
In
algorithmic information theory, algorithmic probability, also known as Solomonoff probability, is a mathematical method of assigning a prior
probability
Probability is a branch of mathematics and statistics concerning events and numerical descriptions of how likely they are to occur. The probability of an event is a number between 0 and 1; the larger the probability, the more likely an e ...
to a given observation. It was invented by
Ray Solomonoff in the 1960s.
It is used in inductive inference theory and analyses of algorithms. In his
general theory of inductive inference, Solomonoff uses the method together with
Bayes' rule to obtain probabilities of prediction for an algorithm's future outputs.
In the mathematical formalism used, the observations have the form of finite binary strings viewed as outputs of
Turing machine
A Turing machine is a mathematical model of computation describing an abstract machine that manipulates symbols on a strip of tape according to a table of rules. Despite the model's simplicity, it is capable of implementing any computer algori ...
s, and the universal prior is a
probability distribution
In probability theory and statistics, a probability distribution is a Function (mathematics), function that gives the probabilities of occurrence of possible events for an Experiment (probability theory), experiment. It is a mathematical descri ...
over the set of finite binary strings calculated from a probability distribution over programs (that is, inputs to a
universal Turing machine). The prior is universal in the
Turing-computability sense, i.e. no string has zero probability. It is not computable, but it can be approximated.
Formally, the probability
is not a probability and it is not computable. It is only "lower semi-computable" and a "semi-measure". By "semi-measure", it means that
. That is, the "probability" does not actually sum up to one, unlike actual probabilities. This is because some inputs to the Turing machine causes it to never halt, which means the probability mass allocated to those inputs is lost. By "lower semi-computable", it means there is a Turing machine that, given an input string
, can print out a sequence
that converges to
from below, but there is no such Turing machine that does the same from above.
Overview
Algorithmic probability is the main ingredient of Solomonoff's theory of inductive inference, the theory of prediction based on observations; it was invented with the goal of using it for machine learning; given a sequence of symbols, which one will come next? Solomonoff's theory provides an answer that is optimal in a certain sense, although it is incomputable.
Four principal inspirations for Solomonoff's algorithmic probability were:
Occam's razor,
Epicurus' principle of multiple explanations, modern computing theory (e.g. use of a universal Turing machine) and Bayes’ rule for prediction.
Occam's razor and Epicurus' principle are essentially two different non-mathematical approximations of the
universal prior.
* Occam's razor: ''among the theories that are consistent with the observed phenomena, one should select the simplest theory''.
* Epicurus' principle of multiple explanations: ''if more than one theory is consistent with the observations, keep all such theories''.
At the heart of the universal prior is an abstract model of a computer, such as a universal Turing machine. Any abstract computer will do, as long as it is Turing-complete, i.e. every
computable function
Computable functions are the basic objects of study in computability theory. Informally, a function is ''computable'' if there is an algorithm that computes the value of the function for every value of its argument. Because of the lack of a precis ...
has at least one program that will compute its application on the abstract computer.
The abstract computer is used to give precise meaning to the phrase "simple explanation". In the formalism used, explanations, or theories of phenomena, are computer programs that generate observation strings when run on the abstract computer. Each computer program is assigned a weight corresponding to its length. The universal probability distribution is the probability distribution on all possible output strings with random input, assigning for each finite output prefix ''q'' the sum of the probabilities of the programs that compute something starting with ''q''. Thus, a simple explanation is a short computer program. A complex explanation is a long computer program. Simple explanations are more likely, so a high-probability observation string is one generated by a short computer program, or perhaps by any of a large number of slightly longer computer programs. A low-probability observation string is one that can only be generated by a long computer program.
Algorithmic probability is closely related to the concept of
Kolmogorov complexity. Kolmogorov's introduction of complexity was motivated by information theory and problems in randomness, while Solomonoff introduced algorithmic complexity for a different reason: inductive reasoning. A single universal prior probability that can be substituted for each actual prior probability in Bayes's rule was invented by Solomonoff with Kolmogorov complexity as a side product. It predicts the most likely continuation of that observation, and provides a measure of how likely this continuation will be.
Solomonoff's enumerable measure is
universal in a certain powerful sense, but the computation time can be infinite. One way of dealing with this issue is a variant of Leonid Levin's Search Algorithm, which limits the time spent computing the success of possible programs, with shorter programs given more time. When run for longer and longer periods of time, it will generate a sequence of approximations which converge to the universal probability distribution. Other methods of dealing with the issue include limiting the search space by including training sequences.
Solomonoff proved this distribution to be machine-invariant within a constant factor (called the
invariance theorem).
Fundamental Theorems
I. Kolmogorov's Invariance Theorem
Kolmogorov's Invariance theorem clarifies that the Kolmogorov Complexity, or ''Minimal Description Length'', of a dataset
is invariant to the choice of Turing-Complete language used to simulate a Universal Turing Machine:
:
where
.
Interpretation
The minimal description
such that
serves as a natural representation of the string
relative to the Turing-Complete language
. Moreover, as
can't be compressed further
is an incompressible and hence uncomputable string. This corresponds to a scientists' notion of randomness and clarifies the reason why Kolmogorov Complexity is not computable.
It follows that any piece of data has a necessary and sufficient representation in terms of a random string.
Proof
The following is taken from
From the theory of compilers, it is known that for any two Turing-Complete languages
and
, there exists a compiler
expressed in
that translates programs expressed in
into functionally-equivalent programs expressed in
.
It follows that if we let
be the shortest program that prints a given string
then:
:
where
, and by symmetry we obtain the opposite inequality.
II. Levin's Universal Distribution
Given that any uniquely-decodable code satisfies the Kraft-McMillan inequality, prefix-free Kolmogorov Complexity allows us to derive the Universal
Distribution:
:
where the fact that
may simulate a prefix-free UTM implies that for two distinct descriptions
and
,
isn't
a substring of
and
isn't a substring of
.
Interpretation
In a Computable Universe, given a phenomenon with encoding
generated by a physical process the probability of that phenomenon is well-defined and equal to the sum over the probabilities of distinct and independent causes. The prefix-free criterion is precisely what guarantees causal independence.
Proof
This is an immediate consequence of the
Kraft-McMillan inequality.
Kraft's inequality states that given a sequence of strings
there exists a prefix code with codewords
where
if and only if:
:
where
is the size of the alphabet
.
Without loss of generality, let's suppose we may order the
such that:
:
Now, there exists a prefix code if and only if at each step
there is at least one codeword to choose that does not contain any of the previous
codewords as a prefix. Due to the existence of a codeword at a previous step