that it is greater than any ordinal produced by ψ. To construct still larger ordinals, we can extend the definition of ψ by throwing in more ways of constructing uncountable ordinals. There are several ways to do this, described to some extent in the article on
ordinal collapsing function In mathematical logic and set theory, an ordinal collapsing function (or projection function) is a technique for defining (Ordinal notation, notations for) certain Recursive ordinal, recursive large countable ordinals, whose principle is to give n ...
. The Bachmann–Howard ordinal (sometimes just called the Howard ordinal, ψ0(εΩ+1) with the notation above) is an important one, because it describes the proof-theoretic strength of
Kripke–Platek set theory The Kripke–Platek set theory (KP), pronounced , is an axiomatic set theory developed by Saul Kripke and Richard Platek. The theory can be thought of as roughly the predicative part of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (ZFC) and is considerably weak ...
. Indeed, the main importance of these large ordinals, and the reason to describe them, is their relation to certain formal systems as explained above. However, such powerful formal systems as full
second-order arithmetic In mathematical logic, second-order arithmetic is a collection of axiomatic systems that formalize the natural numbers and their subsets. It is an alternative to axiomatic set theory as a foundation of mathematics, foundation for much, but not all, ...
, let alone
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory In set theory, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, named after mathematicians Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, is an axiomatic system that was proposed in the early twentieth century in order to formulate a theory of sets free of paradoxes suc ...
, seem beyond reach for the moment.


Beyond even the Bachmann-Howard ordinal

Beyond this, there are multiple recursive ordinals which aren't as well known as the previous ones. The first of these is Buchholz's ordinal, defined as \psi_0(\Omega_\omega), abbreviated as just \psi(\Omega_\omega), using the previous notation. It is the proof-theoretic ordinal of \Pi_1^1-CA_0, a first-order theory of arithmetic allowing quantification over the natural numbers as well as ''sets'' of natural numbers, and ID_, the "formal theory of finitely iterated inductive definitions". Since the hydras from Buchholz's hydra game are isomorphic to Buchholz's ordinal notation, the ordinals up to this point can be expressed using hydras from the game.p.136 For example +(0(\omega)) corresponds to \psi(\Omega_\omega). Next is the Takeuti-Feferman-Buchholz ordinal, the proof-theoretic ordinal of \Pi_1^1 -CA + BI; and another subsystem of second-order arithmetic: \Pi_1^1 - comprehension + transfinite induction, and ID_\omega, the "formal theory of \omega-times iterated inductive definitions". In this notation, it is defined as \psi_0(\varepsilon_). It is the supremum of the range of Buchholz's psi functions. It was first named by David Madore. The next ordinal is mentioned in a piece of code describin
large countable ordinals and numbers in Agda
and defined by "AndrasKovacs" as \psi_0(\Omega_ \cdot \varepsilon_0). The next ordinal is mentioned in the same piece of code as earlier, and defined as \psi_0(\Omega_). It is the proof-theoretic ordinal of ID_. This next ordinal is, once again, mentioned in this same piece of code, defined as \psi_0(\Omega_), is the proof-theoretic ordinal of ID_. In general, the proof-theoretic ordinal of ID_ is equal to \psi_0(\Omega_) — note that in this certain instance, \Omega_0 represents 1, the first nonzero ordinal. Next is an unnamed ordinal, referred by David Madore as the "countable" collapse of \varepsilon_, where I is the first inaccessible (=\Pi^1_0-indescribable) cardinal. This is the proof-theoretic ordinal of Kripke-Platek set theory augmented by the recursive inaccessibility of the class of ordinals (KPi), or, on the arithmetical side, of \Delta^1_2 -comprehension + transfinite induction. Its value is equal to \psi(\varepsilon_) using an unknown function. Next is another unnamed ordinal, referred by David Madore as the "countable" collapse of \varepsilon_, where M is the first
Mahlo cardinal In mathematics, a Mahlo cardinal is a certain kind of large cardinal number. Mahlo cardinals were first described by . As with all large cardinals, none of these varieties of Mahlo cardinals can be proven to exist by ZFC (assuming ZFC is consi ...
. This is the proof-theoretic ordinal of KPM, an extension of Kripke-Platek set theory based on a Mahlo cardinal. Its value is equal to \psi(\varepsilon_) using one of Buchholz's various psi functions. Next is another unnamed ordinal, referred by David Madore as the "countable" collapse of \varepsilon_, where K is the first weakly compact (=\Pi^1_1-indescribable) cardinal. This is the proof-theoretic ordinal of Kripke-Platek set theory + Π3 - Ref. Its value is equal to \Psi(\varepsilon_) using Rathjen's Psi function. Next is another unnamed ordinal, referred by David Madore as the "countable" collapse of \varepsilon_, where \Xi is the first \Pi^2_0-indescribable cardinal. This is the proof-theoretic ordinal of Kripke-Platek set theory + Πω-Ref. Its value is equal to \Psi^_X using Stegert's Psi function, where X = (\omega^+; P_0; \epsilon, \epsilon, 0). Next is the last unnamed ordinal, referred by David Madore as the proof-theoretic ordinal of Stability. This is the proof-theoretic ordinal of Stability, an extension of Kripke-Platek set theory. Its value is equal to \Psi^_X using Stegert's Psi function, where X = (\omega^+; P_0; \epsilon, \epsilon, 0). Next is a group of ordinals which not that much are known about, but are still fairly significant (in ascending order): * The proof-theoretic ordinal of
second-order arithmetic In mathematical logic, second-order arithmetic is a collection of axiomatic systems that formalize the natural numbers and their subsets. It is an alternative to axiomatic set theory as a foundation of mathematics, foundation for much, but not all, ...
. * A possible limit of Taranovsky's C ordinal notation. (Conjectural, assuming well-foundedness of the notation system) * The proof-theoretic ordinal of ZFC.


"Unrecursable" recursive ordinals

By dropping the requirement of having a concrete description, even larger recursive countable ordinals can be obtained as the ordinals measuring the strengths of various strong theories; roughly speaking, these ordinals are the smallest order types of "natural" ordinal notations that the theories cannot prove are well ordered. By taking stronger and stronger theories such as
second-order arithmetic In mathematical logic, second-order arithmetic is a collection of axiomatic systems that formalize the natural numbers and their subsets. It is an alternative to axiomatic set theory as a foundation of mathematics, foundation for much, but not all, ...
, Zermelo set theory,
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory In set theory, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, named after mathematicians Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, is an axiomatic system that was proposed in the early twentieth century in order to formulate a theory of sets free of paradoxes suc ...
, or Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with various
large cardinal In the mathematical field of set theory, a large cardinal property is a certain kind of property of transfinite cardinal numbers. Cardinals with such properties are, as the name suggests, generally very "large" (for example, bigger than the least ...
axioms, one gets some extremely large recursive ordinals. (Strictly speaking it is not known that all of these really are ordinals: by construction, the ordinal strength of a theory can only be proved to be an ordinal from an even stronger theory. So for the large cardinal axioms this becomes quite unclear.)


Beyond recursive ordinals


The Church–Kleene ordinal

The supremum of the set of
recursive ordinal In mathematics, specifically computability and set theory, an ordinal \alpha is said to be computable or recursive if there is a computable well-ordering of a computable subset of the natural numbers having the order type \alpha. It is easy to ch ...
s is the smallest ordinal that ''cannot'' be described in a recursive way. (It is not the
order type In mathematics, especially in set theory, two ordered sets and are said to have the same order type if they are order isomorphic, that is, if there exists a bijection (each element pairs with exactly one in the other set) f\colon X \to Y su ...
of any recursive well-ordering of the integers.) That ordinal is a countable ordinal called the Church–Kleene ordinal, \omega_1^. Thus, \omega_1^ is the smallest non-recursive ordinal, and there is no hope of precisely "describing" any ordinals from this point on—we can only ''define'' them. But it is still far less than the first uncountable ordinal, \omega_1. However, as its symbol suggests, it behaves in many ways rather like \omega_1. For instance, one can define ordinal collapsing functions using \omega_1^ instead of \omega_1.


Admissible ordinals

The Church–Kleene ordinal is again related to
Kripke–Platek set theory The Kripke–Platek set theory (KP), pronounced , is an axiomatic set theory developed by Saul Kripke and Richard Platek. The theory can be thought of as roughly the predicative part of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory (ZFC) and is considerably weak ...
, but now in a different way: whereas the Bachmann–Howard ordinal (described above) was the smallest ordinal for which KP does not prove transfinite induction, the Church–Kleene ordinal is the smallest ''α'' such that the construction of the Gödel universe, ''L'', up to stage ''α'', yields a model L_\alpha of KP. Such ordinals are called ''admissible'', thus \omega_1^ is the smallest admissible ordinal (beyond ω in case the
axiom of infinity In axiomatic set theory and the branches of mathematics and philosophy that use it, the axiom of infinity is one of the axioms of Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory. It guarantees the existence of at least one infinite set, namely a set containing ...
is not included in KP). By a theorem of Friedman, Jensen, and Sacks, the countable admissible ordinals are exactly those constructed in a manner similar to the Church–Kleene ordinal but for Turing machines with oracles. One sometimes writes \omega_\alpha^ for the \alpha-th ordinal that is either admissible or a limit of smaller admissibles.


Beyond admissible ordinals

\omega_\omega^ is the smallest limit of admissible ordinals (mentioned later), yet the ordinal itself is not admissible. It is also the smallest \alpha such that L_\alpha \cap P(\omega) is a model of \Pi^1_1-comprehension. An ordinal that is both admissible and a limit of admissibles, or equivalently such that \alpha is the \alpha-th admissible ordinal, is called ''recursively inaccessible'', and the least recursively inaccessible may be denoted \omega_1^. An ordinal that is both recursively inaccessible and a limit of recursively inaccessibles is called ''recursively hyperinaccessible''. There exists a theory of large ordinals in this manner that is highly parallel to that of (small) large cardinals. For example, we can define ''recursively Mahlo ordinals'': these are the \alpha such that every \alpha-recursive closed unbounded subset of \alpha contains an admissible ordinal (a recursive analog of the definition of a
Mahlo cardinal In mathematics, a Mahlo cardinal is a certain kind of large cardinal number. Mahlo cardinals were first described by . As with all large cardinals, none of these varieties of Mahlo cardinals can be proven to exist by ZFC (assuming ZFC is consi ...
). The 1-section of Harrington's functional ^2S^\# is equal to L_\rho\cap\mathcal P(\omega), where \rho is the least recursively Mahlo ordinal.A. Kechris, "Spector Second-order Classes and Reflection". Appearing in ''Generalized Recursion Theory II: Proceedings of the 1977 Oslo Symposium'', Studies in Logic and the Foundation of Mathematics vol. 94 (1978), pp.147--183p.171 But note that we are still talking about possibly countable ordinals here. (While the existence of inaccessible or Mahlo cardinals cannot be proved in
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory In set theory, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, named after mathematicians Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, is an axiomatic system that was proposed in the early twentieth century in order to formulate a theory of sets free of paradoxes suc ...
, that of recursively inaccessible or recursively Mahlo ordinals is a theorem of ZFC: in fact, any regular cardinal is recursively Mahlo and more, but even if we limit ourselves to countable ordinals, ZFC proves the existence of recursively Mahlo ordinals. They are, however, beyond the reach of Kripke–Platek set theory.)


Reflection

For a set of formulae \Gamma, a limit ordinal \alpha is called ''\Gamma-reflecting'' if the rank L_\alpha satisfies a certain reflection property for each \Gamma-formula \phi. These ordinals appear in ordinal analysis of theories such as ''KP+Π3-ref'', a theory augmenting Kripke-Platek set theory by a \Pi_3-reflection schema. They can also be considered "recursive analogues" of some uncountable cardinals such as weakly compact cardinals and indescribable cardinals. For example, an ordinal which \Pi_3-reflecting is called ''recursively weakly compact''. For finite n, the least \Pi_n-reflecting ordinal is also the supremum of the closure ordinals of monotonic inductive definitions whose graphs are Πm+10. In particular, \Pi_3-reflecting ordinals also have a characterization using higher-type functionals on ordinal functions, lending them the name ''2-admissible ordinals''. An unpublished paper by
Solomon Feferman Solomon Feferman (December 13, 1928July 26, 2016) was an American philosopher and mathematician who worked in mathematical logic. In addition to his prolific technical work in proof theory, computability theory, and set theory, he was known for h ...
supplies, for each finite n, a similar property corresponding to \Pi_n-reflection.


Nonprojectibility

An admissible ordinal \alpha is called ''nonprojectible'' if there is no total \alpha-recursive
injective function In mathematics, an injective function (also known as injection, or one-to-one function ) is a function that maps distinct elements of its domain to distinct elements of its codomain; that is, implies (equivalently by contraposition, impl ...
mapping \alpha into a smaller ordinal. (This is trivially true for regular cardinals; however, we are mainly interested in countable ordinals.) Being nonprojectible is a much stronger condition than being admissible, recursively inaccessible, or even recursively Mahlo. By Jensen's method of projecta, this statement is equivalent to the statement that the Gödel universe, ''L'', up to stage α, yields a model L_\alpha of KP + \Sigma_1-separation. However, \Sigma_1-separation on its own (not in the presence of V=L) is not a strong enough axiom schema to imply nonprojectibility, in fact there are transitive models of KP+\Sigma_1-separation of any countable admissible height >\omega. Nonprojectible ordinals are tied to Jensen's work on projecta. The least ordinals that are nonprojectible relative to a given set are tied to Harrington's construction of the smallest reflecting Spector 2-class.p.174


"Unprovable" ordinals

We can imagine even larger ordinals that are still countable. For example, if ZFC has a transitive model (a hypothesis stronger than the mere hypothesis of consistency, and implied by the existence of an inaccessible cardinal), then there exists a countable \alpha such that L_\alpha is a model of ZFC. Such ordinals are beyond the strength of ZFC in the sense that it cannot (by construction) prove their existence. If T is a recursively enumerable set theory consistent with ''V''=''L'', then the least \alpha such that (L_\alpha,\in)\vDash T is less than the least stable ordinal, which follows.


Stable ordinals

Even larger countable ordinals, called the ''stable ordinals'', can be defined by indescribability conditions or as those \alpha such that L_\alpha is a Σ1-elementary submodel of ''L''; the existence of these ordinals can be proved in ZFC, and they are closely related to the nonprojectible ordinals from a model-theoretic perspective. For countable \alpha, stability of \alpha is equivalent to L_\alpha\prec_L_. The least stable level of L has some definability-related properties. Letting \sigma be least such that L_\sigma\prec_1 L: * A set has a \Sigma_1 definition in L iff it is a member of L_\sigma.p.6 * A set x\subseteq\mathbb N is \Delta^1_2 iff it is a member of L_\sigma.p.6 * A set x\subseteq\mathbb N is \Sigma^1_2 iff it is \sigma-recursively enumerable, in the terminology of alpha recursion theory.p.6


Variants of stable ordinals

These are weakened variants of stable ordinals. There are ordinals with these properties smaller than the aforementioned least nonprojectible ordinal, for example an ordinal is (+1)-stable iff it is \Pi_n^0-reflecting for all natural n. * A countable ordinal \alpha is called (+\beta)-stable
iff In logic and related fields such as mathematics and philosophy, "if and only if" (often shortened as "iff") is paraphrased by the biconditional, a logical connective between statements. The biconditional is true in two cases, where either both ...
L_\alpha \prec_ L_ * A countable ordinal \alpha is called (^+)-stable
iff In logic and related fields such as mathematics and philosophy, "if and only if" (often shortened as "iff") is paraphrased by the biconditional, a logical connective between statements. The biconditional is true in two cases, where either both ...
L_\alpha \prec_ L_, where \beta is the least admissible ordinal larger than \alpha. * A countable ordinal \alpha is called (^)-stable
iff In logic and related fields such as mathematics and philosophy, "if and only if" (often shortened as "iff") is paraphrased by the biconditional, a logical connective between statements. The biconditional is true in two cases, where either both ...
L_\alpha \prec_ L_, where \beta is the least admissible ordinal larger than an admissible ordinal larger than \alpha. * A countable ordinal \alpha is called inaccessibly-stable
iff In logic and related fields such as mathematics and philosophy, "if and only if" (often shortened as "iff") is paraphrased by the biconditional, a logical connective between statements. The biconditional is true in two cases, where either both ...
L_\alpha \prec_ L_, where \beta is the least recursively inaccessible ordinal larger than \alpha. * A countable ordinal \alpha is called Mahlo-stable
iff In logic and related fields such as mathematics and philosophy, "if and only if" (often shortened as "iff") is paraphrased by the biconditional, a logical connective between statements. The biconditional is true in two cases, where either both ...
L_\alpha \prec_ L_, where \beta is the least recursively Mahlo ordinal larger than \alpha. * A countable ordinal \alpha is called doubly (+1)-stable
iff In logic and related fields such as mathematics and philosophy, "if and only if" (often shortened as "iff") is paraphrased by the biconditional, a logical connective between statements. The biconditional is true in two cases, where either both ...
there is a (+1)-stable ordinal \beta > \alpha such that L_\alpha \prec_ L_. Stronger weakenings of stability have appeared in proof-theoretic publications, including analysis of subsystems of
second-order arithmetic In mathematical logic, second-order arithmetic is a collection of axiomatic systems that formalize the natural numbers and their subsets. It is an alternative to axiomatic set theory as a foundation of mathematics, foundation for much, but not all, ...
.


A pseudo-well-ordering

Within the scheme of notations of Kleene some represent ordinals and some do not. One can define a recursive total ordering that is a subset of the Kleene notations and has an initial segment which is well-ordered with order-type \omega_1^. Every recursively enumerable (or even hyperarithmetic) nonempty subset of this total ordering has a least element. So it resembles a well-ordering in some respects. For example, one can define the arithmetic operations on it. Yet it is not possible to effectively determine exactly where the initial well-ordered part ends and the part lacking a least element begins. For an example of a recursive pseudo-well-ordering, let S be ATR0 or another recursively axiomatizable theory that has an ω-model but no hyperarithmetical ω-models, and (if needed) conservatively extend S with Skolem functions. Let T be the tree of (essentially) finite partial ω-models of S: A sequence of natural numbers x_1,x_2,...,x_n is in T iff S plus ∃m φ(m) ⇒ φ(x⌈φ⌉) (for the first n formulas φ with one numeric free variable; ⌈φ⌉ is the Gödel number) has no inconsistency proof shorter than n. Then the Kleene–Brouwer order of T is a recursive pseudowellordering. Any such construction must have order type \omega_1^\times (1+\eta)+\rho, where \eta is the order type of (\mathbb Q,<), and \rho is a recursive ordinal. W. Chan
The countable admissible ordinal equivalence relation
(2017), p.1233. Accessed 28 December 2022.


References

Most books describing large countable ordinals are on proof theory, and unfortunately tend to be out of print.


On recursive ordinals

* Wolfram Pohlers, ''Proof theory'', Springer 1989 (for Veblen hierarchy and some impredicative ordinals). This is probably the most readable book on large countable ordinals (which is not saying much). * Gaisi Takeuti, ''Proof theory'', 2nd edition 1987 (for ordinal diagrams) * Kurt Schütte, ''Proof theory'', Springer 1977 (for Veblen hierarchy and some impredicative ordinals) * Craig Smorynski, ''The varieties of arboreal experience'' Math. Intelligencer 4 (1982), no. 4, 182–189; contains an informal description of the Veblen hierarchy. * Hartley Rogers Jr., ''Theory of Recursive Functions and Effective Computability'' McGraw-Hill (1967) (describes recursive ordinals and the Church–Kleene ordinal) * Larry W. Miller, ''Normal Functions and Constructive Ordinal Notations'', '' The Journal of Symbolic Logic'', volume 41, number 2, June 1976, pages 439 to 459, , * Hilbert Levitz,
Transfinite Ordinals and Their Notations: For The Uninitiated
', expository article (8 pages, in
PostScript PostScript (PS) is a page description language and dynamically typed, stack-based programming language. It is most commonly used in the electronic publishing and desktop publishing realm, but as a Turing complete programming language, it c ...
) * Herman Ruge Jervell
Truth and provability
manuscript in progress.


Beyond recursive ordinals

* *


Both recursive and nonrecursive ordinals

* Michael Rathjen, "The realm of ordinal analysis." in S. B. Cooper and J. Truss (eds.): ''Sets and Proofs''. (Cambridge University Press, 1999) 219–279. A
Postscript file


Inline references

{{countable ordinals Ordinal numbers Proof theory