Absolute Past
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In mathematical physics, the causal structure of a Lorentzian manifold describes the causal relationships between points in the manifold.


Introduction

In
modern physics Modern physics is a branch of physics that developed in the early 20th century and onward or branches greatly influenced by early 20th century physics. Notable branches of modern physics include quantum mechanics, special relativity and general ...
(especially general relativity) spacetime is represented by a Lorentzian manifold. The causal relations between points in the manifold are interpreted as describing which events in spacetime can influence which other events. The causal structure of an arbitrary (possibly curved) Lorentzian manifold is made more complicated by the presence of
curvature In mathematics, curvature is any of several strongly related concepts in geometry. Intuitively, the curvature is the amount by which a curve deviates from being a straight line, or a surface deviates from being a plane. For curves, the canonic ...
. Discussions of the causal structure for such manifolds must be phrased in terms of smooth
curve In mathematics, a curve (also called a curved line in older texts) is an object similar to a line (geometry), line, but that does not have to be Linearity, straight. Intuitively, a curve may be thought of as the trace left by a moving point (ge ...
s joining pairs of points. Conditions on the tangent vectors of the curves then define the causal relationships.


Tangent vectors

If \,(M,g) is a Lorentzian manifold (for metric g on
manifold In mathematics, a manifold is a topological space that locally resembles Euclidean space near each point. More precisely, an n-dimensional manifold, or ''n-manifold'' for short, is a topological space with the property that each point has a n ...
M) then the nonzero tangent vectors at each point in the manifold can be classified into three disjoint types. A tangent vector X is: * timelike if \,g(X,X) < 0 * null or lightlike if \,g(X,X) = 0 * spacelike if \,g(X,X) > 0 Here we use the (-,+,+,+,\cdots) metric signature. We say that a tangent vector is non-spacelike if it is null or timelike. The canonical Lorentzian manifold is Minkowski spacetime, where M=\mathbb^4 and g is the
flat Flat or flats may refer to: Architecture * Flat (housing), an apartment in the United Kingdom, Ireland, Australia and other Commonwealth countries Arts and entertainment * Flat (music), a symbol () which denotes a lower pitch * Flat (soldier), ...
Minkowski metric. The names for the tangent vectors come from the physics of this model. The causal relationships between points in Minkowski spacetime take a particularly simple form because the tangent space is also \mathbb^4 and hence the tangent vectors may be identified with points in the space. The four-dimensional vector X = (t,r) is classified according to the sign of g(X,X) = - c^2 t^2 + \, r\, ^2, where r \in \mathbb^3 is a
Cartesian Cartesian means of or relating to the French philosopher René Descartes—from his Latinized name ''Cartesius''. It may refer to: Mathematics *Cartesian closed category, a closed category in category theory *Cartesian coordinate system, modern ...
coordinate in 3-dimensional space, c is the constant representing the universal speed limit, and t is time. The classification of any vector in the space will be the same in all frames of reference that are related by a Lorentz transformation (but not by a general
Poincaré transformation Poincaré is a French surname. Notable people with the surname include: * Henri Poincaré (1854–1912), French physicist, mathematician and philosopher of science * Henriette Poincaré (1858-1943), wife of Prime Minister Raymond Poincaré * Luci ...
because the origin may then be displaced) because of the invariance of the metric.


Time-orientability

At each point in M the timelike tangent vectors in the point's tangent space can be divided into two classes. To do this we first define an
equivalence relation In mathematics, an equivalence relation is a binary relation that is reflexive, symmetric and transitive. The equipollence relation between line segments in geometry is a common example of an equivalence relation. Each equivalence relation ...
on pairs of timelike tangent vectors. If X and Y are two timelike tangent vectors at a point we say that X and Y are equivalent (written X \sim Y) if \,g(X,Y) < 0. There are then two
equivalence class In mathematics, when the elements of some set S have a notion of equivalence (formalized as an equivalence relation), then one may naturally split the set S into equivalence classes. These equivalence classes are constructed so that elements a ...
es which between them contain all timelike tangent vectors at the point. We can (arbitrarily) call one of these equivalence classes future-directed and call the other past-directed. Physically this designation of the two classes of future- and past-directed timelike vectors corresponds to a choice of an arrow of time at the point. The future- and past-directed designations can be extended to null vectors at a point by continuity. A Lorentzian manifold is time-orientable if a continuous designation of future-directed and past-directed for non-spacelike vectors can be made over the entire manifold.


Curves

A path in M is a
continuous Continuity or continuous may refer to: Mathematics * Continuity (mathematics), the opposing concept to discreteness; common examples include ** Continuous probability distribution or random variable in probability and statistics ** Continuous ...
map \mu : \Sigma \to M where \Sigma is a nondegenerate interval (i.e., a connected set containing more than one point) in \mathbb. A smooth path has \mu differentiable an appropriate number of times (typically C^\infty), and a regular path has nonvanishing derivative. A curve in M is the image of a path or, more properly, an equivalence class of path-images related by re-parametrisation, i.e. homeomorphisms or diffeomorphisms of \Sigma. When M is time-orientable, the curve is oriented if the parameter change is required to be monotonic. Smooth regular curves (or paths) in M can be classified depending on their tangent vectors. Such a curve is * chronological (or timelike) if the tangent vector is timelike at all points in the curve. Also called a world line. * null if the tangent vector is null at all points in the curve. * spacelike if the tangent vector is spacelike at all points in the curve. * causal (or non-spacelike) if the tangent vector is timelike ''or'' null at all points in the curve. The requirements of regularity and nondegeneracy of \Sigma ensure that closed causal curves (such as those consisting of a single point) are not automatically admitted by all spacetimes. If the manifold is time-orientable then the non-spacelike curves can further be classified depending on their orientation with respect to time. A chronological, null or causal curve in M is * future-directed if, for every point in the curve, the tangent vector is future-directed. * past-directed if, for every point in the curve, the tangent vector is past-directed. These definitions only apply to causal (chronological or null) curves because only timelike or null tangent vectors can be assigned an orientation with respect to time. * A closed timelike curve is a closed curve which is everywhere future-directed timelike (or everywhere past-directed timelike). * A closed null curve is a closed curve which is everywhere future-directed null (or everywhere past-directed null). * The holonomy of the ratio of the rate of change of the affine parameter around a closed null geodesic is the redshift factor.


Causal relations

There are several causal
relations Relation or relations may refer to: General uses *International relations, the study of interconnection of politics, economics, and law on a global level *Interpersonal relationship, association or acquaintance between two or more people *Public ...
between points x and y in the manifold M. * x chronologically precedes y (often denoted \,x \ll y) if there exists a future-directed chronological (timelike) curve from x to * x strictly causally precedes y (often denoted x < y) if there exists a future-directed causal (non-spacelike) curve from x to y. * x causally precedes y (often denoted x \prec y or x \le y) if x strictly causally precedes y or x=y. * x horismos y (often denoted x \to y or x \nearrow y ) if x=y or there exists a future-directed null curve from x to y (or equivalently, x \prec y and x \not\ll y). These relations satisfy the following properties: * x \ll y implies x \prec y (this follows trivially from the definition) * x \ll y, y \prec z implies x \ll z * x \prec y, y \ll z implies x \ll z * \ll, <, \prec are transitive. \to is not transitive. * \prec, \to are reflexive For a point x in the manifold M we define * The chronological future of x, denoted \,I^+(x), as the set of all points y in M such that x chronologically precedes y: :\,I^+(x) = \ * The chronological past of x, denoted \,I^-(x), as the set of all points y in M such that y chronologically precedes x: :\,I^-(x) = \ We similarly define * The causal future (also called the absolute future) of x, denoted \,J^+(x), as the set of all points y in M such that x causally precedes y: :\,J^+(x) = \ * The causal past (also called the absolute past) of x, denoted \,J^-(x), as the set of all points y in M such that y causally precedes x: :\,J^-(x) = \ * The future null cone of x as the set of all points y in M such that x \to y. * The past null cone of x as the set of all points y in M such that y \to x. * The light cone of x as the future and past null cones of x together. * elsewhere as points not in the light cone, causal future, or causal past. Points contained in \, I^+(x), for example, can be reached from x by a future-directed timelike curve. The point x can be reached, for example, from points contained in \,J^-(x) by a future-directed non-spacelike curve. In Minkowski spacetime the set \,I^+(x) is the
interior Interior may refer to: Arts and media * ''Interior'' (Degas) (also known as ''The Rape''), painting by Edgar Degas * ''Interior'' (play), 1895 play by Belgian playwright Maurice Maeterlinck * ''The Interior'' (novel), by Lisa See * Interior de ...
of the future light cone at x. The set \,J^+(x) is the full future light cone at x, including the cone itself. These sets \,I^+(x) ,I^-(x), J^+(x), J^-(x) defined for all x in M, are collectively called the causal structure of M. For S a
subset In mathematics, Set (mathematics), set ''A'' is a subset of a set ''B'' if all Element (mathematics), elements of ''A'' are also elements of ''B''; ''B'' is then a superset of ''A''. It is possible for ''A'' and ''B'' to be equal; if they are ...
of M we define :I^\pm = \bigcup_ I^\pm(x) :J^\pm = \bigcup_ J^\pm(x) For S, T two
subset In mathematics, Set (mathematics), set ''A'' is a subset of a set ''B'' if all Element (mathematics), elements of ''A'' are also elements of ''B''; ''B'' is then a superset of ''A''. It is possible for ''A'' and ''B'' to be equal; if they are ...
s of M we define * The chronological future of S relative to T, I^+ ;T/math>, is the chronological future of S considered as a submanifold of T. Note that this is quite a different concept from I^+ \cap T which gives the set of points in T which can be reached by future-directed timelike curves starting from S. In the first case the curves must lie in T in the second case they do not. See Hawking and Ellis. * The causal future of S relative to T, J^+ ;T/math>, is the causal future of S considered as a submanifold of T. Note that this is quite a different concept from J^+ \cap T which gives the set of points in T which can be reached by future-directed causal curves starting from S. In the first case the curves must lie in T in the second case they do not. See Hawking and Ellis. * A future set is a set closed under chronological future. * A past set is a set closed under chronological past. * An indecomposable past set (IP) is a past set which isn't the union of two different open past proper subsets. * An IP which does not coincide with the past of any point in M is called a terminal indecomposable past set (TIP). * A proper indecomposable past set (PIP) is an IP which isn't a TIP. I^-(x) is a proper indecomposable past set (PIP). * The future Cauchy development of S, D^+ (S) is the set of all points x for which every past directed inextendible causal curve through x intersects S at least once. Similarly for the past Cauchy development. The Cauchy development is the union of the future and past Cauchy developments. Cauchy developments are important for the study of
determinism Determinism is a philosophical view, where all events are determined completely by previously existing causes. Deterministic theories throughout the history of philosophy have developed from diverse and sometimes overlapping motives and consi ...
. * A subset S \subset M is achronal if there do not exist q,r \in S such that r \in I^(q), or equivalently, if S is disjoint from I^ /math>. Causal diamond * A Cauchy surface is a closed achronal set whose Cauchy development is M. * A metric is globally hyperbolic if it can be foliated by Cauchy surfaces. * The chronology violating set is the set of points through which closed timelike curves pass. * The causality violating set is the set of points through which closed causal curves pass. * The boundary of the causality violating set is a
Cauchy horizon In physics, a Cauchy horizon is a light-like boundary of the domain of validity of a Cauchy problem (a particular boundary value problem of the theory of partial differential equations). One side of the horizon contains closed space-like geodesics ...
. If the Cauchy horizon is generated by closed null geodesics, then there's a redshift factor associated with each of them. * For a causal curve \gamma, the causal diamond is J^+(\gamma) \cap J^-(\gamma) (here we are using the looser definition of 'curve' whereon it is just a set of points). In words: the causal diamond of a particle's world-line \gamma is the set of all events that lie in both the past of some point in \gamma and the future of some point in \gamma.


Properties

See Penrose (1972), p13. * A point x is in \,I^-(y) if and only if y is in \,I^+(x). * x \prec y \implies I^-(x) \subset I^-(y) * x \prec y \implies I^+(y) \subset I^+(x) * I^+ = I^+ ^+[S \subset J^+ = J^+[J^+[S">.html" ;"title="^+[S">^+[S \subset J^+ = J^+[J^+[S * I^- = I^-[I^-[S \subset J^- = J^-[J^-[S * The horismos is generated by null geodesic congruences. Topology, Topological properties: * I^\pm(x) is open for all points x in M. * I^\pm /math> is open for all subsets S \subset M. * I^\pm = I^\pm overline/math> for all subsets S \subset M. Here \overline is the closure of a subset S. * I^\pm \subset \overline


Conformal geometry

Two metrics \,g and \hat are conformally related if \hat = \Omega^2 g for some real function \Omega called the conformal factor. (See
conformal map In mathematics, a conformal map is a function that locally preserves angles, but not necessarily lengths. More formally, let U and V be open subsets of \mathbb^n. A function f:U\to V is called conformal (or angle-preserving) at a point u_0\in ...
). Looking at the definitions of which tangent vectors are timelike, null and spacelike we see they remain unchanged if we use \,g or \hat. As an example suppose X is a timelike tangent vector with respect to the \,g metric. This means that \,g(X,X) < 0. We then have that \hat(X,X) = \Omega^2 g(X,X) < 0 so X is a timelike tangent vector with respect to the \hat too. It follows from this that the causal structure of a Lorentzian manifold is unaffected by a conformal transformation. A null geodesic remains a null geodesic under a conformal rescaling.


Conformal infinity

An infinite metric admits geodesics of infinite length/proper time. However, we can sometimes make a conformal rescaling of the metric with a conformal factor which falls off sufficiently fast to 0 as we approach infinity to get the conformal boundary of the manifold. The topological structure of the conformal boundary depends upon the causal structure. * Future-directed timelike geodesics end up on i^+, the future timelike infinity. * Past-directed timelike geodesics end up on i^-, the past timelike infinity. * Future-directed null geodesics end up on ℐ+, the future null infinity. * Past-directed null geodesics end up on ℐ, the past null infinity. * Spacelike geodesics end up on spacelike infinity. * For Minkowski space, i^\pm are points, ℐ± are null sheets, and spacelike infinity has codimension 2. * For anti-de Sitter space, there's no timelike or null infinity, and spacelike infinity has codimension 1. * For de Sitter space, the future and past timelike infinity has codimension 1.


Gravitational singularity

If a geodesic terminates after a finite affine parameter, and it is not possible to extend the manifold to extend the geodesic, then we have a singularity. * For
black hole A black hole is a region of spacetime where gravitation, gravity is so strong that nothing, including light or other Electromagnetic radiation, electromagnetic waves, has enough energy to escape it. The theory of general relativity predicts t ...
s, the future timelike boundary ends on a singularity in some places. * For the
Big Bang The Big Bang event is a physical theory that describes how the universe expanded from an initial state of high density and temperature. Various cosmological models of the Big Bang explain the evolution of the observable universe from the ...
, the past timelike boundary is also a singularity. The absolute event horizon is the past null cone of the future timelike infinity. It is generated by null geodesics which obey the Raychaudhuri optical equation.


See also

* Causal dynamical triangulation (CDT) *
Causality conditions In the study of Lorentzian manifold spacetimes there exists a hierarchy of causality conditions which are important in proving mathematical theorems about the global structure of such manifolds. These conditions were collected during the late 1970 ...
* Causal sets * Cauchy surface * Closed timelike curve * Cosmic censorship hypothesis *
Globally hyperbolic manifold In mathematical physics, global hyperbolicity is a certain condition on the causal structure of a spacetime manifold (that is, a Lorentzian manifold). It's called hyperbolic because the fundamental condition that generates the Lorentzian manifold ...
*
Malament–Hogarth spacetime A Malament–Hogarth (M-H) spacetime, named after David B. Malament and Mark Hogarth, is a relativistic spacetime that possesses the following property: there exists a worldline \lambda and an event ''p'' such that all events along \lambda are a ...
* Penrose diagram *
Penrose–Hawking singularity theorems The Penrose–Hawking singularity theorems (after Roger Penrose and Stephen Hawking) are a set of results in general relativity that attempt to answer the question of when gravitation produces singularities. The Penrose singularity theorem is ...
* Spacetime


Notes


References

* * * *


Further reading

* G. W. Gibbons, S. N. Solodukhin; ''The Geometry of Small Causal Diamonds'' arXiv:hep-th/0703098 (Causal intervals) * S.W. Hawking, A.R. King, P.J. McCarthy;
A new topology for curved space–time which incorporates the causal, differential, and conformal structures
'; J. Math. Phys. 17 2:174-181 (1976); (Geometry, Causal Structure) *A.V. Levichev; ''Prescribing the conformal geometry of a lorentz manifold by means of its causal structure''; Soviet Math. Dokl. 35:452-455, (1987); (Geometry, Causal Structure) * D. Malament;
The class of continuous timelike curves determines the topology of spacetime
'; J. Math. Phys. 18 7:1399-1404 (1977); (Geometry, Causal Structure) * A.A. Robb ;
A theory of time and space
'; Cambridge University Press, 1914; (Geometry, Causal Structure) * A.A. Robb ;
The absolute relations of time and space
'; Cambridge University Press, 1921; (Geometry, Causal Structure) * A.A. Robb ;
Geometry of Time and Space
'; Cambridge University Press, 1936; (Geometry, Causal Structure) * R.D. Sorkin, E. Woolgar; ''A Causal Order for Spacetimes with C^0 Lorentzian Metrics: Proof of Compactness of the Space of Causal Curves''; Classical & Quantum Gravity 13: 1971-1994 (1996); arXiv:gr-qc/9508018 ( Causal Structure)


External links


Turing Machine Causal Networks
by Enrique Zeleny, the Wolfram Demonstrations Project * {{MathWorld , title=Causal Network , urlname=CausalNetwork Lorentzian manifolds Theory of relativity General relativity Theoretical physics