Inadmissible Inference Rule
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In logic, a
rule of inference In the philosophy of logic, a rule of inference, inference rule or transformation rule is a logical form consisting of a function which takes premises, analyzes their syntax, and returns a conclusion (or conclusions). For example, the rule of in ...
is admissible in a formal system if the set of theorems of the system does not change when that rule is added to the existing rules of the system. In other words, every
formula In science, a formula is a concise way of expressing information symbolically, as in a mathematical formula or a ''chemical formula''. The informal use of the term ''formula'' in science refers to the general construct of a relationship betwee ...
that can be
derived Derive may refer to: * Derive (computer algebra system), a commercial system made by Texas Instruments * ''Dérive'' (magazine), an Austrian science magazine on urbanism *Dérive, a psychogeographical concept See also * *Derivation (disambiguatio ...
using that rule is already derivable without that rule, so, in a sense, it is redundant. The concept of an admissible rule was introduced by Paul Lorenzen (1955).


Definitions

Admissibility has been systematically studied only in the case of structural (i.e.
substitution Substitution may refer to: Arts and media *Chord substitution, in music, swapping one chord for a related one within a chord progression * Substitution (poetry), a variation in poetic scansion * "Substitution" (song), a 2009 song by Silversun Pi ...
-closed) rules in
propositional In logic and linguistics, a proposition is the meaning of a declarative sentence. In philosophy, " meaning" is understood to be a non-linguistic entity which is shared by all sentences with the same meaning. Equivalently, a proposition is the no ...
non-classical logics, which we will describe next. Let a set of basic propositional connectives be fixed (for instance, \ in the case of
superintuitionistic logic In mathematical logic, a superintuitionistic logic is a propositional logic extending intuitionistic logic. Classical logic is the strongest consistent superintuitionistic logic; thus, consistent superintuitionistic logics are called intermediate l ...
s, or \ in the case of monomodal logics).
Well-formed formulas In mathematical logic, propositional logic and predicate logic, a well-formed formula, abbreviated WFF or wff, often simply formula, is a finite sequence of symbols from a given alphabet that is part of a formal language. A formal language can b ...
are built freely using these connectives from a
countably infinite In mathematics, a set is countable if either it is finite or it can be made in one to one correspondence with the set of natural numbers. Equivalently, a set is ''countable'' if there exists an injective function from it into the natural numbers; ...
set of propositional variables ''p''0, ''p''1, .... A
substitution Substitution may refer to: Arts and media *Chord substitution, in music, swapping one chord for a related one within a chord progression * Substitution (poetry), a variation in poetic scansion * "Substitution" (song), a 2009 song by Silversun Pi ...
''σ'' is a function from formulas to formulas that commutes with applications of the connectives, i.e., :\sigma f(A_1,\dots,A_n)=f(\sigma A_1,\dots,\sigma A_n) for every connective ''f'', and formulas ''A''1, ... , ''A''''n''. (We may also apply substitutions to sets Γ of formulas, making ) A Tarski-style
consequence relation Logical consequence (also entailment) is a fundamental concept in logic, which describes the relationship between statements that hold true when one statement logically ''follows from'' one or more statements. A valid logical argument is on ...
is a relation \vdash between sets of formulas, and formulas, such that for all formulas ''A'', ''B'', and sets of formulas Γ, Δ. A consequence relation such that for all substitutions ''σ'' is called structural. (Note that the term "structural" as used here and below is unrelated to the notion of
structural rule In proof theory, a structural rule is an inference rule that does not refer to any logical connective, but instead operates on the judgment or sequents directly. Structural rules often mimic intended meta-theoretic properties of the logic. Logics ...
s in sequent calculi.) A structural consequence relation is called a propositional logic. A formula ''A'' is a theorem of a logic \vdash if \varnothing\vdash A. For example, we identify a superintuitionistic logic ''L'' with its standard consequence relation \vdash_L generated by
modus ponens In propositional logic, ''modus ponens'' (; MP), also known as ''modus ponendo ponens'' (Latin for "method of putting by placing") or implication elimination or affirming the antecedent, is a deductive argument form and rule of inference. ...
and axioms, and we identify a normal modal logic with its global consequence relation \vdash_L generated by modus ponens, necessitation, and (as axioms) the theorems of the logic. A structural inference rule (or just rule for short) is given by a pair (Γ, ''B''), usually written as :\fracB\qquad\text\qquad A_1,\dots,A_n/B, where Γ =  is a finite set of formulas, and ''B'' is a formula. An instance of the rule is :\sigma A_1,\dots,\sigma A_n/\sigma B for a substitution ''σ''. The rule Γ/''B'' is derivable in \vdash, if \Gamma\vdash B. It is admissible if for every instance of the rule, ''σB'' is a theorem whenever all formulas from ''σ''Γ are theorems. In other words, a rule is admissible if it, when added to the logic, does not lead to new theorems. We also write \Gamma\mathrel B if Γ/''B'' is admissible. (Note that \phantom\! is a structural consequence relation on its own.) Every derivable rule is admissible, but not vice versa in general. A logic is structurally complete if every admissible rule is derivable, i.e., =. In logics with a well-behaved conjunction connective (such as superintuitionistic or modal logics), a rule A_1,\dots,A_n/B is equivalent to A_1\land\dots\land A_n/B with respect to admissibility and derivability. It is therefore customary to only deal with unary rules ''A''/''B''.


Examples

* Classical propositional calculus (''CPC'') is structurally complete. Indeed, assume that ''A''/''B'' is a non-derivable rule, and fix an assignment ''v'' such that ''v''(''A'') = 1, and ''v''(''B'') = 0. Define a substitution ''σ'' such that for every variable ''p'', ''σp'' = \top if ''v''(''p'') = 1, and ''σp'' = \bot if ''v''(''p'') = 0. Then ''σA'' is a theorem, but ''σB'' is not (in fact, ¬''σB'' is a theorem). Thus the rule ''A''/''B'' is not admissible either. (The same argument applies to any multi-valued logic ''L'' complete with respect to a logical matrix all of whose elements have a name in the language of ''L''.) *The
Kreisel Kreisel (German for gyro) is the name of a turn found on some bobsleigh, luge, and skeleton tracks around the world. It is a single continuous curve which turns far enough around that the track must go under itself on the exit of the curve. Ther ...
Putnam rule (also known as Harrop's rule, or independence of premise rule) ::(\mathit)\qquad\frac :is admissible in the
intuitionistic propositional calculus Intuitionistic logic, sometimes more generally called constructive logic, refers to systems of symbolic logic that differ from the systems used for classical logic by more closely mirroring the notion of constructive proof. In particular, systems ...
(''IPC''). In fact, it is admissible in every superintuitionistic logic. On the other hand, the formula ::(\neg p\to q\lor r)\to ((\neg p\to q)\lor(\neg p\to r)) :is not an intuitionistic theorem; hence ''KPR'' is not derivable in ''IPC''. In particular, ''IPC'' is not structurally complete. *The rule ::\fracp :is admissible in many modal logics, such as ''K'', ''D'', ''K''4, ''S''4, ''GL'' (see this table for names of modal logics). It is derivable in ''S''4, but it is not derivable in ''K'', ''D'', ''K''4, or ''GL''. *The rule ::\frac\bot :is admissible in every normal modal logic. It is derivable in ''GL'' and ''S''4.1, but it is not derivable in ''K'', ''D'', ''K''4, ''S''4, or ''S''5. * Löb's rule ::(\mathit)\qquad\fracp :is admissible (but not derivable) in the basic modal logic ''K'', and it is derivable in ''GL''. However, ''LR'' is not admissible in ''K''4. In particular, it is ''not'' true in general that a rule admissible in a logic ''L'' must be admissible in its extensions. *The
Gödel–Dummett logic In mathematical logic, a superintuitionistic logic is a propositional logic extending intuitionistic logic. Classical logic is the strongest consistent superintuitionistic logic; thus, consistent superintuitionistic logics are called intermediate ...
(''LC''), and the modal logic ''Grz''.3 are structurally complete.Rybakov (1997), Thms. 5.4.4, 5.4.8 The product fuzzy logic is also structurally complete.


Decidability and reduced rules

The basic question about admissible rules of a given logic is whether the set of all admissible rules is decidable. Note that the problem is nontrivial even if the logic itself (i.e., its set of theorems) is decidable: the definition of admissibility of a rule ''A''/''B'' involves an unbounded
universal quantifier In mathematical logic, a universal quantification is a type of quantifier, a logical constant which is interpreted as "given any" or "for all". It expresses that a predicate can be satisfied by every member of a domain of discourse. In other w ...
over all propositional substitutions. Hence ''a priori'' we only know that admissibility of rule in a decidable logic is \Pi^0_1 (i.e., its complement is recursively enumerable). For instance, it is known that admissibility in the bimodal logics ''K''''u'' and ''K''4''u'' (the extensions of ''K'' or ''K''4 with the universal modality) is undecidable. Remarkably, decidability of admissibility in the basic modal logic ''K'' is a major open problem. Nevertheless, admissibility of rules is known to be decidable in many modal and superintuitionistic logics. The first decision procedures for admissible rules in basic transitive modal logics were constructed by Rybakov, using the reduced form of rules. A modal rule in variables ''p''0, ... , ''p''''k'' is called reduced if it has the form :\frac, where each \neg_^u is either blank, or
negation In logic, negation, also called the logical complement, is an operation that takes a proposition P to another proposition "not P", written \neg P, \mathord P or \overline. It is interpreted intuitively as being true when P is false, and false ...
\neg. For each rule ''r'', we can effectively construct a reduced rule ''s'' (called the reduced form of ''r'') such that any logic admits (or derives) ''r'' if and only if it admits (or derives) ''s'', by introducing
extension variable Extension, extend or extended may refer to: Mathematics Logic or set theory * Axiom of extensionality * Extensible cardinal * Extension (model theory) * Extension (predicate logic), the set of tuples of values that satisfy the predicate * Ex ...
s for all subformulas in ''A'', and expressing the result in the full disjunctive normal form. It is thus sufficient to construct a decision algorithm for admissibility of reduced rules. Let \textstyle\bigvee_^n\varphi_i/p_0 be a reduced rule as above. We identify every conjunction \varphi_i with the set \ of its conjuncts. For any subset ''W'' of the set \ of all conjunctions, let us define a
Kripke model Kripke semantics (also known as relational semantics or frame semantics, and often confused with possible world semantics) is a formal semantics for non-classical logic systems created in the late 1950s and early 1960s by Saul Kripke and André Jo ...
M=\langle W,R,\rangle by :\varphi_i\Vdash p_j\iff p_j\in\varphi_i, :\varphi_i\,R\,\varphi_\iff\forall j\le k\,(\Box p_j\in\varphi_i\Rightarrow\\subseteq\varphi_). Then the following provides an algorithmic criterion for admissibility in ''K''4: Theorem. The rule \textstyle\bigvee_^n\varphi_i/p_0 is ''not'' admissible in ''K''4 if and only if there exists a set W\subseteq\ such that #\varphi_i\nVdash p_0 for some i\le n, #\varphi_i\Vdash\varphi_i for every i\le n, #for every subset ''D'' of ''W'' there exist elements \alpha,\beta\in W such that the equivalences ::\alpha\Vdash\Box p_j if and only if \varphi\Vdash p_j\land\Box p_j for every \varphi\in D ::\alpha\Vdash\Box p_j if and only if \alpha\Vdash p_j and \varphi\Vdash p_j\land\Box p_j for every \varphi\in D :hold for all ''j''. Similar criteria can be found for the logics ''S''4, ''GL'', and ''Grz''. Furthermore, admissibility in intuitionistic logic can be reduced to admissibility in ''Grz'' using the
Gödel–McKinsey–Tarski translation In logic, a modal companion of a superintuitionistic (intermediate) logic ''L'' is a normal modal logic that interprets ''L'' by a certain canonical translation, described below. Modal companions share various properties of the original intermedi ...
: :A\,, \!\!\!\sim_B if and only if T(A)\,, \!\!\!\sim_T(B). Rybakov (1997) developed much more sophisticated techniques for showing decidability of admissibility, which apply to a robust (infinite) class of transitive (i.e., extending ''K''4 or ''IPC'') modal and superintuitionistic logics, including e.g. ''S''4.1, ''S''4.2, ''S''4.3, ''KC'', ''T''''k'' (as well as the above-mentioned logics ''IPC'', ''K''4, ''S''4, ''GL'', ''Grz''). Despite being decidable, the admissibility problem has relatively high
computational complexity In computer science, the computational complexity or simply complexity of an algorithm is the amount of resources required to run it. Particular focus is given to computation time (generally measured by the number of needed elementary operations) ...
, even in simple logics: admissibility of rules in the basic transitive logics ''IPC'', ''K''4, ''S''4, ''GL'', ''Grz'' is coNEXP-complete. This should be contrasted with the derivability problem (for rules or formulas) in these logics, which is PSPACE-complete.


Projectivity and unification

Admissibility in propositional logics is closely related to unification in the
equational theory Universal algebra (sometimes called general algebra) is the field of mathematics that studies algebraic structures themselves, not examples ("models") of algebraic structures. For instance, rather than take particular groups as the object of study, ...
of modal or Heyting algebras. The connection was developed by Ghilardi (1999, 2000). In the logical setup, a unifier of a formula ''A'' in the language of a logic ''L'' (an ''L''-unifier for short) is a substitution ''σ'' such that ''σA'' is a theorem of ''L''. (Using this notion, we can rephrase admissibility of a rule ''A''/''B'' in ''L'' as "every ''L''-unifier of ''A'' is an ''L''-unifier of ''B''".) An ''L''-unifier ''σ'' is less general than an ''L''-unifier ''τ'', written as ''σ'' ≤ ''τ'', if there exists a substitution ''υ'' such that :\vdash_L\sigma p\leftrightarrow \upsilon\tau p for every variable ''p''. A complete set of unifiers of a formula ''A'' is a set ''S'' of ''L''-unifiers of ''A'' such that every ''L''-unifier of ''A'' is less general than some unifier from ''S''. A most general unifier (MGU) of ''A'' is a unifier ''σ'' such that is a complete set of unifiers of ''A''. It follows that if ''S'' is a complete set of unifiers of ''A'', then a rule ''A''/''B'' is ''L''-admissible if and only if every ''σ'' in ''S'' is an ''L''-unifier of ''B''. Thus we can characterize admissible rules if we can find well-behaved complete sets of unifiers. An important class of formulas that have a most general unifier are the projective formulas: these are formulas ''A'' such that there exists a unifier ''σ'' of ''A'' such that :A\vdash_L B\leftrightarrow\sigma B for every formula ''B''. Note that ''σ'' is an MGU of ''A''. In transitive modal and superintuitionistic logics with the
finite model property In mathematical logic, a logic L has the finite model property (fmp for short) if any non-theorem of L is falsified by some ''finite'' model of L. Another way of putting this is to say that L has the fmp if for every formula ''A'' of L, ''A'' is an ...
, one can characterize projective formulas semantically as those whose set of finite ''L''-models has the extension property: if ''M'' is a finite Kripke ''L''-model with a root ''r'' whose cluster is a singleton, and the formula ''A'' holds at all points of ''M'' except for ''r'', then we can change the valuation of variables in ''r'' so as to make ''A'' true at ''r'' as well. Moreover, the proof provides an explicit construction of an MGU for a given projective formula ''A''. In the basic transitive logics ''IPC'', ''K''4, ''S''4, ''GL'', ''Grz'' (and more generally in any transitive logic with the finite model property whose set of finite frame satisfies another kind of extension property), we can effectively construct for any formula ''A'' its projective approximation Π(''A''): a finite set of projective formulas such that #P\vdash_L A for every P\in\Pi(A), #every unifier of ''A'' is a unifier of a formula from Π(''A''). It follows that the set of MGUs of elements of Π(''A'') is a complete set of unifiers of ''A''. Furthermore, if ''P'' is a projective formula, then :P\,, \!\!\!\sim_L B if and only if P\vdash_L B for any formula ''B''. Thus we obtain the following effective characterization of admissible rules: :A\,, \!\!\!\sim_L B if and only if \forall P\in\Pi(A)\,(P\vdash_L B).


Bases of admissible rules

Let ''L'' be a logic. A set ''R'' of ''L''-admissible rules is called a basis of admissible rules, if every admissible rule Γ/''B'' can be derived from ''R'' and the derivable rules of ''L'', using substitution, composition, and weakening. In other words, ''R'' is a basis if and only if \phantom\! is the smallest structural consequence relation that includes \vdash_L and ''R''. Notice that decidability of admissible rules of a decidable logic is equivalent to the existence of recursive (or recursively enumerable) bases: on the one hand, the set of ''all'' admissible rules is a recursive basis if admissibility is decidable. On the other hand, the set of admissible rules is always co-recursively enumerable, and if we further have a recursively enumerable basis, set of admissible rules is also recursively enumerable; hence it is decidable. (In other words, we can decide admissibility of ''A''/''B'' by the following algorithm: we start in parallel two exhaustive searches, one for a substitution ''σ'' that unifies ''A'' but not ''B'', and one for a derivation of ''A''/''B'' from ''R'' and \vdash_L. One of the searches has to eventually come up with an answer.) Apart from decidability, explicit bases of admissible rules are useful for some applications, e.g. in
proof complexity In logic and theoretical computer science, and specifically proof theory and computational complexity theory, proof complexity is the field aiming to understand and analyse the computational resources that are required to prove or refute statements. ...
. For a given logic, we can ask whether it has a recursive or finite basis of admissible rules, and to provide an explicit basis. If a logic has no finite basis, it can nevertheless have an independent basis: a basis ''R'' such that no proper subset of ''R'' is a basis. In general, very little can be said about existence of bases with desirable properties. For example, while
tabular logic Table may refer to: * Table (furniture), a piece of furniture with a flat surface and one or more legs * Table (landform), a flat area of land * Table (information), a data arrangement with rows and columns * Table (database), how the table data ...
s are generally well-behaved, and always finitely axiomatizable, there exist tabular modal logics without a finite or independent basis of rules. Finite bases are relatively rare: even the basic transitive logics ''IPC'', ''K''4, ''S''4, ''GL'', ''Grz'' do not have a finite basis of admissible rules, though they have independent bases.


Examples of bases

*The empty set is a basis of ''L''-admissible rules if and only if ''L'' is structurally complete. *Every extension of the modal logic ''S''4.3 (including, notably, ''S''5) has a finite basis consisting of the single rule ::\frac\bot. *'s rules ::\frac,\qquad n\ge 1 :are a basis of admissible rules in ''IPC'' or ''KC''. *The rules ::\frac,\qquad n\ge0 :are a basis of admissible rules of ''GL''. (Note that the empty disjunction is defined as \bot.) *The rules ::\frac,\qquad n\ge0 :are a basis of admissible rules of ''S''4 or ''Grz''.


Semantics for admissible rules

A rule Γ/''B'' is valid in a modal or intuitionistic Kripke frame F=\langle W,R\rangle, if the following is true for every valuation \Vdash in ''F'': :if for all A\in\Gamma \forall x\in W\,(x\Vdash A), then \forall x\in W\,(x\Vdash B). (The definition readily generalizes to general frames, if needed.) Let ''X'' be a subset of ''W'', and ''t'' a point in ''W''. We say that ''t'' is *a reflexive tight predecessor of ''X'', if for every ''y'' in ''W'': ''t R y'' if and only if ''t'' = ''y'' or for some ''x'' in ''X'': ''x'' = ''y'' or ''x R y'' , *an irreflexive tight predecessor of ''X'', if for every ''y'' in ''W'': ''t R y'' if and only if for some ''x'' in ''X'': ''x'' = ''y'' or ''x R y'' . We say that a frame ''F'' has reflexive (irreflexive) tight predecessors, if for every ''finite'' subset ''X'' of ''W'', there exists a reflexive (irreflexive) tight predecessor of ''X'' in ''W''. We have: *a rule is admissible in ''IPC'' if and only if it is valid in all intuitionistic frames that have reflexive tight predecessors, *a rule is admissible in ''K''4 if and only if it is valid in all transitive frames that have reflexive and irreflexive tight predecessors, *a rule is admissible in ''S''4 if and only if it is valid in all transitive reflexive frames that have reflexive tight predecessors, *a rule is admissible in ''GL'' if and only if it is valid in all transitive converse
well-founded In mathematics, a binary relation ''R'' is called well-founded (or wellfounded) on a class ''X'' if every non-empty subset ''S'' ⊆ ''X'' has a minimal element with respect to ''R'', that is, an element ''m'' not related by ''s& ...
frames that have irreflexive tight predecessors. Note that apart from a few trivial cases, frames with tight predecessors must be infinite. Hence admissible rules in basic transitive logics do not enjoy the finite model property.


Structural completeness

While a general classification of structurally complete logics is not an easy task, we have a good understanding of some special cases. Intuitionistic logic itself is not structurally complete, but its ''fragments'' may behave differently. Namely, any disjunction-free rule or implication-free rule admissible in a superintuitionistic logic is derivable. On the other hand, the Mints rule :\frac is admissible in intuitionistic logic but not derivable, and contains only implications and disjunctions. We know the ''maximal'' structurally incomplete transitive logics. A logic is called hereditarily structurally complete, if any extension is structurally complete. For example, classical logic, as well as the logics ''LC'' and ''Grz''.3 mentioned above, are hereditarily structurally complete. A complete description of hereditarily structurally complete superintuitionistic and transitive modal logics was given respectively by Citkin and Rybakov. Namely, a superintuitionistic logic is hereditarily structurally complete if and only if it is not valid in any of the five Kripke frames :: Similarly, an extension of ''K''4 is hereditarily structurally complete if and only if it is not valid in any of certain twenty Kripke frames (including the five intuitionistic frames above). There exist structurally complete logics that are not hereditarily structurally complete: for example, Medvedev's logic is structurally complete, but it is included in the structurally incomplete logic ''KC''.


Variants

A rule with parameters is a rule of the form :\frac, whose variables are divided into the "regular" variables ''p''''i'', and the parameters ''s''''i''. The rule is ''L''-admissible if every ''L''-unifier ''σ'' of ''A'' such that ''σs''''i'' = ''s''''i'' for each ''i'' is also a unifier of ''B''. The basic decidability results for admissible rules also carry to rules with parameters. A multiple-conclusion rule is a pair (Γ,Δ) of two finite sets of formulas, written as :\frac\qquad\text\qquad A_1,\dots,A_n/B_1,\dots,B_m. Such a rule is admissible if every unifier of Γ is also a unifier of some formula from Δ. For example, a logic ''L'' is consistent iff it admits the rule :\frac, and a superintuitionistic logic has the
disjunction property In mathematical logic, the disjunction and existence properties are the "hallmarks" of constructive theories such as Heyting arithmetic and constructive set theories (Rathjen 2005). Disjunction property The disjunction property is satisfi ...
iff it admits the rule :\frac. Again, basic results on admissible rules generalize smoothly to multiple-conclusion rules.Jeřábek (2005, 2007, 2008) In logics with a variant of the disjunction property, the multiple-conclusion rules have the same expressive power as single-conclusion rules: for example, in ''S''4 the rule above is equivalent to :\frac. Nevertheless, multiple-conclusion rules can often be employed to simplify arguments. In
proof theory Proof theory is a major branchAccording to Wang (1981), pp. 3–4, proof theory is one of four domains mathematical logic, together with model theory, axiomatic set theory, and recursion theory. Jon Barwise, Barwise (1978) consists of four correspo ...
, admissibility is often considered in the context of sequent calculi, where the basic objects are sequents rather than formulas. For example, one can rephrase the cut-elimination theorem as saying that the cut-free sequent calculus admits the
cut rule In mathematical logic, the cut rule is an inference rule of sequent calculus In mathematical logic, sequent calculus is a style of formal logical argumentation in which every line of a proof is a conditional tautology (called a sequent by Gerhar ...
:\frac. (By abuse of language, it is also sometimes said that the (full) sequent calculus admits cut, meaning its cut-free version does.) However, admissibility in sequent calculi is usually only a notational variant for admissibility in the corresponding logic: any complete calculus for (say) intuitionistic logic admits a sequent rule if and only if ''IPC'' admits the formula rule that we obtain by translating each sequent \Gamma\vdash\Delta to its characteristic formula \bigwedge\Gamma\to\bigvee\Delta.


Notes


References

*W. Blok, D. Pigozzi, ''Algebraizable logics'',
Memoirs of the American Mathematical Society ''Memoirs of the American Mathematical Society'' is a mathematical journal published in six volumes per year, totalling approximately 33 individually bound numbers, by the American Mathematical Society. It is intended to carry papers on new mathema ...
77 (1989), no. 396, 1989. *A. Chagrov and M. Zakharyaschev, ''Modal Logic'', Oxford Logic Guides vol. 35, Oxford University Press, 1997. *P. Cintula and G. Metcalfe, ''Structural completeness in fuzzy logics'',
Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic The ''Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic'' is a quarterly peer-reviewed scientific journal covering the foundations of mathematics and related fields of mathematical logic, as well as philosophy of mathematics. It was established in 1960 and is p ...
50 (2009), no. 2, pp. 153–182. *A. I. Citkin, ''On structurally complete superintuitionistic logics'', Soviet Mathematics - Doklady, vol. 19 (1978), pp. 816–819. *S. Ghilardi, ''Unification in intuitionistic logic'', Journal of Symbolic Logic 64 (1999), no. 2, pp. 859–880
Project EuclidJSTOR
*S. Ghilardi, ''Best solving modal equations'',
Annals of Pure and Applied Logic This is a list of scientific, technical and general interest periodicals published by Elsevier or one of its imprints or subsidiary companies. Both printed items and electronic publications are included in this list. A B C D E F G ...
102 (2000), no. 3, pp. 183–198. *R. Iemhoff, ''On the admissible rules of intuitionistic propositional logic'', Journal of Symbolic Logic 66 (2001), no. 1, pp. 281–294
Project EuclidJSTOR
*R. Iemhoff, ''Intermediate logics and Visser's rules'', Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 46 (2005), no. 1, pp. 65–81. *R. Iemhoff, ''On the rules of intermediate logics'',
Archive for Mathematical Logic '' Archive for Mathematical Logic'' is a peer review, peer-reviewed mathematics journal published by Springer Science+Business Media. It was established in 1950 and publishes articles on mathematical logic. Abstracting and indexing The journal is ...
, 45 (2006), no. 5, pp. 581–599. *E. Jeřábek, ''Admissible rules of modal logics'',
Journal of Logic and Computation The ''Journal of Logic and Computation'' is a peer-reviewed academic journal focused on logic and computing. It was established in 1990 and is published by Oxford University Press under licence from Professor Dov Gabbay Dov M. Gabbay (; born Oc ...
15 (2005), no. 4, pp. 411–431. *E. Jeřábek, ''Complexity of admissible rules'', Archive for Mathematical Logic 46 (2007), no. 2, pp. 73–92. *E. Jeřábek, ''Independent bases of admissible rules'', Logic Journal of the IGPL 16 (2008), no. 3, pp. 249–267. *M. Kracht, ''Modal Consequence Relations'', in: Handbook of Modal Logic (P. Blackburn, J. van Benthem, and F. Wolter, eds.), Studies of Logic and Practical Reasoning vol. 3, Elsevier, 2007, pp. 492–545. *P. Lorenzen, ''Einführung in die operative Logik und Mathematik'', Grundlehren der mathematischen Wissenschaften vol. 78, Springer–Verlag, 1955. *G. Mints and A. Kojevnikov, ''Intuitionistic Frege systems are polynomially equivalent'', Zapiski Nauchnyh Seminarov POMI 316 (2004), pp. 129–146
gzipped PS
*T. Prucnal, ''Structural completeness of Medvedev's propositional calculus'', Reports on Mathematical Logic 6 (1976), pp. 103–105. *T. Prucnal, ''On two problems of Harvey Friedman'', Studia Logica 38 (1979), no. 3, pp. 247–262. *P. Rozière, ''Règles admissibles en calcul propositionnel intuitionniste'', Ph.D. thesis,
Université de Paris VII Paris Diderot University, also known as Paris 7 (french: Université Paris Diderot), was a French university located in Paris, France. It was one of the inheritors of the historic University of Paris, which was split into 13 universities in 197 ...
, 1992
PDF
*V. V. Rybakov, ''Admissibility of Logical Inference Rules'', Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics vol. 136, Elsevier, 1997. *F. Wolter, M. Zakharyaschev, ''Undecidability of the unification and admissibility problems for modal and description logics'',
ACM Transactions on Computational Logic ''ACM Transactions on Computational Logic'' (''ACM TOCL'') is a scientific journal that aims to disseminate the latest findings of note in the field of logic in computer science. It is published by the Association for Computing Machinery, a premier ...
9 (2008), no. 4, article no. 25.
PDF
{{DEFAULTSORT:Admissible Rule Rules of inference Modal logic