Herbert Paul Grice (13 March 1913 – 28 August 1988),
usually publishing under the name H. P. Grice, H. Paul Grice, or Paul Grice, was a British
philosopher of language
In analytic philosophy, philosophy of language investigates the nature of language and the relations between language, language users, and the world. Investigations may include inquiry into the nature of meaning, intentionality, reference, the ...
. He is best known for his theory of
implicature
In pragmatics, a subdiscipline of linguistics, an implicature is something the speaker suggests or implies with an utterance, even though it is not literally expressed. Implicatures can aid in communicating more efficiently than by explicitly sayi ...
and the
cooperative principle
In social science generally and linguistics specifically, the cooperative principle describes how people achieve effective conversational communication in common social situations—that is, how listeners and speakers act cooperatively and mutual ...
(with its namesake Gricean maxims), which became foundational concepts in the linguistic field of
pragmatics
In linguistics and related fields, pragmatics is the study of how context contributes to meaning. The field of study evaluates how human language is utilized in social interactions, as well as the relationship between the interpreter and the int ...
. His work on
meaning has also influenced the philosophical study of
semantics
Semantics (from grc, σημαντικός ''sēmantikós'', "significant") is the study of reference, meaning, or truth. The term can be used to refer to subfields of several distinct disciplines, including philosophy
Philosophy (f ...
.
Life
Born and raised in Harborne (now a suburb of Birmingham), in the United Kingdom, he was educated at
Clifton College
''The spirit nourishes within''
, established = 160 years ago
, closed =
, type = Public schoolIndependent boarding and day school
, religion = Christian
, president =
, head_label = Head of College
, head ...
and then at
Corpus Christi College, Oxford
Corpus Christi College (formally, Corpus Christi College in the University of Oxford; informally abbreviated as Corpus or CCC) is one of the constituent colleges of the University of Oxford in the United Kingdom. Founded in 1517, it is the 12th ...
.
[publish.uwo.ca/~rstainto/papers/Grice.pdf]
After a brief period teaching at
Rossall School
Rossall School is a public school (English independent day and boarding school) for 0–18 year olds, between Cleveleys and Fleetwood, Lancashire. Rossall was founded in 1844 by St Vincent Beechey as a sister school to Marlborough College ...
,
he went back to Oxford, firstly as a graduate student at
Merton College
Merton College (in full: The House or College of Scholars of Merton in the University of Oxford) is one of the constituent colleges of the University of Oxford in England. Its foundation can be traced back to the 1260s when Walter de Merton, ch ...
from 1936 to 1938, and then as a Lecturer, Fellow and Tutor from 1938 at
St John's College.
During the
Second World War
World War II or the Second World War, often abbreviated as WWII or WW2, was a world war that lasted from 1939 to 1945. It involved the vast majority of the world's countries—including all of the great powers—forming two opposin ...
Grice served in the
Royal Navy
The Royal Navy (RN) is the United Kingdom's naval warfare force. Although warships were used by English and Scottish kings from the early medieval period, the first major maritime engagements were fought in the Hundred Years' War against F ...
;
after the war he returned to his Fellowship at St John's, which he held until 1967. In that year, he moved to the United States to take up a professorship at the
University of California, Berkeley
The University of California, Berkeley (UC Berkeley, Berkeley, Cal, or California) is a public land-grant research university in Berkeley, California. Established in 1868 as the University of California, it is the state's first land-grant u ...
, where he taught until his death in 1988. He returned to the UK in 1979 to give the
John Locke lectures
The John Locke Lectures are a series of annual lectures in philosophy given at the University of Oxford. Named for British philosopher John Locke, the Locke Lectures are the world's most prestigious lectures in philosophy, and are among the world' ...
on ''Aspects of Reason''. He reprinted many of his essays and papers in his valedictory book, ''Studies in the Way of Words'' (1989).
Grice married Kathleen Watson in 1942; they had two children.
Grice on meaning
One of Grice's two most influential contributions to the study of language and
communication
Communication (from la, communicare, meaning "to share" or "to be in relation with") is usually defined as the transmission of information. The term may also refer to the message communicated through such transmissions or the field of inquir ...
is his theory of
meaning, which he began to develop in his article "Meaning", written in 1948 but published only in 1957 at the prodding of his colleague,
P. F. Strawson
Peter Frederick Strawson (; 23 November 1919 – 13 February 2006) was an English philosopher. He was the Waynflete Professor of Metaphysical Philosophy at the University of Oxford (Magdalen College) from 1968 to 1987. Before that, he ...
. Grice further developed his theory of meaning in the fifth and sixth of his
William James
William James (January 11, 1842 – August 26, 1910) was an American philosopher, historian, and psychologist, and the first educator to offer a psychology course in the United States.
James is considered to be a leading thinker of the lat ...
lectures on "Logic and Conversation", delivered at Harvard in 1967. These two lectures were initially published as "Utterer's Meaning and Intentions" in 1969 and "Utterer's Meaning, Sentence Meaning, and Word Meaning" in 1968, and were later collected with the other lectures as the first section of ''Studies in the Way of Words'' in 1989.
Natural vs. non-natural meaning
In the 1957 article "Meaning", Grice describes "natural meaning" using the example of "Those spots mean (meant) measles."
And describes "non-natural meaning" using the example of "John means that he'll be late" or "'Schnee' means 'snow'".
Grice does not define these two senses of the verb 'to mean', and does not offer an explicit theory that separates the ideas they're used to express. Instead, he relies on five differences in
ordinary language
Ordinary language philosophy (OLP) is a philosophical methodology that sees traditional philosophical problems as rooted in misunderstandings philosophers develop by distorting or forgetting how words are ordinarily used to convey meaning in ...
usage to show that we use the word in (at least) two different ways.
Intention-based semantics
For the rest of "Meaning", and in his discussions of meaning in "Logic and Conversation", Grice deals exclusively with non-natural meaning. His overall approach to the study of non-natural meaning later came to be called "intention-based semantics" because it attempts to explain non-natural meaning based on the idea of a speakers' intentions. To do this, Grice distinguishes two kinds of non-natural meaning:
Utterer's meaning: What a speaker means by an utterance. (Grice wouldn't introduce this label until "Logic and Conversation." The more common label in contemporary work is "speaker meaning", though Grice didn't use that term.)
Timeless meaning: The kind of meaning that can be possessed by a type of utterance, such as a word or a sentence. (This is often called "conventional meaning", although Grice didn't call it that.)
The two steps in intention-based semantics are (1) to define utterer's meaning in terms of speakers' overt audience-directed intentions, and then (2) to define timeless meaning in terms of utterer's meaning. The net effect is to define all linguistic notions of meaning in purely mental terms, and to thus shed psychological light on the semantic realm.
Grice tries to accomplish the first step by means of the following definition:
"A meantNN something by x" is roughly equivalent to "A uttered x with the intention of inducing a belief by means of the recognition of this intention".
(In this definition, 'A' is a variable ranging over speakers and 'x' is a variable ranging over utterances.) Grice generalises this definition of speaker meaning later in 'Meaning' so that it applies to commands and questions, which, he argues, differ from assertions in that the speaker intends to induce an intention rather than a belief.
[Grice 1989, p. 220.] Grice's initial definition was controversial, and seemingly gives rise to a variety of counterexamples, and so later adherents of intention-based semantics—including Grice himself,
Stephen Schiffer
Stephen Schiffer (born 1940) is an American philosopher and currently Silver Professor of Philosophy at New York University. He is a specialist in the philosophy of language.
Education and career
Schiffer was awarded a B.A. in philosophy from ...
,
Jonathan Bennett,
Dan Sperber
Dan Sperber (born 20 June 1942 in Cagnes-sur-Mer) is a French social and cognitive scientist and philosopher. His most influential work has been in the fields of cognitive anthropology, linguistic pragmatics, psychology of reasoning, and phil ...
and
Deirdre Wilson
Deirdre Susan Moir Wilson, FBA (born 1941) is a British linguist and cognitive scientist. She is emeritus professor of Linguistics at University College London and research professor at the Centre for the Study of Mind in Nature at the Univers ...
, and
Stephen Neale
Stephen Roy Albert Neale (born 9 January 1958) is a British philosopher and specialist in the philosophy of language who has written extensively about meaning, information, interpretation, and communication, and more generally about issues a ...
—have attempted to improve on it in various ways while keeping the basic idea intact.
Grice next turns to the second step in his program: explaining the notion of timeless meaning in terms of the notion of utterer's meaning. He does so very tentatively with the following definition:
"x meansNN (timeless) that so-and-so" might as a first shot be equated with some statement or disjunction of statements about what "people" (vague) intend (with qualifications about "recognition") to effect by x.
The basic idea here is that the meaning of a word or sentence results from a regularity in what speakers use the word or sentence to mean. Grice would give a much more detailed theory of timeless meaning in his sixth Logic and Conversation lecture. A more influential attempt to expand on this component of intention-based semantics has been given by Stephen Schiffer.
Grice's theory of implicature
Grice's most influential contribution to philosophy and linguistics is his theory of implicature, which started in his 1961 article, "The Causal Theory of Perception", and "Logic and Conversation", which was delivered at Harvard's 'William James Lectures' in 1967, and published in 1975 as a chapter in volume 3 of ''Syntax and Semantics: Speech Acts''.
Saying/implicating distinction
According to Grice, what a speaker means by an utterance can be divided into what the speaker "says" and what the speaker thereby "implicates".
Grice makes it clear that the notion of saying he has in mind, though related to a colloquial sense of the word, is somewhat technical, referring to it as "a favored notion of 'saying' that must be further elucidated".
[Grice 1989, p.86.] Nonetheless, Grice never settled on a full elucidation or definition of his favoured notion of saying, and the interpretation of this notion has become a contentious issue in the philosophy of language.
One point of controversy surrounding Grice's favoured notion of saying is the connection between it and his concept of utterer's meaning. Grice makes it clear that he takes saying to be a kind of meaning, in the sense that doing the former entails doing the latter: "I want to say that (1) "U (utterer) said that p" entails (2) "U did something x by which U meant that p" (87). This condition is controversial, but Grice argues that apparent counterexamples—cases in which a speaker apparently says something without meaning it—are actually examples of what he calls "making as if to say", which can be thought of as a kind of "mock saying" or "play saying".
Another point of controversy surrounding Grice's notion of saying is the relationship between what a speaker says with an expression and the expression's timeless meaning. Although he attempts to spell out the connection in detail several times, the most precise statement that he endorses is the following one:
In the sense in which I am using the word say, I intend what someone has said to be closely related to the conventional meaning of the words (the sentence) he has uttered.
Unfortunately, Grice never spelled out what he meant by the phrase "closely related" in this passage, and philosophers of language continue to debate over its best interpretation.
In 'The Causal Theory of Perception', Grice contrasts saying (which he there also calls "stating") with "implying", but in Logic and Conversation he introduces the technical term "implicature" and its cognates "to implicate" and "implicatum" (i.e., that which is implicated). Grice justifies this neologism by saying that "'Implicature' is a blanket word to avoid having to make choices between words like 'imply', 'suggest', 'indicate', and 'mean'".
Grice sums up these notions by suggesting that to implicate is to perform a "non-central" speech act, whereas to say is to perform a "central" speech act.
[Grice 1989, p.88.] As others have more commonly put the same distinction, saying is a kind of "direct" speech act whereas implicating is an "indirect" speech act. This latter way of drawing the distinction is an important part of
John Searle
John Rogers Searle (; born July 31, 1932) is an American philosopher widely noted for contributions to the philosophy of language, philosophy of mind, and social philosophy. He began teaching at UC Berkeley in 1959, and was Willis S. and Mario ...
's influential theory of speech acts.
Conventional vs. conversational implicature
Although Grice is best known for his theory of
conversational implicature
In pragmatics, a subdiscipline of linguistics, an implicature is something the speaker suggests or implies with an utterance, even though it is not literally expressed. Implicatures can aid in communicating more efficiently than by explicitly sayi ...
, he also introduced the notion of
conventional implicature
In pragmatics, a subdiscipline of linguistics, an implicature is something the speaker suggests or implies with an utterance, even though it is not literally expressed. Implicatures can aid in communicating more efficiently than by explicitly sayi ...
. The difference between the two lies in the fact that what a speaker conventionally implicates by uttering a sentence is tied in some way to the timeless meaning of part of the sentence, whereas what a speaker conversationally implicates is not directly connected with timeless meaning. Grice's best-known example of conventional implicature involves the word 'but', which, he argues, differs in meaning from the word 'and' only in that we typically conventionally implicate something over and above what we say with the former but not with the latter. In uttering the sentence '
She was poor but she was honest', for example, we say merely that she was poor and she was honest, but we implicate that poverty contrasts with honesty (or that her poverty contrasts with her honesty).
Grice makes it clear that what a speaker conventionally implicates by uttering a sentence is part of what the speaker means in uttering it, and that it is also closely connected to what the sentence means. Nonetheless, what a speaker conventionally implicates is not a part of what the speaker says.
U's doing ''x'' might be his uttering the sentence "She was poor but she was honest". What ''U'' meant, and what the sentence means, will both contain something contributed by the word "but", and I do not want this contribution to appear in an account of what (in my favored sense) ''U'' said (but rather as a conventional implicature).
Grice did not elaborate much on the notion of conventional implicature, but many other authors have tried to give more extensive theories of it, including
Lauri Karttunen
Lauri Juhani Karttunen was an adjunct professor in linguistics at Stanford and an ACL Fellow. He died in 2022.
Career
Karttunen received his Ph.D. in Linguistics in 1969 from Indiana University in Bloomington. At the University of Texas at Aus ...
and
Stanley Peters
Stanley may refer to:
Arts and entertainment
Film and television
* ''Stanley'' (1972 film), an American horror film
* ''Stanley'' (1984 film), an Australian comedy
* ''Stanley'' (1999 film), an animated short
* ''Stanley'' (1956 TV series) ...
, Kent Bach, Stephen Neale, and Christopher Potts.
Conversational implicature
To conversationally implicate something in speaking, according to Grice, is to mean something that goes beyond what one says in such a way that it must be inferred from non-linguistic features of a conversational situation together with general principles of communication and co-operation.
The general principles Grice proposed are what he called
the Cooperative principle and the Maxims of Conversation. According to Grice, the cooperative principle is a norm governing all cooperative interactions among humans.
Cooperative Principle: "Make your contribution such as it is required, at the stage at which it occurs, by the accepted purpose or direction of the talk exchange in which you are engaged." (Grice 1989: 26).
The conversational maxims can be thought of as precisifications of the cooperative principle that deal specifically with communication.
Maxim of Quantity: Information
* Make your contribution as informative as is required for the current purposes of the exchange.
* Do not make your contribution more informative than is required.
Maxim of Quality: Truth
* Do not say what you believe to be false.
* Do not say that for which you lack adequate evidence.
Maxim of Relation: Relevance
* Be relevant.
Maxim of Manner: Clarity ("be perspicuous")
* Avoid obscurity of expression.
* Avoid ambiguity.
* Be brief (avoid prolixity).
* Be orderly.
Grice follows his summary of the maxims by suggesting that "one might need others", and goes on to say that "There are, of course, all sorts of other maxims (aesthetic, social, or moral in character), such as "Be polite", that are also normally observed by participants in exchanges, and these may also generate nonconventional implicatures."
Conversational implicatures are made possible, according to Grice, by the fact that the participants in a conversation always assume each other to behave according to the maxims. So, when a speaker appears to have violated a maxim by saying or making as if to say something that is false, uninformative or too informative, irrelevant, or unclear, the assumption that the speaker is in fact obeying the maxims causes the interpreter to infer a hypothesis about what the speaker really meant.
[ Kordić 1991, pp.91–92.] That an interpreter will reliably do this allows speakers to intentionally "flout" the maxims—i.e., create the appearance of breaking the maxims in a way that is obvious to both speaker and interpreter—to get their implicatures across.
Perhaps Grice's best-known example of conversational implicature is the case of the reference letter, a "quantity implicature" (i.e., because it involves flouting the first maxim of Quantity):
A is writing a testimonial about a pupil who is a candidate for a philosophy job, and his letter reads as follows: "Dear Sir, Mr. X's command of English is excellent, and his attendance at tutorials has been regular. Yours, etc." (Gloss: A cannot be opting out, since if he wished to be uncooperative, why write at all? He cannot be unable, through ignorance, to say more, since the man is his pupil; moreover, he knows that more information than this is wanted. He must, therefore, be wishing to impart information that he is reluctant to write down. This supposition is tenable only if he thinks Mr. X is no good at philosophy. This, then, is what he is implicating.)
Given that a speaker means a given proposition ''p'' by a given utterance, Grice suggests several features which ''p'' must possess to count as a conversational implicature.
Nondetachability: "The implicature is nondetachable insofar as it is not possible to find another way of saying the same thing (or approximately the same thing) which simply lacks the implicature."
Cancelability: "...a putative conversational implicature is explicitly cancelable if, to the form of words the utterance of which putatively implicates that ''p'', it is admissible to add ''but not p'', or ''I do not mean to imply that p'', and it is contextually cancelable if one can find situations in which the utterance of the form of words would simply not carry the implicature."
[Grice 1989, p.44.]
Non-Conventionality: "...conversational implicata are not part of the meaning of the expressions to the employment of which they attach."
Calculability: "The presence of a conversational implicature must be capable of being worked out; for even if it can in fact be intuitively grasped, unless the intuition is replaceable by an argument, the implicature (if present at all) will not count as a conversational implicature; it will be a conventional implicature."
Generalised vs. particularised conversational implicature
Grice also distinguishes between generalised and particularised conversational implicature. Grice says that particularised conversational implicatures (such as in the reference letter case quoted above) arise in "cases in which an implicature is carried by saying that ''p'' on a particular occasion in virtue of special features about the context, cases in which there is no room for the idea that an implicature of this sort is normally carried by saying that ''p''."
[Grice 1989, p.37.] Generalized implicature, by contrast, arise in cases in which "one can say that the use of a certain form of words in an utterance would normally (in the absence of special circumstances) carry such-and-such an implicature or type of implicature."
Grice does not offer a full theory of generalised conversational implicatures that distinguishes them from particularised conversational implicatures, on one hand, and from conventional implicatures, on the other hand, but later philosophers and linguists have attempted to expand on the idea of generalised conversational implicatures.
Grice's paradox
In his book ''Studies in the Way of Words'' (1989), he presents what he calls Grice's paradox. In it, he supposes that two chess players, Yog and Zog, play 100 games under the following conditions:
(1) Yog is white nine of ten times.
(2) There are no draws.
And the results are:
(1) Yog, when white, won 80 of 90 games.
(2) Yog, when black, won zero of ten games.
This implies that:
(i) 8/9 times, if Yog was white, Yog won.
(ii) 1/2 of the time, if Yog lost, Yog was black.
(iii) 9/10 that either Yog wasn't white or he won.
From these statements, it might ''appear'' one could make these deductions by
contraposition
In logic and mathematics, contraposition refers to the inference of going from a conditional statement into its logically equivalent contrapositive, and an associated proof method known as Proof by contrapositive, proof by contraposition. The cont ...
and
conditional disjunction:
(
from
i If Yog was white, then 1/2 of the time Yog won.
(
from
ii 9/10 times, if Yog was white, then he won.
But both (a) and (b) are untrue—they contradict (i). In fact, (ii) and (iii) don't provide enough information to use
Bayesian
Thomas Bayes (/beɪz/; c. 1701 – 1761) was an English statistician, philosopher, and Presbyterian minister.
Bayesian () refers either to a range of concepts and approaches that relate to statistical methods based on Bayes' theorem, or a followe ...
reasoning to reach those conclusions. That might be clearer if (i)-(iii) had instead been stated like so:
(i) When Yog was white, Yog won 8/9 times. (No information is given about when Yog was black.)
(ii) When Yog lost, Yog was black 1/2 the time. (No information is given about when Yog won.)
(iii) 9/10 times, either Yog was black and won, Yog was black and lost, or Yog was white and won. (No information is provided on how the 9/10 is divided among those three situations.)
Grice's paradox shows that the exact meaning of statements involving conditionals and probabilities is more complicated than may be obvious on casual examination.
Criticisms
Relevance theory
Relevance theory is a framework for understanding the interpretation of utterances. It was first proposed by Dan Sperber and Deirdre Wilson, and is used within cognitive linguistics and pragmatics. The theory was originally inspired by the work o ...
of
Dan Sperber
Dan Sperber (born 20 June 1942 in Cagnes-sur-Mer) is a French social and cognitive scientist and philosopher. His most influential work has been in the fields of cognitive anthropology, linguistic pragmatics, psychology of reasoning, and phil ...
and
Deirdre Wilson
Deirdre Susan Moir Wilson, FBA (born 1941) is a British linguist and cognitive scientist. She is emeritus professor of Linguistics at University College London and research professor at the Centre for the Study of Mind in Nature at the Univers ...
builds on and also challenges Grice's theory of meaning and his account of pragmatic inference.
[''Relevance: Communication and Cognition'' (Oxford: Blackwell, 1986)]
Notes
References
* Bach, Kent (1999). "The Myth of Conventional Implicature," ''Linguistics and Philosophy'', 22, pp. 327–366.
* Bennett, Jonathan (1976). ''Linguistic Behaviour''. Cambridge University Press.
* Borg, Emma (2006). "Intention-Based Semantics," ''The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Language'', edited by Ernest Lepore and Barry C. Smith. Oxford University Press, 2006, pp. 250–266.
* Grice (1941). "Personal Identity", ''Mind'' 50, 330–350; reprinted in J. Perry (ed.), ''Personal Identity'', University of California Press, Berkeley, 1975, pp. 73–95.
* Grice, H.P. (1957). "Meaning", ''Philosophical Review'', 66(3). Reprinted as ch.14 of Grice 1989, pp. 213–223.
* Grice (1961). "The Causal Theory of Perception", ''Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society'' 35 (suppl.), 121–52. Partially reprinted as Chapter 15 of Grice 1989, pp. 224–247.
* Grice, H.P. (1968). "Utterer's Meaning, Sentence Meaning, and Word Meaning," ''Foundations of Language'', 4. Reprinted as ch.6 of Grice 1989, pp. 117–137.
* Grice (1969). "Vacuous Names", in D. Davidson and J. Hintikka (eds.), ''Words and Objections'', D. Reidel, Dordrecht, pp. 118–145.
* Grice, H.P. (1969). "Utterer's Meaning and Intentions", ''The Philosophical Review'', 78. Reprinted as ch.5 of Grice 1989, pp. 86–116.
* Grice, H.P. (1971)
"Intention and Uncertainty" ''Proceedings of the British Academy'', pp. 263–279.
* Grice, H.P. (1975). "Method in Philosophical Psychology: From the Banal to the Bizarre", ''Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association'' (1975), pp. 23–53.
* Grice, H.P. (1975). "Logic and Conversation," ''Syntax and Semantics'', vol.3 edited by P. Cole and J. Morgan, Academic Press. Reprinted as ch.2 of Grice 1989, 22–40.
* Grice, H.P. (1978). "Further Notes on Logic and Conversation," ''Syntax and Semantics'', vol.9 edited by P. Cole, Academic Press. Reprinted as ch.3 of Grice 1989, 41–57.
* Grice (1981). "Presupposition and Conversational Implicature", in P. Cole (ed.), ''Radical Pragmatics'', Academic Press, New York, pp. 183–198. Reprinted as ch.17 of Grice 1989, 269–282.
* Grice, H.P. (1989). ''
Studies in the Way of Words''. Harvard University Press.
* Grice, H.P. (1991). ''The Conception of Value''. Oxford University Press. (His 1983 Carus Lectures.)
* Grice, H.P., (2001). ''Aspects of Reason'' (Richard Warner, ed.). Oxford University Press. (His 1979 John Locke Lectures, mostly the same as his 1977 Immanuel Kant Lectures.)
* Karttunen, Lauri and Stanley Peters (1978). "Conventional Implicature," ''Syntax and Semantics'', vol.11 edited by P. Cole, Academic Press. pp. 1–56.
*
* Levinson, Stephen (2000). ''Presumptive Meanings: The Theory of Generalized Conversational Implicature''. MIT Press.
* Neale, Stephen (1992). "Paul Grice and the Philosophy of Language," ''Linguistics and Philosophy'', 15, pp. 509–559.
* Neale, Stephen (1999). "Colouring and Composition," ''Philosophy and Linguistics'', edited by Rob Stainton. Westview Press, 1999. pp. 35–82.
* Potts, Christopher (2005). ''The Logic of Conventional Implicature''. Oxford University Press.
* Searle, John (1975). "Indirect Speech Acts," ''Syntax and Semantics'', vol.3 edited by P. Cole and J. Morgan, Academic Press.
* Schiffer, Stephen (1972). ''Meaning''. Oxford University Press.
* Schiffer, Stephen (1982). "Intention-Based Semantics," ''Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic'', 23(2), pp. 119–156.
* Sperber, Dan and Dierdre Wilson (1986). ''Relevance: Communication and Cognition''. Blackwell. Second edition 1995.
Further reading
Siobhan Chapman Paul Grice: Philosopher and Linguist', Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan, 2005. .
The Literary Encyclopedia
''The Literary Encyclopedia'' is an online reference work first published in October 2000. It was founded as an innovative project designed to bring the benefits of information technology to what at the time was still a largely conservative li ...
'' is archived by Wayback Machine]
here
*
External links
*
* ''MIT Encyclopedia of the Cognitive Sciences'':
—by
Kent Bach
Kent Bach (born 1943) is an American philosopher and Professor of Philosophy at San Francisco State University. His primary areas of research include the philosophy of language, linguistics and epistemology. He is the author of three books: ''Exi ...
.
* ''Dictionary of Philosophy of Mind'':
Paul Grice—by
Christopher Gauker.
Herbert Paul Grice (1913 - 1988)by Peter Strawson and
David Wiggins
David Wiggins (born 1933) is an English moral philosopher, metaphysician, and philosophical logician working especially on identity and issues in meta-ethics.
Biography
David Wiggins was born on 8 March 1933 in London, the son of Norman ...
for ''
The Proceedings of the British Academy'' (2001).
La comunicación según Grice (Spanish) rchived by Wayback Machine*
{{DEFAULTSORT:Grice, Paul
1913 births
1988 deaths
20th-century British philosophers
20th-century essayists
20th-century linguists
Action theorists
Alumni of Corpus Christi College, Oxford
Alumni of Merton College, Oxford
Analytic philosophers
Aristotelian philosophers
British emigrants to the United States
British logicians
British male essayists
British semioticians
Communication theorists
Epistemologists
Historians of philosophy
History of linguistics
History of logic
Metaphysicians
Ontologists
Ordinary language philosophy
People educated at Clifton College
People from Harborne
Philosophers of language
Philosophers of logic
Philosophers of mind
Pragmaticists
Fellows of St John's College, Oxford
University of California, Berkeley faculty