In mathematics
Combinatory logic was originally intended as a 'pre-logic' that would clarify the role of quantified variables in logic, essentially by eliminating them. Another way of eliminating quantified variables is Quine's predicate functor logic. While the expressive power of combinatory logic typically exceeds that of first-order logic, the expressive power of predicate functor logic is identical to that of first order logic ( Quine 1960, 1966, 1976). The original inventor of combinatory logic, Moses Schönfinkel, published nothing on combinatory logic after his original 1924 paper. Haskell Curry rediscovered the combinators while working as an instructor atIn computing
InSummary of lambda calculus
Lambda calculus is concerned with objects called ''lambda-terms'', which can be represented by the following three forms of strings: * * * where is a variable name drawn from a predefined infinite set of variable names, and and are lambda-terms. Terms of the form are called ''abstractions''. The variable ''v'' is called the formal parameter of the abstraction, and is the ''body'' of the abstraction. The term represents the function which, applied to an argument, binds the formal parameter ''v'' to the argument and then computes the resulting value of — that is, it returns , with every occurrence of ''v'' replaced by the argument. Terms of the form are called ''applications''. Applications model function invocation or execution: the function represented by is to be invoked, with as its argument, and the result is computed. If (sometimes called the ''applicand'') is an abstraction, the term may be ''reduced'': , the argument, may be substituted into the body of in place of the formal parameter of , and the result is a new lambda term which is ''equivalent'' to the old one. If a lambda term contains no subterms of the form then it cannot be reduced, and is said to be in normal form. The expression represents the result of taking the term and replacing all free occurrences of in it with . Thus we write : By convention, we take as shorthand for (i.e., application is left associative). The motivation for this definition of reduction is that it captures the essential behavior of all mathematical functions. For example, consider the function that computes the square of a number. We might write :The square of ''x'' is (Using "" to indicate multiplication.) ''x'' here is the formal parameter of the function. To evaluate the square for a particular argument, say 3, we insert it into the definition in place of the formal parameter: :The square of 3 is To evaluate the resulting expression , we would have to resort to our knowledge of multiplication and the number 3. Since any computation is simply a composition of the evaluation of suitable functions on suitable primitive arguments, this simple substitution principle suffices to capture the essential mechanism of computation. Moreover, in lambda calculus, notions such as '3' and '' can be represented without any need for externally defined primitive operators or constants. It is possible to identify terms in lambda calculus, which, when suitably interpreted, behave like the number 3 and like the multiplication operator, q.v. Church encoding. Lambda calculus is known to be computationally equivalent in power to many other plausible models for computation (includingCombinatory calculi
Since abstraction is the only way to manufacture functions in the lambda calculus, something must replace it in the combinatory calculus. Instead of abstraction, combinatory calculus provides a limited set of primitive functions out of which other functions may be built.Combinatory terms
A combinatory term has one of the following forms: The primitive functions are ''combinators'', or functions that, when seen as lambda terms, contain no free variables. To shorten the notations, a general convention is that , or even , denotes the term . This is the same general convention (left-associativity) as for multiple application in lambda calculus.Reduction in combinatory logic
In combinatory logic, each primitive combinator comes with a reduction rule of the form : where ''E'' is a term mentioning only variables from the set . It is in this way that primitive combinators behave as functions.Examples of combinators
The simplest example of a combinator is I, the identity combinator, defined by :(I ''x'') = ''x'' for all terms ''x''. Another simple combinator is K, which manufactures constant functions: (K ''x'') is the function which, for any argument, returns ''x'', so we say :((K ''x'') ''y'') = ''x'' for all terms ''x'' and ''y''. Or, following the convention for multiple application, :(K ''x'' ''y'') = ''x'' A third combinator is S, which is a generalized version of application: :(S ''x y z'') = (''x z'' (''y z'')) S applies ''x'' to ''y'' after first substituting ''z'' into each of them. Or put another way, ''x'' is applied to ''y'' inside the environment ''z''. Given S and K, I itself is unnecessary, since it can be built from the other two: :((S K K) ''x'') :: = (S K K ''x'') :: = (K ''x'' (K ''x'')) :: = ''x'' for any term ''x''. Note that although ((S K K) ''x'') = (I ''x'') for any ''x'', (S K K) itself is not equal to I. We say the terms are extensionally equal. Extensional equality captures the mathematical notion of the equality of functions: that two functions are ''equal'' if they always produce the same results for the same arguments. In contrast, the terms themselves, together with the reduction of primitive combinators, capture the notion of ''intensional equality'' of functions: that two functions are ''equal'' only if they have identical implementationsCompleteness of the S-K basis
S and K can be composed to produce combinators that are extensionally equal to ''any'' lambda term, and therefore, by Church's thesis, to any computable function whatsoever. The proof is to present a transformation, , which converts an arbitrary lambda term into an equivalent combinator. may be defined as follows: # # # (if ''x'' does not occur free in ''E'') # # (if ''x'' occurs free in ''E'') # (if ''x'' occurs free in ''E'' or ''E'') Note that ''T'' nbsp;as given is not a well-typed mathematical function, but rather a term rewriter: Although it eventually yields a combinator, the transformation may generate intermediary expressions that are neither lambda terms nor combinators, via rule (5). This process is also known as ''abstraction elimination''. This definition is exhaustive: any lambda expression will be subject to exactly one of these rules (see Summary of lambda calculus above). It is related to the process of ''bracket abstraction'', which takes an expression ''E'' built from variables and application and produces a combinator expression in which the variable x is not free, such that 'x'''E x'' = ''E'' holds. A very simple algorithm for bracket abstraction is defined by induction on the structure of expressions as follows: # 'x'''y'' := K ''y'' # 'x'''x'' := I # 'x''''E'' ''E'') := S( 'x'''E'')( 'x'''E'') Bracket abstraction induces a translation from lambda terms to combinator expressions, by interpreting lambda-abstractions using the bracket abstraction algorithm.Conversion of a lambda term to an equivalent combinatorial term
For example, we will convert the lambda term ''λx''.''λy''.(''y'' ''x'') to a combinatorial term: :''T'' 'λx''.''λy''.(''y'' ''x''):: = ''T'λx''.''T'λy''.(''y'' ''x'') (by 5) :: = ''T'' 'λx''.(S ''T''[''λy''.''y''''T''[''λy''.''x''">'λy''.''y''.html" ;"title="'λx''.(S ''T''[''λy''.''y''">'λx''.(S ''T''[''λy''.''y''''T''[''λy''.''x''] (by 6) :: = ''T''[''λx''.(S I ''T''[''λy''.''x''])] (by 4) :: = ''T''[''λx''.(S I (K ''T''[''x'']))] (by 3) :: = ''T''[''λx''.(S I (K ''x''))] (by 1) :: = (S ''T'' 'λx''.(S I)''T'' 'λx''.(K ''x'') (by 6) :: = (S (K (S I)) ''T'' 'λx''.(K ''x'') (by 3) :: = (S (K (S I)) (S ''T'' 'λx''.K''T'' 'λx''.''x'') (by 6) :: = (S (K (S I)) (S (K K) ''T'' 'λx''.''x'') (by 3) :: = (S (K (S I)) (S (K K) I)) (by 4) If we apply this combinatorial term to any two terms ''x'' and ''y'' (by feeding them in a queue-like fashion into the combinator 'from the right'), it reduces as follows: : (S (K (S I)) (S (K K) I) x y) :: = (K (S I) x (S (K K) I x) y) :: = (S I (S (K K) I x) y) :: = (I y (S (K K) I x y)) :: = (y (S (K K) I x y)) :: = (y (K K x (I x) y)) :: = (y (K (I x) y)) :: = (y (I x)) :: = (y x) The combinatory representation, (S (K (S I)) (S (K K) I)) is much longer than the representation as a lambda term, ''λx''.''λy''.(y x). This is typical. In general, the ''T'' nbsp;construction may expand a lambda term of length ''n'' to a combinatorial term of length Θ(''n''3).Explanation of the ''T'' nbsp;transformation
The ''T'' nbsp;transformation is motivated by a desire to eliminate abstraction. Two special cases, rules 3 and 4, are trivial: ''λx''.''x'' is clearly equivalent to I, and ''λx''.''E'' is clearly equivalent to (K ''T'' 'E'' if ''x'' does not appear free in ''E''. The first two rules are also simple: Variables convert to themselves, and applications, which are allowed in combinatory terms, are converted to combinators simply by converting the applicand and the argument to combinators. It is rules 5 and 6 that are of interest. Rule 5 simply says that to convert a complex abstraction to a combinator, we must first convert its body to a combinator, and then eliminate the abstraction. Rule 6 actually eliminates the abstraction. ''λx''.(''E'' ''E'') is a function which takes an argument, say ''a'', and substitutes it into the lambda term (''E'' ''E'') in place of ''x'', yielding (''E'' ''E'') 'x'' : = ''a'' But substituting ''a'' into (''E'' ''E'') in place of ''x'' is just the same as substituting it into both ''E'' and ''E'', so :(''E'' ''E'') 'x'' := ''a''= (''E'' 'x'' := ''a''''E'' 'x'' := ''a'' :(''λx''.(''E'' ''E'') ''a'') = ((''λx''.''E'' ''a'') (''λx''.''E'' ''a'')) :::::= (S ''λx''.''E'' ''λx''.''E'' ''a'') :::::= ((S ''λx''.''E'' ''λx''.''E'') ''a'') By extensional equality, :''λx''.(''E'' ''E'') = (S ''λx''.''E'' ''λx''.''E'') Therefore, to find a combinator equivalent to ''λx''.(''E'' ''E''), it is sufficient to find a combinator equivalent to (S ''λx''.''E'' ''λx''.''E''), and :(S ''T'' 'λx''.''E''''T'' 'λx''.''E'' evidently fits the bill. ''E'' and ''E'' each contain strictly fewer applications than (''E'' ''E''), so the recursion must terminate in a lambda term with no applications at all—either a variable, or a term of the form ''λx''.''E''.Simplifications of the transformation
η-reduction
The combinators generated by the ''T'' nbsp;transformation can be made smaller if we take into account the ''η-reduction'' rule: :''T'' 'λx''.(''E'' ''x'')= ''T'' 'E'' (if ''x'' is not free in ''E'') ''λx''.(''E'' x) is the function which takes an argument, ''x'', and applies the function ''E'' to it; this is extensionally equal to the function ''E'' itself. It is therefore sufficient to convert ''E'' to combinatorial form. Taking this simplification into account, the example above becomes: :''T'' 'λx''.''λy''.(''y'' ''x''):= ... := (S (K (S I)) ''T'' 'λx''.(K ''x'') := (S (K (S I)) K) (by η-reduction) This combinator is equivalent to the earlier, longer one: :(S (K (S I)) K ''x y'') := (K (S I) ''x'' (K ''x'') ''y'') := (S I (K ''x'') ''y'') := (I ''y'' (K ''x y'')) := (''y'' (K ''x y'')) := (''y x'') Similarly, the original version of the ''T'' nbsp;transformation transformed the identity function ''λf''.''λx''.(''f'' ''x'') into (S (S (K S) (S (K K) I)) (K I)). With the η-reduction rule, ''λf''.''λx''.(''f'' ''x'') is transformed into I.One-point basis
There are one-point bases from which every combinator can be composed extensionally equal to ''any'' lambda term. A simple example of such a basis is where: :X ≡ ''λx''.((xS)K) It is not difficult to verify that: :X (X (X X)) =β K and :X (X (X (X X))) =β S. Since is a basis, it follows that is a basis too. TheCombinators B, C
In addition to S and K, included two combinators which are now called B and C, with the following reductions: :(C ''f'' ''g'' ''x'') = ((''f'' ''x'') ''g'') :(B ''f'' ''g'' ''x'') = (''f'' (''g'' ''x'')) He also explains how they in turn can be expressed using only S and K: :B = (S (K S) K) :C = (S (S (K (S (K S) K)) S) (K K)) These combinators are extremely useful when translating predicate logic or lambda calculus into combinator expressions. They were also used by Curry, and much later by David Turner, whose name has been associated with their computational use. Using them, we can extend the rules for the transformation as follows: # # # (if ''x'' is not free in ''E'') # # (if ''x'' is free in ''E'') # (if ''x'' is free in both ''E'' and ''E'') # (if ''x'' is free in ''E'' but not ''E'') # (if ''x'' is free in ''E'' but not ''E'') Using B and C combinators, the transformation of ''λx''.''λy''.(''y'' ''x'') looks like this: : : : (by rule 7) : : (η-reduction) : (traditional canonical notation: ) : (traditional canonical notation: ) And indeed, (C I ''x'' ''y'') does reduce to (''y'' ''x''): :(C I ''x'' ''y'') := (I ''y'' ''x'') := (''y'' ''x'') The motivation here is that B and C are limited versions of S. Whereas S takes a value and substitutes it into both the applicand and its argument before performing the application, C performs the substitution only in the applicand, and B only in the argument. The modern names for the combinators come from Haskell Curry's doctoral thesis of 1930 (see B, C, K, W System). In Schönfinkel's original paper, what we now call S, K, I, B and C were called S, C, I, Z, and T respectively. The reduction in combinator size that results from the new transformation rules can also be achieved without introducing B and C, as demonstrated in Section 3.2 of .= CLK versus CLI calculus
= A distinction must be made between the CLK as described in this article and the CLI calculus. The distinction corresponds to that between the λK and the λI calculus. Unlike the λK calculus, the λI calculus restricts abstractions to: ::''λx''.''E'' where ''x'' has at least one free occurrence in ''E''. As a consequence, combinator K is not present in the λI calculus nor in the CLI calculus. The constants of CLI are: I, B, C and S, which form a basis from which all CLI terms can be composed (modulo equality). Every λI term can be converted into an equal CLI combinator according to rules similar to those presented above for the conversion of λK terms into CLK combinators. See chapter 9 in Barendregt (1984).Reverse conversion
The conversion ''L'' nbsp;from combinatorial terms to lambda terms is trivial: :''L'' ''I= ''λx''.''x'' :''L'' ''K= ''λx''.''λy''.''x'' :''L'' ''C= ''λx''.''λy''.''λz''.(''x'' ''z'' ''y'') :''L'' ''B= ''λx''.''λy''.''λz''.(''x'' (''y'' ''z'')) :''L'' ''S= ''λx''.''λy''.''λz''.(''x'' ''z'' (''y'' ''z'')) :''L'' ''E'' ''E'')= (''L'' 'E''''L'' 'E'' Note, however, that this transformation is not the inverse transformation of any of the versions of ''T'' nbsp;that we have seen.Undecidability of combinatorial calculus
A normal form is any combinatory term in which the primitive combinators that occur, if any, are not applied to enough arguments to be simplified. It is undecidable whether a general combinatory term has a normal form; whether two combinatory terms are equivalent, etc. This can be shown in a similar way as for the corresponding problems for lambda terms.Undefinability by predicates
The undecidable problems above (equivalence, existence of normal form, etc.) take as input syntactic representations of terms under a suitable encoding (e.g., Church encoding). One may also consider a toy trivial computation model where we "compute" properties of terms by means of combinators applied directly to the terms themselves as arguments, rather than to their syntactic representations. More precisely, let a ''predicate'' be a combinator that, when applied, returns either T or F (where T and F represent the conventional Church encodings of true and false, ''λx''.''λy''.''x'' and ''λx''.''λy''.''y'', transformed into combinatory logic; the combinatory versions have and ). A predicate N is ''nontrivial'' if there are two arguments ''A'' and ''B'' such that N ''A'' = T and N ''B'' = F. A combinator N is ''complete'' if N''M'' has a normal form for every argument ''M''. An analogue of Rice's theorem for this toy model then says that every complete predicate is trivial. The proof of this theorem is rather simple. From this undefinability theorem it immediately follows that there is no complete predicate that can discriminate between terms that have a normal form and terms that do not have a normal form. It also follows that there is no complete predicate, say EQUAL, such that: :(EQUAL ''A B'') = T if ''A'' = ''B'' and :(EQUAL ''A B'') = F if ''A'' ≠ ''B''. If EQUAL would exist, then for all ''A'', ''λx.''(EQUAL ''x A'') would have to be a complete non trivial predicate. However, note that it also immediately follows from this undefinability theorem that many properties of terms that are obviously decidable are not definable by complete predicates either: e.g., there is no predicate that could tell whether the first primitive function letter occurring in a term is a K. This shows that definability by predicates is a not a reasonable model of decidability.Applications
Compilation of functional languages
David Turner used his combinators to implement the SASL programming language. Kenneth E. Iverson used primitives based on Curry's combinators in his J programming language, a successor to APL. This enabled what Iverson called tacit programming, that is, programming in functional expressions containing no variables, along with powerful tools for working with such programs. It turns out that tacit programming is possible in any APL-like language with user-defined operators.Logic
The Curry–Howard isomorphism implies a connection between logic and programming: every proof of a theorem of intuitionistic logic corresponds to a reduction of a typed lambda term, and conversely. Moreover, theorems can be identified with function type signatures. Specifically, a typed combinatory logic corresponds to a Hilbert system inSee also
* Applicative computing systems * B, C, K, W system * Categorical abstract machine * Combinatory categorial grammar * Explicit substitution * Fixed point combinator * Graph reduction machine *References
Literature
* * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * (eBook: )External links
*