HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

Gabriel's horn (also called Torricelli's trumpet) is a particular geometric figure that has infinite surface area but finite
volume Volume is a measure of occupied three-dimensional space. It is often quantified numerically using SI derived units (such as the cubic metre and litre) or by various imperial or US customary units (such as the gallon, quart, cubic inch). Th ...
. The name refers to the Christian tradition where the archangel
Gabriel In Abrahamic religions ( Judaism, Christianity and Islam), Gabriel (); Greek: grc, Γαβριήλ, translit=Gabriḗl, label=none; Latin: ''Gabriel''; Coptic: cop, Ⲅⲁⲃⲣⲓⲏⲗ, translit=Gabriêl, label=none; Amharic: am, ገብ ...
blows the horn to announce Judgment Day. The properties of this figure were first studied by Italian physicist and mathematician
Evangelista Torricelli Evangelista Torricelli ( , also , ; 15 October 160825 October 1647) was an Italian physicist and mathematician, and a student of Galileo. He is best known for his invention of the barometer, but is also known for his advances in optics and work ...
in the 17th century. These colourful informal names and the allusion to religion came along later. Torricelli's own name for it is to be found in the Latin title of his paper , written in 1643, a truncated acute hyperbolic solid, cut by a plane. Volume 1, part 1 of his published the following year included that paper and a second more orthodox (for the time) Archimedean proof of its theorem about the volume of a truncated acute hyperbolic solid. This name was used in mathematical dictionaries of the 18th century (including "Hyperbolicum Acutum" in Harris' 1704 dictionary and in Stone's 1726 one, and the French translation in d'Alembert's 1751 one. Although credited with primacy by his contemporaries, Torricelli was not the first to describe an infinitely long shape with a finite volume/area. The work of
Nicole Oresme Nicole Oresme (; c. 1320–1325 – 11 July 1382), also known as Nicolas Oresme, Nicholas Oresme, or Nicolas d'Oresme, was a French philosopher of the later Middle Ages. He wrote influential works on economics, mathematics, physics, astrology an ...
in the 14th century had either been forgotten by, or was unknown to them. Oresme had posited such things as an infinitely long shape constructed by subdividing two squares of finite total area 2 using a
geometric series In mathematics, a geometric series is the sum of an infinite number of terms that have a constant ratio between successive terms. For example, the series :\frac \,+\, \frac \,+\, \frac \,+\, \frac \,+\, \cdots is geometric, because each suc ...
and rearranging the parts into a figure, infinitely long in one dimension, comprising a series of rectangles.


Mathematical definition

Gabriel's horn is formed by taking the
graph Graph may refer to: Mathematics *Graph (discrete mathematics), a structure made of vertices and edges **Graph theory, the study of such graphs and their properties *Graph (topology), a topological space resembling a graph in the sense of discre ...
of y = \frac, with the domain x \ge 1 and
rotating Rotation, or spin, is the circular movement of an object around a '' central axis''. A two-dimensional rotating object has only one possible central axis and can rotate in either a clockwise or counterclockwise direction. A three-dimensional ...
it in three
dimension In physics and mathematics, the dimension of a mathematical space (or object) is informally defined as the minimum number of coordinates needed to specify any point within it. Thus, a line has a dimension of one (1D) because only one coor ...
s about the  axis. The discovery was made using Cavalieri's principle before the invention of
calculus Calculus, originally called infinitesimal calculus or "the calculus of infinitesimals", is the mathematical study of continuous change, in the same way that geometry is the study of shape, and algebra is the study of generalizations of arithm ...
, but today, calculus can be used to calculate the volume and surface area of the horn between and , where . Using integration (see Solid of revolution and
Surface of revolution A surface of revolution is a surface in Euclidean space created by rotating a curve (the generatrix) around an axis of rotation. Examples of surfaces of revolution generated by a straight line are cylindrical and conical surfaces depending on ...
for details), it is possible to find the volume and the surface area : V = \pi\int_1^a \left(\frac\right)^2 \,\mathrmx = \pi\left(1 - \frac\right), A = 2\pi\int_1^a \frac \sqrt \,\mathrmx > 2\pi\int_1^a \frac = 2\pi \cdot \left ln x \right^ = 2\pi\ln a. The value can be as large as required, but it can be seen from the equation that the volume of the part of the horn between and will never exceed ; however, it does gradually draw nearer to as increases. Mathematically, the volume ''approaches'' as ''approaches'' infinity. Using the limit notation of calculus, \lim_ V = \lim_ \pi\left(1 - \frac\right) = \pi \cdot \lim_\left(1 - \frac\right) = \pi. The surface area formula above gives a lower bound for the area as 2 times the natural logarithm of . There is no
upper bound In mathematics, particularly in order theory, an upper bound or majorant of a subset of some preordered set is an element of that is greater than or equal to every element of . Dually, a lower bound or minorant of is defined to be an eleme ...
for the natural logarithm of , as approaches infinity. That means, in this case, that the horn has an infinite surface area. That is to say, \lim_ A \ge \lim_ 2\pi\ln a = \infty.


In

Torricelli's original non-calculus proof used an object, slightly different to the aforegiven, that was constructed by truncating the acute hyperbolic solid with a plane perpendicular to the ''x'' axis and extending it from the opposite side of that plane with a cylinder of the same base. Whereas the calculus method proceeds by setting the plane of truncation at x = 1 and integrating along the ''x'' axis, Torricelli proceeded by calculating the volume of this compound solid (with the added cylinder) by summing the surface areas of a series of concentric right cylinders within it along the ''y'' axis and showing that this was equivalent to summing areas within another solid whose (finite) volume was known. In modern terminology this solid was created by constructing a surface of revolution of the function (for strictly positive ) y = \begin \dfrac, & \text0 \le x \le b, \\ \dfrac, & \textb \le x. \end and Torricelli's theorem was that its volume is the same as the volume of the right cylinder with height 1/b and radius \sqrt: Torricelli showed that the volume of the solid could be derived from the surface areas of this series of concentric right cylinders whose radii were 1/b \ge r \ge 0 and heights h = 1/r. Substituting in the formula for the surface areas of (just the sides of) these cylinders yields a constant surface area for all cylinders of 2\pi r \times h = 2\pi r \times 1/r = 2\pi. This is the also the area of a circle of radius \sqrt, and the nested surfaces of the cylinders (filling the volume of the solid) are thus equivalent to the stacked areas of the circles of radius \sqrt stacked from 0 to 1/b, and hence the volume of the aforementioned right cylinder, which is known to be V = \pi r^2 \times h = \pi(\sqrt)^2 \times 1/b = 2\pi/b: (The volume of the added cylinder is of course V_c = \pi r^2 \times h = \pi(1/b)^2 \times b = \pi/b and thus the volume of the truncated acute hyperbolic solid alone is V_s = V - V_c = 2\pi/b - \pi/b = \pi/b. If b = 1, as in the modern calculus derivation, V_s = \pi.) In the this is one of two proofs of the volume of the (truncated) acute hyperbolic solid. The use of Cavalieri's indivisibles in this proof was controversial at the time and the result shocking (Torricelli later recording that
Gilles de Roberval Gilles Personne de Roberval (August 10, 1602 – October 27, 1675), French mathematician, was born at Roberval near Beauvais, France. His name was originally Gilles Personne or Gilles Personier, with Roberval the place of his birth. Biography ...
had attempted to disprove it); so when the was published, the year after , Torricelli also supplied a second proof based upon orthodox Archimedean principles showing that the right cylinder (height 1/b radius \sqrt) was both upper and lower bound for the volume. Ironically, this was an echo of Archimedes' own caution in supplying two proofs, mechanical and geometrical, in his '' Quadrature of the Parabola'' to Dositheus.


Apparent paradox

When the properties of Gabriel's horn were discovered, the fact that the rotation of an infinitely large section of the  plane about the  axis generates an object of finite volume was considered a
paradox A paradox is a logically self-contradictory statement or a statement that runs contrary to one's expectation. It is a statement that, despite apparently valid reasoning from true premises, leads to a seemingly self-contradictory or a logically u ...
. While the section lying in the  plane has an infinite area, any other section parallel to it has a finite area. Thus the volume, being calculated from the "weighted sum" of sections, is finite. Another approach is to treat the solid as a stack of disks with diminishing
radii In classical geometry, a radius ( : radii) of a circle or sphere is any of the line segments from its center to its perimeter, and in more modern usage, it is also their length. The name comes from the latin ''radius'', meaning ray but also the ...
. The sum of the radii produces a harmonic series that goes to infinity. However, the correct calculation is the sum of their squares. Every disk has a radius and an area or . The series diverges, but the series converges. In general, for any real , the series converges. The apparent paradox formed part of a dispute over the nature of infinity involving many of the key thinkers of the time, including
Thomas Hobbes Thomas Hobbes ( ; 5/15 April 1588 – 4/14 December 1679) was an English philosopher, considered to be one of the founders of modern political philosophy. Hobbes is best known for his 1651 book ''Leviathan'', in which he expounds an influ ...
, John Wallis, and
Galileo Galilei Galileo di Vincenzo Bonaiuti de' Galilei (15 February 1564 – 8 January 1642) was an Italian astronomer, physicist and engineer, sometimes described as a polymath. Commonly referred to as Galileo, his name was pronounced (, ). He wa ...
. There is a similar phenomenon that applies to lengths and areas in the plane. The area between the curves and from 1 to infinity is finite, but the lengths of the two curves are clearly infinite. In lecture 16 of his 1666 , Isaac Barrow held that Torricelli's theorem had constrained
Aristotle Aristotle (; grc-gre, Ἀριστοτέλης ''Aristotélēs'', ; 384–322 BC) was a Greek philosopher and polymath during the Classical period in Ancient Greece. Taught by Plato, he was the founder of the Peripatetic school of ph ...
's general dictum (from ''
De Caelo ''On the Heavens'' (Greek: ''Περὶ οὐρανοῦ''; Latin: ''De Caelo'' or ''De Caelo et Mundo'') is Aristotle's chief cosmological treatise: written in 350 BC, it contains his astronomical theory and his ideas on the concrete workings ...
'' book 1, part 6) that "there is no proportion between the finite and the infinite". Aristotle had himself, strictly speaking, been making a case for the impossibility of the physical existence of an infinite body rather than a case for its impossibility as a geometrical abstract. Barrow had been adopting the contemporary 17th-century view that Aristotle's dictum and other geometrical axioms were (as he had said in lecture 7) from "some higher and universal science", underpinning both mathematics and physics. Thus Torricelli's demonstration of an object with a relation between a finite (volume) and an infinite (area) contradicted this dictum, at least in part. Barrow's explanation was that Aristotle's dictum still held, but only in a more limited fashion when comparing things of the same type, length with length, area with area, volume with volume, and so forth. It did not hold when comparing things of two different genera (area with volume, for example) and thus an infinite area ''could'' be connected to a finite volume. Others used Torricelli's theorem to bolster their own philosophical claims, unrelated to mathematics from a modern viewpoint. Ignace-Gaston Pardies in 1671 used the acute hyperbolic solid to argue that finite humans could comprehend the infinite, and proceeded to offer it as proof of the existences of God and immaterial souls. Since finite matter could not comprehend the infinite, Pardies argued, the fact that humans could comprehend this proof showed that humans must be more than matter, and have immaterial souls. In contrast,
Antoine Arnauld Antoine Arnauld (6 February 16128 August 1694) was a French Catholic theologian, philosopher and mathematician. He was one of the leading intellectuals of the Jansenist group of Port-Royal and had a very thorough knowledge of patristics. Cont ...
argued that because humans perceived a paradox here, human thought was limited in what it could comprehend, and thus is not up to the task of disproving divine, religious, truths. Hobbes' and Wallis' dispute was actually within the realm of mathematics: Wallis enthusiastically embracing the new concepts of infinity and indivisibles, proceeding to make further conclusions based upon Torricelli's work and to extend it to employ arithmetic rather than Torricelli's geometric arguments; and Hobbes claiming that since mathematics is derived from real world perceptions of finite things, "infinite" in mathematics can only mean "indefinite". These led to strongly worded letters by each to the Royal Society and in ''Philosophical Transactions'', Hobbes resorting to namecalling Wallis "mad" at one point. In 1672 Hobbes tried to re-cast Torricelli's theorem as about a ''finite'' solid that was extended ''indefinitely'', in an attempt to hold on to his contention that "natural light" (i.e. common sense) told us that an infinitely long thing must have an infinite volume. This aligned with Hobbes' other assertions that the use of the idea of a zero-width line in geometry was erroneous, and that Cavalieri's idea of indivisibles was ill-founded. Wallis argued that there existed geometrical shapes with finite area/volume but no centre of gravity based upon Torricelli, stating that understanding this required more of a command of geometry and logic "than M. Hobs is Master of". He also restructured the arguments in arithmetical terms as the sums of
arithmetic progression An arithmetic progression or arithmetic sequence () is a sequence of numbers such that the difference between the consecutive terms is constant. For instance, the sequence 5, 7, 9, 11, 13, 15, . . . is an arithmetic progression with a common differ ...
s, sequences of arithmetic
infinitesimals In mathematics, an infinitesimal number is a quantity that is closer to zero than any standard real number, but that is not zero. The word ''infinitesimal'' comes from a 17th-century Modern Latin coinage ''infinitesimus'', which originally refer ...
rather than sequences of geometric indivisibles. Oresme had already demonstrated that an infinitely long shape can have a finite area where, as one dimension tends towards infinitely large, another dimension tends towards infinitely small. In Barrow's own words "the infinite diminution of one dimension compensates for the infinite increase of the other", in the case of the acute hyperbolic solid by the equation of the
Apollonian The Apollonian and the Dionysian are philosophical and literary concepts represented by a duality between the figures of Apollo and Dionysus from Greek mythology. Its popularization is widely attributed to the work ''The Birth of Tragedy'' by Fri ...
hyperbola In mathematics, a hyperbola (; pl. hyperbolas or hyperbolae ; adj. hyperbolic ) is a type of smooth curve lying in a plane, defined by its geometric properties or by equations for which it is the solution set. A hyperbola has two pieces, ca ...
xy=1.


Painter's paradox

Since the horn has finite volume but infinite surface area, there is an apparent paradox that the horn could be filled with a finite quantity of paint and yet that paint would not be sufficient to coat its surface. However, this paradox is again only an apparent paradox caused by an incomplete definition of "paint", or by using contradictory definitions of paint for the actions of filling and painting. One could be postulating a "mathematical" paint that is infinitely divisible (or infinitely thinnable, or simply zero-width like the zero-width geometric lines that Hobbes took issue with) and capable of travelling at infinite speed, or a "physical" paint with the properties of paint in the real world. With either one, the apparent paradox vanishes: With "mathematical" paint, it does not follow in the first place that an infinite surface area requires an infinite volume of paint, as infinite surface area times zero-thickness paint is indeterminate. With physical paint, painting the outside of the solid would require an infinite amount of paint because physical paint has a non-zero thickness. Torricelli's theorem does not talk about a layer of finite width on the ''outside'' of the solid, which in fact would have infinite volume. Thus there is no contradiction between infinite volume of paint and infinite surface area to cover. It is also impossible to paint the interior of the solid, the finite volume of Torricelli's theorem, with physical paint, so no contradiction exists. This is because physical paint can only fill an ''approximation'' of the volume of the solid. The molecules do not completely tile 3-dimensional space and leave gaps, and there is a point where the "throat" of the solid becomes too narrow for paint molecules to flow down. Physical paint travels at a bounded speed and would take an infinite amount of time to flow down. This also applies to "mathematical" paint of zero thickness if one does not additionally postulate it flowing at infinite speed. Other different postulates of "mathematical" paint, such as infinite-speed paint that gets thinner at a fast enough rate, remove the paradox too. For volume \pi of paint, as the surface area to be covered tends towards infinity, the thickness of the paint \pi/A tends towards zero. Like with the solid itself, the infinite increase of the surface area to be painted in one dimension is compensated by the infinite decrease in another dimension, the thickness of the paint.


Converse

The converse of Torricelli's acute hyperbolic solid is a surface of revolution that has a ''finite'' surface area but an ''infinite'' volume. In response to Torricelli's theorem, after learning of it from Marin Mersenne, Christiaan Huygens and René-François de Sluse wrote letters to each other about extending the theorem to other infinitely long solids of revolution; which have been mistakenly identified as finding such a converse. Jan A. van Maanen, professor of mathematics at the
University of Utrecht Utrecht University (UU; nl, Universiteit Utrecht, formerly ''Rijksuniversiteit Utrecht'') is a public research university in Utrecht, Netherlands. Established , it is one of the oldest universities in the Netherlands. In 2018, it had an enrollme ...
, reported in the 1990s that he once mis-stated in a conference at
Kristiansand Kristiansand is a seaside resort city and municipality in Agder county, Norway. The city is the fifth-largest and the municipality the sixth-largest in Norway, with a population of around 112,000 as of January 2020, following the incorporati ...
that de Sluse wrote to Huygens in 1658 that he had found such a shape: to be told in response (by Tony Gardiner and Man-Keung Siu of the
University of Hong Kong The University of Hong Kong (HKU) (Chinese: 香港大學) is a public research university in Hong Kong. Founded in 1887 as the Hong Kong College of Medicine for Chinese, it is the oldest tertiary institution in Hong Kong. HKU was also the f ...
) that any surface of rotation with a finite surface area would of necessity have a finite volume. Professor van Maanen realized that this was a misinterpretation of de Sluse's letter, and that what de Sluse was ''actually'' reporting that the solid "goblet" shape, formed by rotating the
cissoid of Diocles In geometry, the cissoid of Diocles (; named for Diocles) is a cubic plane curve notable for the property that it can be used to construct two mean proportionals to a given ratio. In particular, it can be used to double a cube. It can be de ...
and its asymptote about the ''y'' axis, had a finite volume (and hence "small weight") and enclosed a cavity of infinite volume. Huygens first showed that the area of the rotated two-dimensional shape (between the cissoid and its asymptote) was finite, calculating its area to be 3 times the area of the generating circle of the cissoid, and de Sluse applied
Pappus's centroid theorem In mathematics, Pappus's centroid theorem (also known as the Guldinus theorem, Pappus–Guldinus theorem or Pappus's theorem) is either of two related theorems dealing with the surface areas and volumes of surfaces and solids of revolution. The ...
to show that the solid of revolution thus has finite volume, being a product of that finite area and the finite orbit of rotation. The area ''being rotated'' is finite; de Sluse did not actually say anything about the surface area of the resultant rotated volume. Such a converse cannot occur (assuming
Euclidean geometry Euclidean geometry is a mathematical system attributed to ancient Greek mathematician Euclid, which he described in his textbook on geometry: the '' Elements''. Euclid's approach consists in assuming a small set of intuitively appealing axioms ...
) when revolving a continuous function on a closed set.


Theorem

Let be a continuously differentiable function. Write for the solid of revolution of the graph about the  axis. ''If the surface area of is finite, then so is the volume.''


Proof

Since the lateral surface area is finite, the
limit superior In mathematics, the limit inferior and limit superior of a sequence can be thought of as limiting (that is, eventual and extreme) bounds on the sequence. They can be thought of in a similar fashion for a function (see limit of a function). For a ...
: \begin \lim_ \sup_ f(x)^2 - f(1)^2 &= \limsup_ \int_1^t \left(f(x)^2\right)' \,\mathrmx \\ &\le \int_1^\infty \left, \left(f(x)^2\right)'\ \,\mathrmx = \int_1^\infty 2f(x) \left, f'(x)\ \,\mathrmx \\ &\le \int_1^\infty 2f(x) \sqrt \,\mathrmx = \frac \\ &< \infty. \end Therefore, there exists a such that the supremum is finite. Hence, M = \sup\ must be finite, since is a continuous function, which implies that is bounded on the interval . Finally, the volume: \begin V &= \int_1^\infty f(x) \cdot \pi f(x) \,\mathrmx \\ &\le \int_1^\infty \frac \cdot 2\pi f(x) \,\mathrmx \\ &\le \frac \cdot \int_1^\infty 2\pi f(x) \sqrt \,\mathrmx = \frac \cdot A. \end Therefore: ''if the area is finite, then the volume must also be finite.''


See also

* * * * * * *


References


Reference bibliography

* * * * * * * * * * * *


Further reading

* * * *


External links


Torricelli's trumpet at PlanetMath
*
"Gabriel's Horn"
by John Snyder, the
Wolfram Demonstrations Project The Wolfram Demonstrations Project is an organized, open-source collection of small (or medium-size) interactive programs called Demonstrations, which are meant to visually and interactively represent ideas from a range of fields. It is hos ...
, 2007.
Gabriel's Horn: An Understanding of a Solid with Finite Volume and Infinite Surface Area
by Jean S. Joseph. {{Calculus topics Mathematical paradoxes Paradoxes of infinity Calculus
Horn Horn most often refers to: *Horn (acoustic), a conical or bell shaped aperture used to guide sound ** Horn (instrument), collective name for tube-shaped wind musical instruments *Horn (anatomy), a pointed, bony projection on the head of various ...
Surfaces