The de Broglie–Bohm theory is an
interpretation of
quantum mechanics
Quantum mechanics is the fundamental physical Scientific theory, theory that describes the behavior of matter and of light; its unusual characteristics typically occur at and below the scale of atoms. Reprinted, Addison-Wesley, 1989, It is ...
which postulates that, in addition to the
wavefunction
In quantum physics, a wave function (or wavefunction) is a mathematical description of the quantum state of an isolated quantum system. The most common symbols for a wave function are the Greek letters and (lower-case and capital psi (letter) ...
, an actual configuration of particles exists, even when unobserved. The evolution over time of the configuration of all particles is defined by a
guiding equation. The evolution of the wave function over time is given by the
Schrödinger equation
The Schrödinger equation is a partial differential equation that governs the wave function of a non-relativistic quantum-mechanical system. Its discovery was a significant landmark in the development of quantum mechanics. It is named after E ...
. The theory is named after
Louis de Broglie (1892–1987) and
David Bohm
David Joseph Bohm (; 20 December 1917 – 27 October 1992) was an American scientist who has been described as one of the most significant Theoretical physics, theoretical physicists of the 20th centuryDavid Peat Who's Afraid of Schrödinger' ...
(1917–1992).
The theory is
deterministic
Determinism is the metaphysical view that all events within the universe (or multiverse) can occur only in one possible way. Deterministic theories throughout the history of philosophy have developed from diverse and sometimes overlapping mo ...
and explicitly
nonlocal: the velocity of any one particle depends on the value of the guiding equation, which depends on the configuration of all the particles under consideration.
Measurements are a particular case of quantum processes described by the theory—for which it yields the same quantum predictions as other interpretations of quantum mechanics. The theory does not have a "
measurement problem", due to the fact that the particles have a definite configuration at all times. The
Born rule in de Broglie–Bohm theory is not a postulate. Rather, in this theory, the link between the probability density and the wave function has the status of a theorem, a result of a separate postulate, the "
quantum equilibrium hypothesis", which is additional to the basic principles governing the wave function.
There are several equivalent
mathematical formulations of the theory.
Overview
De Broglie–Bohm theory is based on the following postulates:
* There is a configuration
of the universe, described by coordinates
, which is an element of the configuration space
. The configuration space is different for different versions of pilot-wave theory. For example, this may be the space of positions
of
particles, or, in case of field theory, the space of field configurations
. The configuration evolves (for spin=0) according to the guiding equation
where
is the
probability current or probability flux, and
is the
momentum operator. Here,
is the standard complex-valued wavefunction from quantum theory, which evolves according to the
Schrödinger equation
The Schrödinger equation is a partial differential equation that governs the wave function of a non-relativistic quantum-mechanical system. Its discovery was a significant landmark in the development of quantum mechanics. It is named after E ...
This completes the specification of the theory for any quantum theory with Hamilton operator of type
.
* The configuration is distributed according to
at some moment of time
, and this consequently holds for all times. Such a state is named quantum equilibrium. With quantum equilibrium, this theory agrees with the results of standard quantum mechanics.
Even though this latter relation is frequently presented as an axiom of the theory, Bohm presented it as derivable from statistical-mechanical arguments in the original papers of 1952. This argument was further supported by the work of Bohm in 1953 and was substantiated by Vigier and Bohm's paper of 1954, in which they introduced stochastic ''fluid fluctuations'' that drive a process of asymptotic relaxation from
quantum non-equilibrium to quantum equilibrium (ρ → , ψ,
2).
Double-slit experiment
The
double-slit experiment is an illustration of
wave–particle duality
Wave–particle duality is the concept in quantum mechanics that fundamental entities of the universe, like photons and electrons, exhibit particle or wave (physics), wave properties according to the experimental circumstances. It expresses the in ...
. In it, a beam of particles (such as electrons) travels through a barrier that has two slits. If a detector screen is on the side beyond the barrier, the pattern of detected particles shows interference fringes characteristic of waves arriving at the screen from two sources (the two slits); however, the interference pattern is made up of individual dots corresponding to particles that had arrived on the screen. The system seems to exhibit the behaviour of both waves (interference patterns) and particles (dots on the screen).
If this experiment is modified so that one slit is closed, no interference pattern is observed. Thus, the state of both slits affects the final results. It can also be arranged to have a minimally invasive detector at one of the slits to detect which slit the particle went through. When that is done, the interference pattern disappears.
In de Broglie–Bohm theory, the wavefunction is defined at both slits, but each particle has a well-defined trajectory that passes through exactly one of the slits. The final position of the particle on the detector screen and the slit through which the particle passes is determined by the initial position of the particle. Such initial position is not knowable or controllable by the experimenter, so there is an appearance of randomness in the pattern of detection. In Bohm's 1952 papers he used the wavefunction to construct a
quantum potential that, when included in Newton's equations, gave the trajectories of the particles streaming through the two slits. In effect the wavefunction interferes with itself and guides the particles by the quantum potential in such a way that the particles avoid the regions in which the interference is destructive and are attracted to the regions in which the interference is constructive, resulting in the interference pattern on the detector screen.
To explain the behavior when the particle is detected to go through one slit, one needs to appreciate the role of the conditional wavefunction and how it results in the collapse of the wavefunction; this is explained below. The basic idea is that the environment registering the detection effectively separates the two wave packets in configuration space.
Theory
Pilot wave
The de Broglie–Bohm theory describes a pilot wave
in a
configuration space and trajectories
of particles as in classical mechanics but defined by non-Newtonian mechanics. At every moment of time there exists not only a wavefunction, but also a well-defined configuration of the whole universe (i.e., the system as defined by the boundary conditions used in solving the Schrödinger equation).
The de Broglie–Bohm theory works on particle positions and trajectories like
classical mechanics
Classical mechanics is a Theoretical physics, physical theory describing the motion of objects such as projectiles, parts of Machine (mechanical), machinery, spacecraft, planets, stars, and galaxies. The development of classical mechanics inv ...
but the dynamics are different. In classical mechanics, the accelerations of the particles are imparted directly by forces, which exist in physical three-dimensional space. In de Broglie–Bohm theory, the quantum "field exerts a new kind of "quantum-mechanical" force". Bohm hypothesized that each particle has a "complex and subtle inner structure" that provides the capacity to react to the information provided by the wavefunction by the quantum potential. Also, unlike in classical mechanics, physical properties (e.g., mass, charge) are spread out over the wavefunction in de Broglie–Bohm theory, not localized at the position of the particle.
The wavefunction itself, and not the particles, determines the dynamical evolution of the system: the particles do not act back onto the wave function. As Bohm and Hiley worded it, "the Schrödinger equation for the quantum field does not have sources, nor does it have any other way by which the field could be directly affected by the condition of the particles
..the quantum theory can be understood completely in terms of the assumption that the quantum field has no sources or other forms of dependence on the particles". P. Holland considers this lack of reciprocal action of particles and wave function to be one "
ong the many nonclassical properties exhibited by this theory". Holland later called this a merely ''apparent'' lack of back reaction, due to the incompleteness of the description.
In what follows below, the setup for one particle moving in
is given followed by the setup for ''N'' particles moving in 3 dimensions. In the first instance, configuration space and real space are the same, while in the second, real space is still
, but configuration space becomes
. While the particle positions themselves are in real space, the velocity field and wavefunction are on configuration space, which is how particles are entangled with each other in this theory.
Extensions to this theory include spin and more complicated configuration spaces.
We use variations of
for particle positions, while
represents the complex-valued wavefunction on configuration space.
Guiding equation
For a spinless single particle moving in
, the particle's velocity is
:
For many particles labeled
for the
-th particle their velocities are
:
The main fact to notice is that this velocity field depends on the actual positions of all of the
particles in the universe. As explained below, in most experimental situations, the influence of all of those particles can be encapsulated into an effective wavefunction for a subsystem of the universe.
Schrödinger equation
The one-particle Schrödinger equation governs the time evolution of a complex-valued wavefunction on
. The equation represents a quantized version of the total energy of a classical system evolving under a real-valued potential function
on
:
:
For many particles, the equation is the same except that
and
are now on configuration space,
:
:
This is the same wavefunction as in conventional quantum mechanics.
Relation to the Born rule
In Bohm's original papers,
he discusses how de Broglie–Bohm theory results in the usual measurement results of quantum mechanics. The main idea is that this is true if the positions of the particles satisfy the statistical distribution given by
. And that distribution is guaranteed to be true for all time by the guiding equation if the initial distribution of the particles satisfies
.
For a given experiment, one can postulate this as being true and verify it experimentally. But, as argued by Dürr et al.,
one needs to argue that this distribution for subsystems is typical. The authors argue that
, by virtue of its equivariance under the dynamical evolution of the system, is the appropriate measure of typicality for
initial conditions of the positions of the particles. The authors then prove that the vast majority of possible initial configurations will give rise to statistics obeying the Born rule (i.e.,
) for measurement outcomes. In summary, in a universe governed by the de Broglie–Bohm dynamics, Born rule behavior is typical.
The situation is thus analogous to the situation in classical statistical physics. A low-
entropy
Entropy is a scientific concept, most commonly associated with states of disorder, randomness, or uncertainty. The term and the concept are used in diverse fields, from classical thermodynamics, where it was first recognized, to the micros ...
initial condition will, with overwhelmingly high probability, evolve into a higher-entropy state: behavior consistent with the
second law of thermodynamics
The second law of thermodynamics is a physical law based on Universal (metaphysics), universal empirical observation concerning heat and Energy transformation, energy interconversions. A simple statement of the law is that heat always flows spont ...
is typical. There are anomalous initial conditions that would give rise to violations of the second law; however in the absence of some very detailed evidence supporting the realization of one of those conditions, it would be quite unreasonable to expect anything but the actually observed uniform increase of entropy. Similarly in the de Broglie–Bohm theory, there are anomalous initial conditions that would produce measurement statistics in violation of the Born rule (conflicting the predictions of standard quantum theory), but the typicality theorem shows that absent some specific reason to believe one of those special initial conditions was in fact realized, the Born rule behavior is what one should expect.
It is in this qualified sense that the Born rule is, for the de Broglie–Bohm theory, a
theorem
In mathematics and formal logic, a theorem is a statement (logic), statement that has been Mathematical proof, proven, or can be proven. The ''proof'' of a theorem is a logical argument that uses the inference rules of a deductive system to esta ...
rather than (as in ordinary quantum theory) an additional
postulate.
It can also be shown that a distribution of particles which is ''not'' distributed according to the Born rule (that is, a distribution "out of quantum equilibrium") and evolving under the de Broglie–Bohm dynamics is overwhelmingly likely to evolve dynamically into a state distributed as
.
The conditional wavefunction of a subsystem
In the formulation of the de Broglie–Bohm theory, there is only a wavefunction for the entire universe (which always evolves by the Schrödinger equation). Here, the "universe" is simply the system limited by the same boundary conditions used to solve the Schrödinger equation. However, once the theory is formulated, it is convenient to introduce a notion of wavefunction also for subsystems of the universe. Let us write the wavefunction of the universe as
, where
denotes the configuration variables associated to some subsystem (I) of the universe, and
denotes the remaining configuration variables. Denote respectively by
and
the actual configuration of subsystem (I) and of the rest of the universe. For simplicity, we consider here only the spinless case. The ''conditional wavefunction'' of subsystem (I) is defined by
:
It follows immediately from the fact that
satisfies the guiding equation that also the configuration
satisfies a guiding equation identical to the one presented in the formulation of the theory, with the universal wavefunction
replaced with the conditional wavefunction
. Also, the fact that
is random with
probability density given by the
square modulus of
implies that the
conditional probability density of
given
is given by the square modulus of the (normalized) conditional wavefunction
(in the terminology of Dürr et al. this fact is called the ''fundamental conditional probability formula'').
Unlike the universal wavefunction, the conditional wavefunction of a subsystem does not always evolve by the Schrödinger equation, but in many situations it does. For instance, if the universal wavefunction factors as
:
then the conditional wavefunction of subsystem (I) is (up to an irrelevant scalar factor) equal to
(this is what standard quantum theory would regard as the wavefunction of subsystem (I)). If, in addition, the Hamiltonian does not contain an interaction term between subsystems (I) and (II), then
does satisfy a Schrödinger equation. More generally, assume that the universal wave function
can be written in the form
:
where
solves Schrödinger equation and,
for all
and
. Then, again, the conditional wavefunction of subsystem (I) is (up to an irrelevant scalar factor) equal to
, and if the Hamiltonian does not contain an interaction term between subsystems (I) and (II), then
satisfies a Schrödinger equation.
The fact that the conditional wavefunction of a subsystem does not always evolve by the Schrödinger equation is related to the fact that the usual collapse rule of standard quantum theory emerges from the Bohmian formalism when one considers conditional wavefunctions of subsystems.
Extensions
Relativity
Pilot-wave theory is explicitly nonlocal, which is in ostensible conflict with
special relativity
In physics, the special theory of relativity, or special relativity for short, is a scientific theory of the relationship between Spacetime, space and time. In Albert Einstein's 1905 paper, Annus Mirabilis papers#Special relativity,
"On the Ele ...
. Various extensions of "Bohm-like" mechanics exist that attempt to resolve this problem. Bohm himself in 1953 presented an extension of the theory satisfying the
Dirac equation
In particle physics, the Dirac equation is a relativistic wave equation derived by British physicist Paul Dirac in 1928. In its free form, or including electromagnetic interactions, it describes all spin-1/2 massive particles, called "Dirac ...
for a single particle. However, this was not extensible to the many-particle case because it used an absolute time.
A renewed interest in constructing
Lorentz-invariant extensions of Bohmian theory arose in the 1990s; see ''Bohm and Hiley: The Undivided Universe'' and references therein. Another approach is given by Dürr et al., who use Bohm–Dirac models and a Lorentz-invariant foliation of space-time.
Thus, Dürr et al. (1999) showed that it is possible to formally restore Lorentz invariance for the Bohm–Dirac theory by introducing additional structure. This approach still requires a
foliation
In mathematics (differential geometry), a foliation is an equivalence relation on an topological manifold, ''n''-manifold, the equivalence classes being connected, injective function, injectively immersed submanifolds, all of the same dimension ...
of space-time. While this is in conflict with the standard interpretation of relativity, the preferred foliation, if unobservable, does not lead to any empirical conflicts with relativity. In 2013, Dürr et al. suggested that the required foliation could be covariantly determined by the wavefunction.
The relation between nonlocality and preferred foliation can be better understood as follows. In de Broglie–Bohm theory, nonlocality manifests as the fact that the velocity and acceleration of one particle depends on the instantaneous positions of all other particles. On the other hand, in the theory of relativity the concept of instantaneousness does not have an invariant meaning. Thus, to define particle trajectories, one needs an additional rule that defines which space-time points should be considered instantaneous. The simplest way to achieve this is to introduce a preferred foliation of space-time by hand, such that each hypersurface of the foliation defines a hypersurface of equal time.
Initially, it had been considered impossible to set out a description of photon trajectories in the de Broglie–Bohm theory in view of the difficulties of describing bosons relativistically.
In 1996,
Partha Ghose presented a relativistic quantum-mechanical description of spin-0 and spin-1 bosons starting from the
Duffin–Kemmer–Petiau equation, setting out Bohmian trajectories for massive bosons and for massless bosons (and therefore
photon
A photon () is an elementary particle that is a quantum of the electromagnetic field, including electromagnetic radiation such as light and radio waves, and the force carrier for the electromagnetic force. Photons are massless particles that can ...
s).
In 2001,
Jean-Pierre Vigier emphasized the importance of deriving a well-defined description of light in terms of particle trajectories in the framework of either the Bohmian mechanics or the Nelson stochastic mechanics. The same year, Ghose worked out Bohmian photon trajectories for specific cases. Subsequent
weak-measurement experiments yielded trajectories that coincide with the predicted trajectories. The significance of these experimental findings is controversial.
Chris Dewdney and G. Horton have proposed a relativistically covariant, wave-functional formulation of Bohm's quantum field theory and have extended it to a form that allows the inclusion of gravity.
Nikolić has proposed a Lorentz-covariant formulation of the Bohmian interpretation of many-particle wavefunctions. He has developed a generalized relativistic-invariant probabilistic interpretation of quantum theory,
in which
is no longer a probability density in space, but a probability density in space-time. He uses this generalized probabilistic interpretation to formulate a relativistic-covariant version of de Broglie–Bohm theory without introducing a preferred foliation of space-time. His work also covers the extension of the Bohmian interpretation to a quantization of fields and strings.
Roderick I. Sutherland at the University in Sydney has a Lagrangian formalism for the pilot wave and its
beables. It draws on
Yakir Aharonov's retrocasual weak measurements to explain many-particle entanglement in a special relativistic way without the need for configuration space. The basic idea was already published by
Olivier Costa de Beauregard in the 1950s and is also used by
John Cramer in his transactional interpretation except the beables that exist between the von Neumann strong projection operator measurements. Sutherland's Lagrangian includes two-way action-reaction between pilot wave and beables. Therefore, it is a post-quantum non-statistical theory with final boundary conditions that violate the no-signal theorems of quantum theory. Just as special relativity is a limiting case of general relativity when the spacetime curvature vanishes, so, too is statistical no-entanglement signaling quantum theory with the Born rule a limiting case of the post-quantum action-reaction Lagrangian when the reaction is set to zero and the final boundary condition is integrated out.
Spin
To incorporate
spin, the wavefunction becomes complex-vector-valued. The value space is called spin space; for a
spin-1/2 particle, spin space can be taken to be
. The guiding equation is modified by taking
inner product
In mathematics, an inner product space (or, rarely, a Hausdorff pre-Hilbert space) is a real vector space or a complex vector space with an operation called an inner product. The inner product of two vectors in the space is a scalar, ofte ...
s in spin space to reduce the complex vectors to complex numbers. The Schrödinger equation is modified by adding a
Pauli spin term:
where
*
— the mass, charge and
magnetic moment
In electromagnetism, the magnetic moment or magnetic dipole moment is the combination of strength and orientation of a magnet or other object or system that exerts a magnetic field. The magnetic dipole moment of an object determines the magnitude ...
of the
–th particle
*
— the appropriate
spin operator acting in the
–th particle's spin space
*
—
spin quantum number
In physics and chemistry, the spin quantum number is a quantum number (designated ) that describes the intrinsic angular momentum (or spin angular momentum, or simply ''spin'') of an electron or other particle. It has the same value for all ...
of the
–th particle (
for electron)
*
is
vector potential in
*
is the
magnetic field
A magnetic field (sometimes called B-field) is a physical field that describes the magnetic influence on moving electric charges, electric currents, and magnetic materials. A moving charge in a magnetic field experiences a force perpendicular ...
in
*
is the covariant derivative, involving the vector potential, ascribed to the coordinates of
–th particle (in
SI units
The International System of Units, internationally known by the abbreviation SI (from French ), is the modern form of the metric system and the world's most widely used system of measurement. It is the only system of measurement with official st ...
)
*
— the wavefunction defined on the multidimensional configuration space; e.g. a system consisting of two spin-1/2 particles and one spin-1 particle has a wavefunction of the form
where
is a
tensor product
In mathematics, the tensor product V \otimes W of two vector spaces V and W (over the same field) is a vector space to which is associated a bilinear map V\times W \rightarrow V\otimes W that maps a pair (v,w),\ v\in V, w\in W to an element of ...
, so this spin space is 12-dimensional
*
is the
inner product
In mathematics, an inner product space (or, rarely, a Hausdorff pre-Hilbert space) is a real vector space or a complex vector space with an operation called an inner product. The inner product of two vectors in the space is a scalar, ofte ...
in spin space
:
Stochastic electrodynamics
Stochastic electrodynamics (SED) is an extension of the de Broglie–Bohm interpretation of
quantum mechanics
Quantum mechanics is the fundamental physical Scientific theory, theory that describes the behavior of matter and of light; its unusual characteristics typically occur at and below the scale of atoms. Reprinted, Addison-Wesley, 1989, It is ...
, with the electromagnetic
zero-point field (ZPF) playing a central role as the guiding
pilot-wave. Modern approaches to SED, like those proposed by the group around late Gerhard Grössing, among others, consider wave and particle-like quantum effects as well-coordinated emergent systems. These emergent systems are the result of speculated and calculated sub-quantum interactions with the zero-point field.
Quantum field theory
In Dürr et al.,
the authors describe an extension of de Broglie–Bohm theory for handling
creation and annihilation operators
Creation operators and annihilation operators are Operator (mathematics), mathematical operators that have widespread applications in quantum mechanics, notably in the study of quantum harmonic oscillators and many-particle systems. An annihilatio ...
, which they refer to as "Bell-type quantum field theories". The basic idea is that configuration space becomes the (disjoint) space of all possible configurations of any number of particles. For part of the time, the system evolves deterministically under the guiding equation with a fixed number of particles. But under a
stochastic process
In probability theory and related fields, a stochastic () or random process is a mathematical object usually defined as a family of random variables in a probability space, where the index of the family often has the interpretation of time. Sto ...
, particles may be created and annihilated. The distribution of creation events is dictated by the wavefunction. The wavefunction itself is evolving at all times over the full multi-particle configuration space.
Hrvoje Nikolić
introduces a purely deterministic de Broglie–Bohm theory of particle creation and destruction, according to which particle trajectories are continuous, but particle detectors behave as if particles have been created or destroyed even when a true creation or destruction of particles does not take place.
Curved space
To extend de Broglie–Bohm theory to curved space (
Riemannian manifolds in mathematical parlance), one simply notes that all of the elements of these equations make sense, such as
gradient
In vector calculus, the gradient of a scalar-valued differentiable function f of several variables is the vector field (or vector-valued function) \nabla f whose value at a point p gives the direction and the rate of fastest increase. The g ...
s and
Laplacian
In mathematics, the Laplace operator or Laplacian is a differential operator given by the divergence of the gradient of a scalar function on Euclidean space. It is usually denoted by the symbols \nabla\cdot\nabla, \nabla^2 (where \nabla is th ...
s. Thus, we use equations that have the same form as above. Topological and
boundary conditions may apply in supplementing the evolution of the Schrödinger equation.
For a de Broglie–Bohm theory on curved space with spin, the spin space becomes a
vector bundle
In mathematics, a vector bundle is a topological construction that makes precise the idea of a family of vector spaces parameterized by another space X (for example X could be a topological space, a manifold, or an algebraic variety): to eve ...
over configuration space, and the potential in the Schrödinger equation becomes a local self-adjoint operator acting on that space.
The field equations for the de Broglie–Bohm theory in the relativistic case with spin can also be given for curved space-times with torsion.
In a general spacetime with curvature and torsion, the guiding equation for the
four-velocity of an elementary
fermion
In particle physics, a fermion is a subatomic particle that follows Fermi–Dirac statistics. Fermions have a half-integer spin (spin 1/2, spin , Spin (physics)#Higher spins, spin , etc.) and obey the Pauli exclusion principle. These particles i ...
particle is
where the wave function
is a
spinor
In geometry and physics, spinors (pronounced "spinner" IPA ) are elements of a complex numbers, complex vector space that can be associated with Euclidean space. A spinor transforms linearly when the Euclidean space is subjected to a slight (infi ...
,
is the corresponding
adjoint,
are the
Dirac matrices, and
is a
tetrad.
If the wave function propagates according to the
curved Dirac equation, then the particle moves according to the
Mathisson-Papapetrou equations of motion, which are an extension of the
geodesic equation. This relativistic wave-particle duality follows from the
conservation laws for the
spin tensor and
energy-momentum tensor,
and also from the covariant
Heisenberg picture
In physics, the Heisenberg picture or Heisenberg representation is a Dynamical pictures, formulation (largely due to Werner Heisenberg in 1925) of quantum mechanics in which observables incorporate a dependency on time, but the quantum state, st ...
equation of motion.
Exploiting nonlocality
De Broglie and Bohm's causal interpretation of quantum mechanics was later extended by Bohm, Vigier, Hiley, Valentini and others to include stochastic properties. Bohm and other physicists, including Valentini, view the Born rule linking
to the
probability density function
In probability theory, a probability density function (PDF), density function, or density of an absolutely continuous random variable, is a Function (mathematics), function whose value at any given sample (or point) in the sample space (the s ...
as representing not a basic law, but a result of a system having reached ''quantum equilibrium'' during the course of the time development under the
Schrödinger equation
The Schrödinger equation is a partial differential equation that governs the wave function of a non-relativistic quantum-mechanical system. Its discovery was a significant landmark in the development of quantum mechanics. It is named after E ...
. It can be shown that, once an equilibrium has been reached, the system remains in such equilibrium over the course of its further evolution: this follows from the
continuity equation associated with the Schrödinger evolution of
. It is less straightforward to demonstrate whether and how such an equilibrium is reached in the first place.
Antony Valentini has extended de Broglie–Bohm theory to include signal nonlocality that would allow entanglement to be used as a stand-alone communication channel without a secondary classical "key" signal to "unlock" the message encoded in the entanglement. This violates orthodox quantum theory but has the virtue of making the parallel universes of the
chaotic inflation theory observable in principle.
Unlike de Broglie–Bohm theory, Valentini's theory the wavefunction evolution also depends on the ontological variables. This introduces an instability, a feedback loop that pushes the hidden variables out of "sub-quantal heat death". The resulting theory becomes nonlinear and non-unitary. Valentini argues that the laws of quantum mechanics are
emergent and form a "quantum equilibrium" that is analogous to thermal equilibrium in classical dynamics, such that other "
quantum non-equilibrium" distributions may in principle be observed and exploited, for which the statistical predictions of quantum theory are violated. It is controversially argued that quantum theory is merely a special case of a much wider nonlinear physics, a physics in which non-local (
superluminal) signalling is possible, and in which the uncertainty principle can be violated.
Results
Below are some highlights of the results that arise out of an analysis of de Broglie–Bohm theory. Experimental results agree with all of quantum mechanics' standard predictions insofar as it has them. But while standard quantum mechanics is limited to discussing the results of "measurements", de Broglie–Bohm theory governs the dynamics of a system without the intervention of outside observers (p. 117 in Bell
).
The basis for agreement with standard quantum mechanics is that the particles are distributed according to
. This is a statement of observer ignorance: the initial positions are represented by a statistical distribution so deterministic trajectories will result in a statistical distribution.
Measuring spin and polarization
According to ordinary quantum theory, it is not possible to measure the
spin or
polarization of a particle directly; instead, the component in one direction is measured; the outcome from a single particle may be 1, meaning that the particle is aligned with the measuring apparatus, or −1, meaning that it is aligned the opposite way. An ensemble of particles prepared by a polarizer to be in state 1 will all measure polarized in state 1 in a subsequent apparatus. A polarized ensemble sent through a polarizer set at angle to the first pass will result in some values of 1 and some of −1 with a probability that depends on the relative alignment. For a full explanation of this, see the
Stern–Gerlach experiment.
In de Broglie–Bohm theory, the results of a spin experiment cannot be analyzed without some knowledge of the experimental setup. It is possible to modify the setup so that the trajectory of the particle is unaffected, but that the particle with one setup registers as spin-up, while in the other setup it registers as spin-down. Thus, for the de Broglie–Bohm theory, the particle's spin is not an intrinsic property of the particle; instead spin is, so to speak, in the wavefunction of the particle in relation to the particular device being used to measure the spin. This is an illustration of what is sometimes referred to as contextuality and is related to naive realism about operators. Interpretationally, measurement results are a deterministic property of the system and its environment, which includes information about the experimental setup including the context of co-measured observables; in no sense does the system itself possess the property being measured, as would have been the case in classical physics.
Measurements, the quantum formalism, and observer independence
De Broglie–Bohm theory gives almost the same results as (non-relativisitic) quantum mechanics. It treats the wavefunction as a fundamental object in the theory, as the wavefunction describes how the particles move. This means that no experiment can distinguish between the two theories. This section outlines the ideas as to how the standard quantum formalism arises out of quantum mechanics.
Collapse of the wavefunction
De Broglie–Bohm theory is a theory that applies primarily to the whole universe. That is, there is a single wavefunction governing the motion of all of the particles in the universe according to the guiding equation. Theoretically, the motion of one particle depends on the positions of all of the other particles in the universe. In some situations, such as in experimental systems, we can represent the system itself in terms of a de Broglie–Bohm theory in which the wavefunction of the system is obtained by conditioning on the environment of the system. Thus, the system can be analyzed with the Schrödinger equation and the guiding equation, with an initial
distribution for the particles in the system (see the section on
the conditional wavefunction of a subsystem for details).
It requires a special setup for the conditional wavefunction of a system to obey a quantum evolution. When a system interacts with its environment, such as through a measurement, the conditional wavefunction of the system evolves in a different way. The evolution of the universal wavefunction can become such that the wavefunction of the system appears to be in a superposition of distinct states. But if the environment has recorded the results of the experiment, then using the actual Bohmian configuration of the environment to condition on, the conditional wavefunction collapses to just one alternative, the one corresponding with the measurement results.
Collapse of the universal wavefunction never occurs in de Broglie–Bohm theory. Its entire evolution is governed by the Schrödinger equation, and the particles' evolutions are governed by the guiding equation. Collapse only occurs in a
phenomenological way for systems that seem to follow their own Schrödinger equation. As this is an effective description of the system, it is a matter of choice as to what to define the experimental system to include, and this will affect when "collapse" occurs.
Operators as observables
In the standard quantum formalism, measuring observables is generally thought of as measuring operators on the Hilbert space. For example, measuring position is considered to be a measurement of the position operator. This relationship between physical measurements and Hilbert space operators is, for standard quantum mechanics, an additional axiom of the theory. The de Broglie–Bohm theory, by contrast, requires no such measurement axioms (and measurement as such is not a dynamically distinct or special sub-category of physical processes in the theory). In particular, the usual operators-as-observables formalism is, for de Broglie–Bohm theory, a theorem. A major point of the analysis is that many of the measurements of the observables do not correspond to properties of the particles; they are (as in the case of spin discussed above) measurements of the wavefunction.
In the history of de Broglie–Bohm theory, the proponents have often had to deal with claims that this theory is impossible. Such arguments are generally based on inappropriate analysis of operators as observables. If one believes that spin measurements are indeed measuring the spin of a particle that existed prior to the measurement, then one does reach contradictions. De Broglie–Bohm theory deals with this by noting that spin is not a feature of the particle, but rather that of the wavefunction. As such, it only has a definite outcome once the experimental apparatus is chosen. Once that is taken into account, the impossibility theorems become irrelevant.
There are also objections to this theory based on what it says about particular situations usually involving eigenstates of an operator. For example, the ground state of hydrogen is a real wavefunction. According to the guiding equation, this means that the electron is at rest when in this state. Nevertheless, it is distributed according to
, and no contradiction to experimental results is possible to detect.
Operators as observables leads many to believe that many operators are equivalent. De Broglie–Bohm theory, from this perspective, chooses the position observable as a favored observable rather than, say, the momentum observable. Again, the link to the position observable is a consequence of the dynamics. The motivation for de Broglie–Bohm theory is to describe a system of particles. This implies that the goal of the theory is to describe the positions of those particles at all times. Other observables do not have this compelling ontological status. Having definite positions explains having definite results such as flashes on a detector screen. Other observables would not lead to that conclusion, but there need not be any problem in defining a mathematical theory for other observables; see Hyman et al. for an exploration of the fact that a probability density and probability current can be defined for any set of commuting operators.
Hidden variables
De Broglie–Bohm theory is often referred to as a "hidden-variable" theory. Bohm used this description in his original papers on the subject, writing: "From the point of view of the
usual interpretation, these additional elements or parameters
ermitting a detailed causal and continuous description of all processescould be called 'hidden' variables." Bohm and Hiley later stated that they found Bohm's choice of the term "hidden variables" to be too restrictive. In particular, they argued that a particle is not actually hidden but rather "is what is most directly manifested in an observation
houghits properties cannot be observed with arbitrary precision (within the limits set by
uncertainty principle
The uncertainty principle, also known as Heisenberg's indeterminacy principle, is a fundamental concept in quantum mechanics. It states that there is a limit to the precision with which certain pairs of physical properties, such as position a ...
)". However, others nevertheless treat the term "hidden variable" as a suitable description.
Generalized particle trajectories can be extrapolated from numerous weak measurements on an ensemble of equally prepared systems, and such trajectories coincide with the de Broglie–Bohm trajectories. In particular, an experiment with two entangled photons, in which a set of Bohmian trajectories for one of the photons was determined using weak measurements and postselection, can be understood in terms of a nonlocal connection between that photon's trajectory and the other photon's polarization.
[Anil Ananthaswamy]
Quantum weirdness may hide an orderly reality after all
newscientist.com, 19 February 2016. However, not only the De Broglie–Bohm interpretation, but also many other interpretations of quantum mechanics that do not include such trajectories are consistent with such experimental evidence.
Different predictions
A specialized version of the
double slit experiment
In modern physics, the double-slit experiment demonstrates that light and matter can exhibit behavior of both classical Particle, particles and classical Wave, waves. This type of experiment was first performed by Thomas Young (scientist), Thom ...
has been devised to test characteristics of the trajectory predictions.
Results from one such experiment agreed with the predictions of standard quantum mechanics and disagreed with the Bohm predictions when they conflicted. These conclusions have been the subject of debate.
Heisenberg's uncertainty principle
The Heisenberg's uncertainty principle states that when two complementary measurements are made, there is a limit to the product of their accuracy. As an example, if one measures the position with an accuracy of
and the momentum with an accuracy of
, then
In de Broglie–Bohm theory, there is always a matter of fact about the position and momentum of a particle. Each particle has a well-defined trajectory, as well as a wavefunction. Observers have limited knowledge as to what this trajectory is (and thus of the position and momentum). It is the lack of knowledge of the particle's trajectory that accounts for the uncertainty relation. What one can know about a particle at any given time is described by the wavefunction. Since the uncertainty relation can be derived from the wavefunction in other interpretations of quantum mechanics, it can be likewise derived (in the
epistemic sense mentioned above) on the de Broglie–Bohm theory.
To put the statement differently, the particles' positions are only known statistically. As in
classical mechanics
Classical mechanics is a Theoretical physics, physical theory describing the motion of objects such as projectiles, parts of Machine (mechanical), machinery, spacecraft, planets, stars, and galaxies. The development of classical mechanics inv ...
, successive observations of the particles' positions refine the experimenter's knowledge of the particles'
initial conditions. Thus, with succeeding observations, the initial conditions become more and more restricted. This formalism is consistent with the normal use of the Schrödinger equation.
For the derivation of the uncertainty relation, see
Heisenberg uncertainty principle
The uncertainty principle, also known as Heisenberg's indeterminacy principle, is a fundamental concept in quantum mechanics. It states that there is a limit to the precision with which certain pairs of physical properties, such as position a ...
, noting that this article describes the principle from the viewpoint of the
Copenhagen interpretation.
Quantum entanglement, Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen paradox, Bell's theorem, and nonlocality
De Broglie–Bohm theory highlighted the issue of
nonlocality: it inspired
John Stewart Bell
John Stewart Bell (28 July 1928 – 1 October 1990) was a physicist from Northern Ireland and the originator of Bell's theorem, an important theorem in quantum mechanics, quantum physics regarding hidden-variable theory, hidden-variable theor ...
to prove his now-famous
theorem
In mathematics and formal logic, a theorem is a statement (logic), statement that has been Mathematical proof, proven, or can be proven. The ''proof'' of a theorem is a logical argument that uses the inference rules of a deductive system to esta ...
, which in turn led to the
Bell test experiments.
In the
Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen paradox, the authors describe a thought experiment that one could perform on a pair of particles that have interacted, the results of which they interpreted as indicating that quantum mechanics is an incomplete theory.
Decades later
John Bell proved
Bell's theorem
Bell's theorem is a term encompassing a number of closely related results in physics, all of which determine that quantum mechanics is incompatible with local hidden-variable theories, given some basic assumptions about the nature of measuremen ...
(see p. 14 in Bell
), in which he showed that, if they are to agree with the empirical predictions of quantum mechanics, all such "hidden-variable" completions of quantum mechanics must either be nonlocal (as the Bohm interpretation is) or give up the assumption that experiments produce unique results (see
counterfactual definiteness and
many-worlds interpretation
The many-worlds interpretation (MWI) is an interpretation of quantum mechanics that asserts that the universal wavefunction is Philosophical realism, objectively real, and that there is no wave function collapse. This implies that all Possible ...
). In particular, Bell proved that any local theory with unique results must make empirical predictions satisfying a statistical constraint called "Bell's inequality".
Alain Aspect performed a series of
Bell test experiments that test Bell's inequality using an EPR-type setup. Aspect's results show experimentally that Bell's inequality is in fact violated, meaning that the relevant quantum-mechanical predictions are correct. In these Bell test experiments, entangled pairs of particles are created; the particles are separated, traveling to remote measuring apparatus. The orientation of the measuring apparatus can be changed while the particles are in flight, demonstrating the apparent nonlocality of the effect.
The de Broglie–Bohm theory makes the same (empirically correct) predictions for the Bell test experiments as ordinary quantum mechanics. It is able to do this because it is manifestly nonlocal. It is often criticized or rejected based on this; Bell's attitude was: "It is a merit of the de Broglie–Bohm version to bring this
onlocalityout so explicitly that it cannot be ignored."
The de Broglie–Bohm theory describes the physics in the Bell test experiments as follows: to understand the evolution of the particles, we need to set up a wave equation for both particles; the orientation of the apparatus affects the wavefunction. The particles in the experiment follow the guidance of the wavefunction. It is the wavefunction that carries the faster-than-light effect of changing the orientation of the apparatus.
Maudlin provides an analysis of exactly what kind of nonlocality is present and how it is compatible with relativity. Bell has shown that the nonlocality does not allow
superluminal communication. Maudlin has shown this in greater detail.
Classical limit
Bohm's formulation of de Broglie–Bohm theory in a classical-looking version has the merits that the emergence of classical behavior seems to follow immediately for any situation in which the quantum potential is negligible, as noted by Bohm in 1952. Modern methods of
decoherence are relevant to an analysis of this limit. See Allori et al. for steps towards a rigorous analysis.
Quantum trajectory method
Work by
Robert E. Wyatt in the early 2000s attempted to use the Bohm "particles" as an adaptive mesh that follows the actual trajectory of a quantum state in time and space. In the "quantum trajectory" method, one samples the quantum wavefunction with a mesh of quadrature points. One then evolves the quadrature points in time according to the Bohm equations of motion. At each time step, one then re-synthesizes the wavefunction from the points, recomputes the quantum forces, and continues the calculation. (QuickTime movies of this for H + H
2 reactive scattering can be found on th
Wyatt group web-siteat UT Austin.)
This approach has been adapted, extended, and used by a number of researchers in the chemical physics community as a way to compute semi-classical and quasi-classical molecular dynamics. A 2007 issue of
The Journal of Physical Chemistry A was dedicated to Prof. Wyatt and his work on "computational Bohmian dynamics".
Eric R. Bittner's group
at the
University of Houston
The University of Houston (; ) is a Public university, public research university in Houston, Texas, United States. It was established in 1927 as Houston Junior College, a coeducational institution and one of multiple junior colleges formed in ...
has advanced a statistical variant of this approach that uses Bayesian sampling technique to sample the quantum density and compute the quantum potential on a structureless mesh of points. This technique was recently used to estimate quantum effects in the heat capacity of small clusters Ne
n for ''n'' ≈ 100.
There remain difficulties using the Bohmian approach, mostly associated with the formation of singularities in the quantum potential due to nodes in the quantum wavefunction. In general, nodes forming due to interference effects lead to the case where
This results in an infinite force on the sample particles forcing them to move away from the node and often crossing the path of other sample points (which violates single-valuedness). Various schemes have been developed to overcome this; however, no general solution has yet emerged.
These methods, as does Bohm's Hamilton–Jacobi formulation, do not apply to situations in which the full dynamics of spin need to be taken into account.
The properties of trajectories in the de Broglie–Bohm theory differ significantly from the
Moyal quantum trajectories as well as the
quantum trajectories from the unraveling of an open quantum system.
Similarities with the many-worlds interpretation
Kim Joris Boström has proposed a non-relativistic quantum mechanical theory that combines elements of de Broglie-Bohm mechanics and
Everett's many-worlds. In particular, the unreal many-worlds interpretation of Hawking and Weinberg is similar to the Bohmian concept of unreal empty branch worlds:
Many authors have expressed critical views of de Broglie–Bohm theory by comparing it to Everett's many-worlds approach. Many (but not all) proponents of de Broglie–Bohm theory (such as Bohm and Bell) interpret the universal wavefunction as physically real. According to some supporters of Everett's theory, if the (never collapsing) wavefunction is taken to be physically real, then it is natural to interpret the theory as having the same many worlds as Everett's theory. In the Everettian view the role of the Bohmian particle is to act as a "pointer", tagging, or selecting, just one branch of the
universal wavefunction
The universal wavefunction or the wavefunction of the universe is the wavefunction or quantum state of the entire universe. It is regarded as the basic physical entity in the many-worlds interpretation of quantum mechanics,Hugh Everett, Relative St ...
(the assumption that this branch indicates which ''wave packet'' determines the observed result of a given experiment is called the "result assumption"
); the other branches are designated "empty" and implicitly assumed by Bohm to be devoid of conscious observers.
H. Dieter Zeh comments on these "empty" branches:
David Deutsch
David Elieser Deutsch ( ; ; born 18 May 1953) is a British physicist at the University of Oxford, often described as the "father of quantum computing". He is a visiting professor in the Department of Atomic and Laser Physics at the Centre for ...
has expressed the same point more "acerbically":
This conclusion has been challenged by Detlef Dürr and Justin Lazarovici:
The Bohmian, of course, cannot accept this argument. For her, it is decidedly the particle configuration in three-dimensional space and not the wave function on the abstract configuration space that constitutes a world (or rather, the world). Instead, she will accuse the Everettian of not having local beables (in Bell's sense) in her theory, that is, the ontological variables that refer to localized entities in three-dimensional space or four-dimensional spacetime. The many worlds of her theory thus merely appear as a grotesque consequence of this omission.
Occam's-razor criticism
Both
Hugh Everett III and Bohm treated the wavefunction as a
physically real field. Everett's
many-worlds interpretation
The many-worlds interpretation (MWI) is an interpretation of quantum mechanics that asserts that the universal wavefunction is Philosophical realism, objectively real, and that there is no wave function collapse. This implies that all Possible ...
is an attempt to demonstrate that the wavefunction alone is sufficient to account for all our observations. When we see the particle detectors flash or hear the click of a
Geiger counter, Everett's theory interprets this as our ''wavefunction'' responding to changes in the detector's ''wavefunction'', which is responding in turn to the passage of another ''wavefunction'' (which we think of as a "particle", but is actually just another
wave packet
In physics, a wave packet (also known as a wave train or wave group) is a short burst of localized wave action that travels as a unit, outlined by an Envelope (waves), envelope. A wave packet can be analyzed into, or can be synthesized from, a ...
).
[ Abstract: "The quantum theory of de Broglie and Bohm solves the measurement problem, but the hypothetical corpuscles play no role in the argument. The solution finds a more natural home in the Everett interpretation."] No particle (in the Bohm sense of having a defined position and velocity) exists according to that theory. For this reason Everett sometimes referred to his own
many-worlds approach as the "pure wave theory". Of Bohm's 1952 approach, Everett said:
In the Everettian view, then, the Bohm particles are superfluous entities, similar to, and equally as unnecessary as, for example, the
luminiferous ether, which was found to be unnecessary in
special relativity
In physics, the special theory of relativity, or special relativity for short, is a scientific theory of the relationship between Spacetime, space and time. In Albert Einstein's 1905 paper, Annus Mirabilis papers#Special relativity,
"On the Ele ...
. This argument is sometimes called the "redundancy argument", since the superfluous particles are redundant in the sense of
Occam's razor
In philosophy, Occam's razor (also spelled Ockham's razor or Ocham's razor; ) is the problem-solving principle that recommends searching for explanations constructed with the smallest possible set of elements. It is also known as the principle o ...
.
According to
Brown
Brown is a color. It can be considered a composite color, but it is mainly a darker shade of orange. In the CMYK color model used in printing and painting, brown is usually made by combining the colors Orange (colour), orange and black.
In the ...
& Wallace,
the de Broglie–Bohm particles play no role in the solution of the measurement problem. For these authors,
the "result assumption" (see above) is inconsistent with the view that there is no measurement problem in the predictable outcome (i.e. single-outcome) case. They also say
that a standard
tacit assumption
A tacit assumption or implicit assumption is an assumption that underlies a logical argument, course of action, Decision-making, decision, or judgment that is not explicitly voiced nor necessarily understood by the decision maker or judge. These as ...
of de Broglie–Bohm theory (that an observer becomes aware of configurations of particles of ordinary objects by means of correlations between such configurations and the configuration of the particles in the observer's brain) is unreasonable. This conclusion has been challenged by
Valentini, who argues that the entirety of such objections arises from a failure to interpret de Broglie–Bohm theory on its own terms.
According to
Peter R. Holland, in a wider Hamiltonian framework, theories can be formulated in which particles ''do'' act back on the wave function.
Derivations
De Broglie–Bohm theory has been derived many times and in many ways. Below are six derivations, all of which are very different and lead to different ways of understanding and extending this theory.
* The
Schrödinger equation
The Schrödinger equation is a partial differential equation that governs the wave function of a non-relativistic quantum-mechanical system. Its discovery was a significant landmark in the development of quantum mechanics. It is named after E ...
can be derived by using
Einstein's light quanta hypothesis:
and
de Broglie's hypothesis:
.
: The guiding equation can be derived in a similar fashion. We assume a plane wave:
. Notice that
. Assuming that
for the particle's actual velocity, we have that
. Thus, we have the guiding equation.
: Notice that this derivation does not use the Schrödinger equation.
* Preserving the density under the time evolution is another method of derivation. This is the method that Bell cites. It is this method that generalizes to many possible alternative theories. The starting point is the
continuity equation for the density
. This equation describes a probability flow along a current. We take the velocity field associated with this current as the velocity field whose integral curves yield the motion of the particle.
* A method applicable for particles without spin is to do a polar decomposition of the wavefunction and transform the Schrödinger equation into two coupled equations: the
continuity equation from above and the
Hamilton–Jacobi equation
In physics, the Hamilton–Jacobi equation, named after William Rowan Hamilton and Carl Gustav Jacob Jacobi, is an alternative formulation of classical mechanics, equivalent to other formulations such as Newton's laws of motion, Lagrangian mecha ...
. This is the method used by Bohm in 1952. The decomposition and equations are as follows:
: Decomposition:
Note that
corresponds to the probability density
.
: Continuity equation:
.
: Hamilton–Jacobi equation:
: The Hamilton–Jacobi equation is the equation derived from a Newtonian system with potential
and velocity field
The potential
is the classical potential that appears in the Schrödinger equation, and the other term involving
is the
quantum potential, terminology introduced by Bohm.
: This leads to viewing the quantum theory as particles moving under the classical force modified by a quantum force. However, unlike standard
Newtonian mechanics
Newton's laws of motion are three physical laws that describe the relationship between the motion of an object and the forces acting on it. These laws, which provide the basis for Newtonian mechanics, can be paraphrased as follows:
# A body r ...
, the initial velocity field is already specified by
, which is a symptom of this being a first-order theory, not a second-order theory.
* A fourth derivation was given by Dürr et al.
In their derivation, they derive the velocity field by demanding the appropriate transformation properties given by the various symmetries that the Schrödinger equation satisfies, once the wavefunction is suitably transformed. The guiding equation is what emerges from that analysis.
* A fifth derivation, given by Dürr et al.
is appropriate for generalization to quantum field theory and the Dirac equation. The idea is that a velocity field can also be understood as a first-order differential operator acting on functions. Thus, if we know how it acts on functions, we know what it is. Then given the Hamiltonian operator
, the equation to satisfy for all functions
(with associated multiplication operator
) is
, where
is the local Hermitian inner product on the value space of the wavefunction.
: This formulation allows for stochastic theories such as the creation and annihilation of particles.
* A further derivation has been given by Peter R. Holland, on which he bases his quantum-physics textbook ''The Quantum Theory of Motion''. It is based on three basic postulates and an additional fourth postulate that links the wavefunction to measurement probabilities:
*# A physical system consists in a spatiotemporally propagating wave and a point particle guided by it.
*# The wave is described mathematically by a solution
to the Schrödinger wave equation.
*# The particle motion is described by a solution to
in dependence on initial condition
, with
the phase of
.The fourth postulate is subsidiary yet consistent with the first three:
*# The probability
to find the particle in the differential volume
at time ''t'' equals
.
History
The theory was historically developed in the 1920s by de Broglie, who, in 1927, was persuaded to abandon it in favour of the then-mainstream Copenhagen interpretation. David Bohm, dissatisfied with the prevailing orthodoxy, rediscovered de Broglie's pilot-wave theory in 1952. Bohm's suggestions were not then widely received, partly due to reasons unrelated to their content, such as Bohm's youthful
communist
Communism () is a sociopolitical, philosophical, and economic ideology within the socialist movement, whose goal is the creation of a communist society, a socioeconomic order centered on common ownership of the means of production, di ...
affiliations. The de Broglie–Bohm theory was widely deemed unacceptable by mainstream theorists, mostly because of its explicit non-locality. On the theory,
John Stewart Bell
John Stewart Bell (28 July 1928 – 1 October 1990) was a physicist from Northern Ireland and the originator of Bell's theorem, an important theorem in quantum mechanics, quantum physics regarding hidden-variable theory, hidden-variable theor ...
, author of the 1964
Bell's theorem
Bell's theorem is a term encompassing a number of closely related results in physics, all of which determine that quantum mechanics is incompatible with local hidden-variable theories, given some basic assumptions about the nature of measuremen ...
wrote in 1982:
Since the 1990s, there has been renewed interest in formulating extensions to de Broglie–Bohm theory, attempting to reconcile it with
special relativity
In physics, the special theory of relativity, or special relativity for short, is a scientific theory of the relationship between Spacetime, space and time. In Albert Einstein's 1905 paper, Annus Mirabilis papers#Special relativity,
"On the Ele ...
and
quantum field theory
In theoretical physics, quantum field theory (QFT) is a theoretical framework that combines Field theory (physics), field theory and the principle of relativity with ideas behind quantum mechanics. QFT is used in particle physics to construct phy ...
, besides other features such as
spin or curved spatial geometries.
De Broglie–Bohm theory has a history of different formulations and names. In this section, each stage is given a name and a main reference.
Pilot-wave theory
Louis de Broglie presented his
pilot wave theory at the 1927 Solvay Conference, after close collaboration with Schrödinger, who developed his wave equation for de Broglie's theory. At the end of the presentation,
Wolfgang Pauli
Wolfgang Ernst Pauli ( ; ; 25 April 1900 – 15 December 1958) was an Austrian theoretical physicist and a pioneer of quantum mechanics. In 1945, after having been nominated by Albert Einstein, Pauli received the Nobel Prize in Physics "for the ...
pointed out that it was not compatible with a semi-classical technique Fermi had previously adopted in the case of inelastic scattering. Contrary to a popular legend, de Broglie actually gave the correct rebuttal that the particular technique could not be generalized for Pauli's purpose, although the audience might have been lost in the technical details and de Broglie's mild manner left the impression that Pauli's objection was valid. He was eventually persuaded to abandon this theory nonetheless because he was "discouraged by criticisms which
troused". De Broglie's theory already applies to multiple spin-less particles, but lacks an adequate theory of measurement as no one understood
quantum decoherence
Quantum decoherence is the loss of quantum coherence. It involves generally a loss of information of a system to its environment. Quantum decoherence has been studied to understand how quantum systems convert to systems that can be expla ...
at the time. An analysis of de Broglie's presentation is given in Bacciagaluppi et al. Also, in 1932
John von Neumann
John von Neumann ( ; ; December 28, 1903 – February 8, 1957) was a Hungarian and American mathematician, physicist, computer scientist and engineer. Von Neumann had perhaps the widest coverage of any mathematician of his time, in ...
published a
no hidden variables proof in his book ''
Mathematical Foundations of Quantum Mechanics'', that was widely believed to prove that all hidden-variable theories are impossible. This sealed the fate of de Broglie's theory for the next two decades.
In 1926,
Erwin Madelung had developed a hydrodynamic version of the
Schrödinger equation
The Schrödinger equation is a partial differential equation that governs the wave function of a non-relativistic quantum-mechanical system. Its discovery was a significant landmark in the development of quantum mechanics. It is named after E ...
, which is incorrectly considered as a basis for the density current derivation of the de Broglie–Bohm theory. The
Madelung equations, being quantum analog of
Euler equations of fluid dynamics, differ philosophically from the de Broglie–Bohm mechanics and are the basis of the
stochastic interpretation of quantum mechanics.
Peter R. Holland has pointed out that, earlier in 1927,
Einstein had actually submitted a preprint with a similar proposal but, not convinced, had withdrawn it before publication. According to Holland, failure to appreciate key points of the de Broglie–Bohm theory has led to confusion, the key point being "that the trajectories of a many-body quantum system are correlated not because the particles exert a direct force on one another (''à la'' Coulomb) but because all are acted upon by an entity – mathematically described by the wavefunction or functions of it – that lies beyond them". This entity is the
quantum potential.
After publishing his popular textbook ''Quantum Theory'' that adhered entirely to the Copenhagen orthodoxy, Bohm was persuaded by Einstein to take a critical look at von Neumann's no hidden variables proof. The result was 'A Suggested Interpretation of the Quantum Theory in Terms of "Hidden Variables" I and II'
ohm 1952 It was an independent origination of the pilot wave theory, and extended it to incorporate a consistent theory of measurement, and to address a criticism of Pauli that de Broglie did not properly respond to; it is taken to be deterministic (though Bohm hinted in the original papers that there should be disturbances to this, in the way
Brownian motion
Brownian motion is the random motion of particles suspended in a medium (a liquid or a gas). The traditional mathematical formulation of Brownian motion is that of the Wiener process, which is often called Brownian motion, even in mathematical ...
disturbs Newtonian mechanics). This stage is known as the ''de Broglie–Bohm Theory'' in Bell's work
ell 1987and is the basis for 'The Quantum Theory of Motion'
olland 1993
This stage applies to multiple particles, and is deterministic.
The de Broglie–Bohm theory is an example of a
hidden-variables theory. Bohm originally hoped that hidden variables could provide a
local
Local may refer to:
Geography and transportation
* Local (train), a train serving local traffic demand
* Local, Missouri, a community in the United States
Arts, entertainment, and media
* ''Local'' (comics), a limited series comic book by Bria ...
,
causal
Causality is an influence by which one Event (philosophy), event, process, state, or Object (philosophy), object (''a'' ''cause'') contributes to the production of another event, process, state, or object (an ''effect'') where the cause is at l ...
,
objective description that would resolve or eliminate many of the paradoxes of quantum mechanics, such as
Schrödinger's cat
In quantum mechanics, Schrödinger's cat is a thought experiment concerning quantum superposition. In the thought experiment, a hypothetical cat in a closed box may be considered to be simultaneously both alive and dead while it is unobserved, ...
, the
measurement problem and the collapse of the wavefunction. However,
Bell's theorem
Bell's theorem is a term encompassing a number of closely related results in physics, all of which determine that quantum mechanics is incompatible with local hidden-variable theories, given some basic assumptions about the nature of measuremen ...
complicates this hope, as it demonstrates that there can be no local hidden-variable theory that is compatible with the predictions of quantum mechanics. The Bohmian interpretation is
causal
Causality is an influence by which one Event (philosophy), event, process, state, or Object (philosophy), object (''a'' ''cause'') contributes to the production of another event, process, state, or object (an ''effect'') where the cause is at l ...
but not
local
Local may refer to:
Geography and transportation
* Local (train), a train serving local traffic demand
* Local, Missouri, a community in the United States
Arts, entertainment, and media
* ''Local'' (comics), a limited series comic book by Bria ...
.
Bohm's paper was largely ignored or panned by other physicists.
Albert Einstein
Albert Einstein (14 March 187918 April 1955) was a German-born theoretical physicist who is best known for developing the theory of relativity. Einstein also made important contributions to quantum mechanics. His mass–energy equivalence f ...
, who had suggested that Bohm search for a realist alternative to the prevailing
Copenhagen approach, did not consider Bohm's interpretation to be a satisfactory answer to the quantum nonlocality question, calling it "too cheap", while
Werner Heisenberg
Werner Karl Heisenberg (; ; 5 December 1901 – 1 February 1976) was a German theoretical physicist, one of the main pioneers of the theory of quantum mechanics and a principal scientist in the German nuclear program during World War II.
He pub ...
considered it a "superfluous 'ideological superstructure' ".
Wolfgang Pauli
Wolfgang Ernst Pauli ( ; ; 25 April 1900 – 15 December 1958) was an Austrian theoretical physicist and a pioneer of quantum mechanics. In 1945, after having been nominated by Albert Einstein, Pauli received the Nobel Prize in Physics "for the ...
, who had been unconvinced by de Broglie in 1927, conceded to Bohm as follows:
I just received your long letter of 20th November, and I also have studied more thoroughly the details of your paper. I do not see any longer the possibility of any logical contradiction as long as your results agree completely with those of the usual wave mechanics and as long as no means is given to measure the values of your hidden parameters both in the measuring apparatus and in the observe icsystem. As far as the whole matter stands now, your 'extra wave-mechanical predictions' are still a check, which cannot be cashed.
He subsequently described Bohm's theory as "artificial metaphysics".
According to physicist
Max Dresden, when Bohm's theory was presented at the
Institute for Advanced Study
The Institute for Advanced Study (IAS) is an independent center for theoretical research and intellectual inquiry located in Princeton, New Jersey. It has served as the academic home of internationally preeminent scholars, including Albert Ein ...
in Princeton, many of the objections were
ad hominem, focusing on Bohm's sympathy with communists as exemplified by his refusal to give testimony to the
House Un-American Activities Committee
The House Committee on Un-American Activities (HCUA), popularly the House Un-American Activities Committee (HUAC), was an investigative United States Congressional committee, committee of the United States House of Representatives, created in 19 ...
.
In 1979, Chris Philippidis, Chris Dewdney and
Basil Hiley were the first to perform numeric computations on the basis of the quantum potential to deduce ensembles of particle trajectories. Their work renewed the interests of physicists in the Bohm interpretation of quantum physics.
Eventually
John Bell began to defend the theory. In "Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics"
ell 1987 several of the papers refer to hidden-variables theories (which include Bohm's).
The trajectories of the Bohm model that would result for particular experimental arrangements were termed "surreal" by some.
[ Still in 2016, mathematical physicist Sheldon Goldstein said of Bohm's theory: "There was a time when you couldn't even talk about it because it was heretical. It probably still is the kiss of death for a physics career to be actually working on Bohm, but maybe that's changing."]
Bohmian mechanics
Bohmian mechanics is the same theory, but with an emphasis on the notion of current flow, which is determined on the basis of the quantum equilibrium hypothesis that the probability follows the Born rule. The term "Bohmian mechanics" is also often used to include most of the further extensions past the spin-less version of Bohm. While de Broglie–Bohm theory has Lagrangians and Hamilton-Jacobi equations as a primary focus and backdrop, with the icon of the quantum potential, Bohmian mechanics considers the continuity equation as primary and has the guiding equation as its icon. They are mathematically equivalent in so far as the Hamilton-Jacobi formulation applies, i.e., spin-less particles.
All of non-relativistic quantum mechanics can be fully accounted for in this theory. Recent studies have used this formalism to compute the evolution of many-body quantum systems, with a considerable increase in speed as compared to other quantum-based methods.
Causal interpretation and ontological interpretation
Bohm developed his original ideas, calling them the ''Causal Interpretation''. Later he felt that ''causal'' sounded too much like ''deterministic'' and preferred to call his theory the ''Ontological Interpretation''. The main reference is "The Undivided Universe" (Bohm, Hiley 1993).
This stage covers work by Bohm and in collaboration with Jean-Pierre Vigier and Basil Hiley. Bohm is clear that this theory is non-deterministic (the work with Hiley includes a stochastic theory). As such, this theory is not strictly speaking a formulation of de Broglie–Bohm theory, but it deserves mention here because the term "Bohm Interpretation" is ambiguous between this theory and de Broglie–Bohm theory.
In 1996 philosopher of science
Philosophy ('love of wisdom' in Ancient Greek) is a systematic study of general and fundamental questions concerning topics like existence, reason, knowledge, Value (ethics and social sciences), value, mind, and language. It is a rational an ...
Arthur Fine gave an in-depth analysis of possible interpretations of Bohm's model of 1952.
William Simpson has suggested a hylomorphic interpretation of Bohmian mechanics, in which the cosmos is an Aristotelian substance composed of material particles and a substantial form. The wave function is assigned a dispositional role in choreographing the trajectories of the particles.
Hydrodynamic quantum analogs
Experiments on hydrodynamical analogs of quantum mechanics beginning with the work of Couder and Fort (2006) have purported to show that macroscopic classical pilot-waves can exhibit characteristics previously thought to be restricted to the quantum realm. Hydrodynamic pilot-wave analogs have been claimed to duplicate the double slit experiment, tunneling, quantized orbits, and numerous other quantum phenomena which have led to a resurgence in interest in pilot wave theories.
The analogs have been compared to the '' Faraday wave''.
These results have been disputed: experiments fail to reproduce aspects of the double-slit experiments. High precision measurements in the tunneling case point to a different origin of the unpredictable crossing: rather than initial position uncertainty or environmental noise, interactions at the barrier seem to be involved.
Another classical analog has been reported in surface gravity waves.
Surrealistic trajectories
In 1992, Englert, Scully, Sussman, and Walther proposed experiments that would show particles taking paths that differ from the Bohm trajectories. They described the Bohm trajectories as "surrealistic"; their proposal was later referred to as ESSW after the last names of the authors.
In 2016, Mahler et al. verified the ESSW predictions. However they propose the surrealistic effect is a consequence of the nonlocality inherent in Bohm's theory.
See also
* Madelung equations
* Local hidden-variable theory
* Superfluid vacuum theory
* Fluid analogs in quantum mechanics
* Probability current
Notes
References
Sources
*
*
*
full text
*
full text
*
*
*
*
* (Demonstrates incompleteness of the Bohm interpretation in the face of fractal, differentiable-nowhere wavefunctions.)
*
*
*
*
* (Describes a Bohmian resolution to the dilemma posed by non-differentiable wavefunctions.)
*
*
*
Bohmian mechanics on arxiv.org
Further reading
* John S. Bell: ''Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics: Collected Papers on Quantum Philosophy'', Cambridge University Press, 2004,
* David Bohm
David Joseph Bohm (; 20 December 1917 – 27 October 1992) was an American scientist who has been described as one of the most significant Theoretical physics, theoretical physicists of the 20th centuryDavid Peat Who's Afraid of Schrödinger' ...
, Basil Hiley: ''The Undivided Universe: An Ontological Interpretation of Quantum Theory'', Routledge Chapman & Hall, 1993,
* Detlef Dürr, Sheldon Goldstein, Nino Zanghì: ''Quantum Physics Without Quantum Philosophy'', Springer, 2012,
* Detlef Dürr, Stefan Teufel: ''Bohmian Mechanics: The Physics and Mathematics of Quantum Theory'', Springer, 2009,
* Peter R. Holland: ''The quantum theory of motion'', Cambridge University Press, 1993 (re-printed 2000, transferred to digital printing 2004),
External links
"Pilot-Wave Hydrodynamics"
Bush, J. W. M., ''Annual Review of Fluid Mechanics'', 2015
"Bohmian Mechanics" (''Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'')
*
*
"Bohmian-Mechanics.net"
the homepage of the international research network on Bohmian Mechanics that was started by D. Dürr, S. Goldstein and N. Zanghì.
Workgroup Bohmian Mechanics at LMU Munich (D. Dürr)
Bohmian Mechanics Group at University of Innsbruck (G. Grübl)
, lecture course on de Broglie-Bohm theory by Mike Towler, Cambridge University.
"21st-century directions in de Broglie-Bohm theory and beyond"
August 2010 international conference on de Broglie-Bohm theory. Site contains slides for all the talks – the latest cutting-edge deBB research.
"Observing the Trajectories of a Single Photon Using Weak Measurement"
"Bohmian trajectories are no longer 'hidden variables'"
The David Bohm Society
De Broglie–Bohm theory inspired visualization of atomic orbitals.
{{DEFAULTSORT:Bohm Interpretation
Interpretations of quantum mechanics
Quantum measurement