Epsilon numbers (mathematics)
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
mathematics Mathematics is an area of knowledge that includes the topics of numbers, formulas and related structures, shapes and the spaces in which they are contained, and quantities and their changes. These topics are represented in modern mathematics ...
, the epsilon numbers are a collection of
transfinite number In mathematics, transfinite numbers are numbers that are "infinite" in the sense that they are larger than all finite numbers, yet not necessarily absolutely infinite. These include the transfinite cardinals, which are cardinal numbers used to qua ...
s whose defining property is that they are fixed points of an exponential map. Consequently, they are not reachable from 0 via a finite series of applications of the chosen exponential map and of "weaker" operations like addition and multiplication. The original epsilon numbers were introduced by
Georg Cantor Georg Ferdinand Ludwig Philipp Cantor ( , ;  – January 6, 1918) was a German mathematician. He played a pivotal role in the creation of set theory, which has become a fundamental theory in mathematics. Cantor established the importance of ...
in the context of
ordinal arithmetic In the mathematical field of set theory, ordinal arithmetic describes the three usual operations on ordinal numbers: addition, multiplication, and exponentiation. Each can be defined in essentially two different ways: either by constructing an expl ...
; they are the
ordinal numbers In set theory, an ordinal number, or ordinal, is a generalization of ordinal numerals (first, second, th, etc.) aimed to extend enumeration to infinite sets. A finite set can be enumerated by successively labeling each element with the least n ...
''ε'' that satisfy the
equation In mathematics, an equation is a formula that expresses the equality of two expressions, by connecting them with the equals sign . The word ''equation'' and its cognates in other languages may have subtly different meanings; for example, in ...
:\varepsilon = \omega^\varepsilon, \, in which ω is the smallest infinite ordinal. The least such ordinal is ''ε''0 (pronounced epsilon nought or epsilon zero), which can be viewed as the "limit" obtained by
transfinite recursion Transfinite induction is an extension of mathematical induction to well-ordered sets, for example to sets of ordinal numbers or cardinal numbers. Its correctness is a theorem of ZFC. Induction by cases Let P(\alpha) be a property defined for a ...
from a sequence of smaller limit ordinals: :\varepsilon_0 = \omega^ = \sup \\,, where is the
supremum In mathematics, the infimum (abbreviated inf; plural infima) of a subset S of a partially ordered set P is a greatest element in P that is less than or equal to each element of S, if such an element exists. Consequently, the term ''greatest l ...
function, which is equivalent to
set union In set theory, the union (denoted by ∪) of a collection of sets is the set of all elements in the collection. It is one of the fundamental operations through which sets can be combined and related to each other. A refers to a union of ze ...
in the case of the von Neumann representation of ordinals. Larger ordinal fixed points of the exponential map are indexed by ordinal subscripts, resulting in \varepsilon_1, \varepsilon_2,\ldots,\varepsilon_\omega, \varepsilon_, \ldots, \varepsilon_, \ldots, \varepsilon_, \ldots, \varepsilon_,\ldots.Stephen G. Simpson, ''Subsystems of Second-order Arithmetic'' (2009, p.387) The ordinal ε0 is still
countable In mathematics, a set is countable if either it is finite or it can be made in one to one correspondence with the set of natural numbers. Equivalently, a set is ''countable'' if there exists an injective function from it into the natural numbers ...
, as is any epsilon number whose index is countable (there exist uncountable ordinals, and uncountable epsilon numbers whose index is an uncountable ordinal). The smallest epsilon number ε0 appears in many
induction Induction, Inducible or Inductive may refer to: Biology and medicine * Labor induction (birth/pregnancy) * Induction chemotherapy, in medicine * Induced stem cells, stem cells derived from somatic, reproductive, pluripotent or other cell t ...
proofs, because for many purposes,
transfinite induction Transfinite induction is an extension of mathematical induction to well-ordered sets, for example to sets of ordinal numbers or cardinal numbers. Its correctness is a theorem of ZFC. Induction by cases Let P(\alpha) be a property defined for a ...
is only required up to ε0 (as in
Gentzen's consistency proof Gentzen's consistency proof is a result of proof theory in mathematical logic, published by Gerhard Gentzen in 1936. It shows that the Peano axioms of first-order arithmetic do not contain a contradiction (i.e. are "consistent"), as long as a cer ...
and the proof of
Goodstein's theorem In mathematical logic, Goodstein's theorem is a statement about the natural numbers, proved by Reuben Goodstein in 1944, which states that every ''Goodstein sequence'' eventually terminates at 0. Kirby and Paris showed that it is unprovable in Pe ...
). Its use by
Gentzen Gerhard Karl Erich Gentzen (24 November 1909 – 4 August 1945) was a German mathematician and logician. He made major contributions to the foundations of mathematics, proof theory, especially on natural deduction and sequent calculus. He died o ...
to prove the consistency of
Peano arithmetic In mathematical logic, the Peano axioms, also known as the Dedekind–Peano axioms or the Peano postulates, are axioms for the natural numbers presented by the 19th century Italian mathematician Giuseppe Peano. These axioms have been used nearly u ...
, along with Gödel's second incompleteness theorem, show that Peano arithmetic cannot prove the
well-foundedness In mathematics, a binary relation ''R'' is called well-founded (or wellfounded) on a class ''X'' if every non-empty subset ''S'' ⊆ ''X'' has a minimal element with respect to ''R'', that is, an element ''m'' not related by ''s&nb ...
of this ordering (it is in fact the least ordinal with this property, and as such, in proof-theoretic
ordinal analysis In proof theory, ordinal analysis assigns ordinals (often large countable ordinals) to mathematical theories as a measure of their strength. If theories have the same proof-theoretic ordinal they are often equiconsistent, and if one theory h ...
, is used as a measure of the strength of the theory of Peano arithmetic). Many larger epsilon numbers can be defined using the
Veblen function In mathematics, the Veblen functions are a hierarchy of normal functions ( continuous strictly increasing functions from ordinals to ordinals), introduced by Oswald Veblen in . If φ0 is any normal function, then for any non-zero ordinal α, φ ...
. A more general class of epsilon numbers has been identified by
John Horton Conway John Horton Conway (26 December 1937 – 11 April 2020) was an English mathematician active in the theory of finite groups, knot theory, number theory, combinatorial game theory and coding theory. He also made contributions to many branches ...
and
Donald Knuth Donald Ervin Knuth ( ; born January 10, 1938) is an American computer scientist, mathematician, and professor emeritus at Stanford University. He is the 1974 recipient of the ACM Turing Award, informally considered the Nobel Prize of computer sc ...
in the
surreal number In mathematics, the surreal number system is a totally ordered proper class containing the real numbers as well as infinite and infinitesimal numbers, respectively larger or smaller in absolute value than any positive real number. The surreals ...
system, consisting of all surreals that are fixed points of the base ω exponential map ''x'' → ω''x''. defined gamma numbers (see
additively indecomposable ordinal In set theory, a branch of mathematics, an additively indecomposable ordinal ''α'' is any ordinal number that is not 0 such that for any \beta,\gamma<\alpha, we have \beta+\gamma<\alpha. Additively indecomposable ordi ...
) to be numbers γ>0 such that α+γ=γ whenever α<γ, and delta numbers (see multiplicatively indecomposable ordinals) to be numbers δ>1 such that αδ=δ whenever 0<α<δ, and epsilon numbers to be numbers ''ε''>2 such that ''α''''ε''=''ε'' whenever 1<''α''<''ε''. His gamma numbers are those of the form ω''β'', and his delta numbers are those of the form ωω''β''.


Ordinal ε numbers

The standard definition of
ordinal exponentiation In the mathematical field of set theory, ordinal arithmetic describes the three usual operations on ordinal numbers: addition, multiplication, and exponentiation. Each can be defined in essentially two different ways: either by constructing an expl ...
with base α is: *\alpha^0 = 1 \,, *\alpha^\beta = \alpha^ \cdot \alpha \,, when \beta has an immediate predecessor \beta - 1. *\alpha^\beta=\sup \lbrace\alpha^\delta \mid 0 < \delta < \beta\rbrace, whenever \beta is a
limit ordinal In set theory, a limit ordinal is an ordinal number that is neither zero nor a successor ordinal. Alternatively, an ordinal λ is a limit ordinal if there is an ordinal less than λ, and whenever β is an ordinal less than λ, then there exists a ...
. From this definition, it follows that for any fixed ordinal , the mapping \beta \mapsto \alpha^\beta is a
normal function In axiomatic set theory, a function ''f'' : Ord → Ord is called normal (or a normal function) if and only if it is continuous (with respect to the order topology) and strictly monotonically increasing. This is equivalent to the following two c ...
, so it has arbitrarily large fixed points by the
fixed-point lemma for normal functions The fixed-point lemma for normal functions is a basic result in axiomatic set theory stating that any normal function has arbitrarily large fixed points (Levy 1979: p. 117). It was first proved by Oswald Veblen in 1908. Background and form ...
. When \alpha = \omega, these fixed points are precisely the ordinal epsilon numbers. *\varepsilon_0 = \sup \lbrace 1, \omega, \omega^\omega, \omega^, \omega^, \ldots\rbrace \,, *\varepsilon_\beta = \sup \lbrace , \omega^, \omega^, \omega^, \ldots\rbrace \,, when \beta has an immediate predecessor \beta - 1. *\varepsilon_\beta=\sup \lbrace \varepsilon_\delta \mid \delta < \beta \rbrace, whenever \beta is a limit ordinal. Because :\omega^ = \omega^ \cdot \omega^1 = \varepsilon_0 \cdot \omega \,, :\omega^ = \omega^ = ^\omega = \varepsilon_0^\omega \,, :\omega^ = \omega^ = \omega^ = \omega^ = ^ = ^ \,, a different sequence with the same supremum, \varepsilon_1, is obtained by starting from 0 and exponentiating with base ε0 instead: :\varepsilon_1 = \sup\, Generally, the epsilon number \varepsilon_ indexed by any ordinal that has an immediate predecessor \beta-1 can be constructed similarly. :\varepsilon_ = \sup\ In particular, whether or not the index β is a limit ordinal, \varepsilon_\beta is a fixed point not only of base ω exponentiation but also of base δ exponentiation for all ordinals 1 < \delta < \varepsilon_\beta. Since the epsilon numbers are an unbounded subclass of the ordinal numbers, they are enumerated using the ordinal numbers themselves. For any ordinal number \beta, \varepsilon_\beta is the least epsilon number (fixed point of the exponential map) not already in the set \. It might appear that this is the non-constructive equivalent of the constructive definition using iterated exponentiation; but the two definitions are equally non-constructive at steps indexed by limit ordinals, which represent transfinite recursion of a higher order than taking the supremum of an exponential series. The following facts about epsilon numbers are straightforward to prove: * Although it is quite a large number, \varepsilon_0 is still
countable In mathematics, a set is countable if either it is finite or it can be made in one to one correspondence with the set of natural numbers. Equivalently, a set is ''countable'' if there exists an injective function from it into the natural numbers ...
, being a countable union of countable ordinals; in fact, \varepsilon_\beta is countable if and only if \beta is countable. * The union (or supremum) of any nonempty set of epsilon numbers is an epsilon number; so for instance ::\varepsilon_\omega = \sup\ : is an epsilon number. Thus, the mapping \beta \mapsto \varepsilon_\beta is a normal function. * The
initial ordinal In a written or published work, an initial capital, also referred to as a drop capital or simply an initial cap, initial, initcapital, initcap or init or a drop cap or drop, is a letter at the beginning of a word, a chapter, or a paragraph that ...
of any
uncountable In mathematics, an uncountable set (or uncountably infinite set) is an infinite set that contains too many elements to be countable. The uncountability of a set is closely related to its cardinal number: a set is uncountable if its cardinal num ...
cardinal is an epsilon number. ::\alpha \ge 1 \Rightarrow \varepsilon_ = \omega_ \,.


Representation of ε0 by rooted trees

Any epsilon number ε has
Cantor normal form In the mathematical field of set theory, ordinal arithmetic describes the three usual operations on ordinal numbers: addition, multiplication, and exponentiation. Each can be defined in essentially two different ways: either by constructing an e ...
\varepsilon =\omega ^, which means that the Cantor normal form is not very useful for epsilon numbers. The ordinals less than ε0, however, can be usefully described by their Cantor normal forms, which leads to a representation of ε0 as the ordered set of all finite rooted trees, as follows. Any ordinal \alpha<\varepsilon_0 has Cantor normal form \alpha=\omega^+\omega^+\cdots+\omega^ where ''k'' is a natural number and \beta_1,\ldots,\beta_k are ordinals with \alpha>\beta_1\geq\cdots\geq\beta_k, uniquely determined by \alpha. Each of the ordinals \beta_1,\ldots,\beta_k in turn has a similar Cantor normal form. We obtain the finite rooted tree representing α by joining the roots of the trees representing \beta_1,\ldots,\beta_k to a new root. (This has the consequence that the number 0 is represented by a single root while the number 1=\omega^0 is represented by a tree containing a root and a single leaf.) An order on the set of finite rooted trees is defined recursively: we first order the subtrees joined to the root in decreasing order, and then use
lexicographic order In mathematics, the lexicographic or lexicographical order (also known as lexical order, or dictionary order) is a generalization of the alphabetical order of the dictionaries to sequences of ordered symbols or, more generally, of elements of a ...
on these ordered sequences of subtrees. In this way the set of all finite rooted trees becomes a
well-ordered set In mathematics, a well-order (or well-ordering or well-order relation) on a set ''S'' is a total order on ''S'' with the property that every non-empty subset of ''S'' has a least element in this ordering. The set ''S'' together with the well-ord ...
which is order-isomorphic to ε0. This representation is related to the proof of the hydra theorem, which represents decreasing sequences of ordinals as a graph-theoretic game.


Veblen hierarchy

The fixed points of the "epsilon mapping" x \mapsto \varepsilon_x form a normal function, whose fixed points form a normal function; this is known as the
Veblen hierarchy In mathematics, the Veblen functions are a hierarchy of normal functions (continuous function (set theory), continuous strictly increasing function, strictly increasing function (mathematics), functions from ordinal number, ordinals to ordinals), i ...
(the Veblen functions with base φ0(α) = ωα). In the notation of the Veblen hierarchy, the epsilon mapping is φ1, and its fixed points are enumerated by φ2. Continuing in this vein, one can define maps φα for progressively larger ordinals α (including, by this rarefied form of transfinite recursion, limit ordinals), with progressively larger least fixed points φα+1(0). The least ordinal not reachable from 0 by this procedure—i. e., the least ordinal α for which φα(0)=α, or equivalently the first fixed point of the map \alpha \mapsto \varphi_\alpha(0)—is the
Feferman–Schütte ordinal In mathematics, the Feferman–Schütte ordinal Γ0 is a large countable ordinal. It is the proof-theoretic ordinal of several mathematical theories, such as arithmetical transfinite recursion. It is named after Solomon Feferman and Kurt Schütte, ...
Γ0. In a set theory where such an ordinal can be proved to exist, one has a map Γ that enumerates the fixed points Γ0, Γ1, Γ2, ... of \alpha \mapsto \varphi_\alpha(0); these are all still epsilon numbers, as they lie in the image of φβ for every β ≤ Γ0, including of the map φ1 that enumerates epsilon numbers.


Surreal ε numbers

In ''
On Numbers and Games ''On Numbers and Games'' is a mathematics book by John Horton Conway first published in 1976. The book is written by a pre-eminent mathematician, and is directed at other mathematicians. The material is, however, developed in a playful and unpre ...
'', the classic exposition on
surreal number In mathematics, the surreal number system is a totally ordered proper class containing the real numbers as well as infinite and infinitesimal numbers, respectively larger or smaller in absolute value than any positive real number. The surreals ...
s,
John Horton Conway John Horton Conway (26 December 1937 – 11 April 2020) was an English mathematician active in the theory of finite groups, knot theory, number theory, combinatorial game theory and coding theory. He also made contributions to many branches ...
provided a number of examples of concepts that had natural extensions from the ordinals to the surreals. One such function is the \omega-map n \mapsto \omega^n; this mapping generalises naturally to include all surreal numbers in its
domain Domain may refer to: Mathematics *Domain of a function, the set of input values for which the (total) function is defined **Domain of definition of a partial function **Natural domain of a partial function **Domain of holomorphy of a function * Do ...
, which in turn provides a natural generalisation of the
Cantor normal form In the mathematical field of set theory, ordinal arithmetic describes the three usual operations on ordinal numbers: addition, multiplication, and exponentiation. Each can be defined in essentially two different ways: either by constructing an e ...
for surreal numbers. It is natural to consider any fixed point of this expanded map to be an epsilon number, whether or not it happens to be strictly an ordinal number. Some examples of non-ordinal epsilon numbers are :\varepsilon_ = \ and :\varepsilon_ = \. There is a natural way to define \varepsilon_n for every surreal number ''n'', and the map remains order-preserving. Conway goes on to define a broader class of "irreducible" surreal numbers that includes the epsilon numbers as a particularly-interesting subclass.


See also

*
Ordinal arithmetic In the mathematical field of set theory, ordinal arithmetic describes the three usual operations on ordinal numbers: addition, multiplication, and exponentiation. Each can be defined in essentially two different ways: either by constructing an expl ...
*
Large countable ordinal In the mathematical discipline of set theory, there are many ways of describing specific countable ordinals. The smallest ones can be usefully and non-circularly expressed in terms of their Cantor normal forms. Beyond that, many ordinals of rele ...


References

* J.H. Conway, ''On Numbers and Games'' (1976) Academic Press * Section XIV.20 of {{countable ordinals Ordinal numbers