Stochastic Dominance
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

Stochastic dominance is a
partial order In mathematics, especially order theory, a partially ordered set (also poset) formalizes and generalizes the intuitive concept of an ordering, sequencing, or arrangement of the elements of a set. A poset consists of a set together with a bina ...
between random variables. It is a form of
stochastic ordering In probability theory and statistics, a stochastic order quantifies the concept of one random variable being "bigger" than another. These are usually partial orders, so that one random variable A may be neither stochastically greater than, less tha ...
. The concept arises in
decision theory Decision theory (or the theory of choice; not to be confused with choice theory) is a branch of applied probability theory concerned with the theory of making decisions based on assigning probabilities to various factors and assigning numerical ...
and
decision analysis Decision analysis (DA) is the discipline comprising the philosophy, methodology, and professional practice necessary to address important decisions in a formal manner. Decision analysis includes many procedures, methods, and tools for identifyi ...
in situations where one gamble (a probability distribution over possible outcomes, also known as prospects) can be ranked as superior to another gamble for a broad class of decision-makers. It is based on shared preferences regarding sets of possible outcomes and their associated probabilities. Only limited knowledge of preferences is required for determining dominance.
Risk aversion In economics and finance, risk aversion is the tendency of people to prefer outcomes with low uncertainty to those outcomes with high uncertainty, even if the average outcome of the latter is equal to or higher in monetary value than the more c ...
is a factor only in second order stochastic dominance. Stochastic dominance does not give a
total order In mathematics, a total or linear order is a partial order in which any two elements are comparable. That is, a total order is a binary relation \leq on some set X, which satisfies the following for all a, b and c in X: # a \leq a ( reflex ...
, but rather only a
partial order In mathematics, especially order theory, a partially ordered set (also poset) formalizes and generalizes the intuitive concept of an ordering, sequencing, or arrangement of the elements of a set. A poset consists of a set together with a bina ...
: for some pairs of gambles, neither one stochastically dominates the other, since different members of the broad class of decision-makers will differ regarding which gamble is preferable without them generally being considered to be equally attractive. Throughout the article, \rho, \nu stand for probability distributions on \R, while A, B, X, Y, Z stand for particular random variables on \R. The notation X \sim \rho means that X has distribution \rho. There are a sequence of stochastic dominance orderings, from first \succeq_1, to second \succeq_2, to higher orders \succeq_n. The sequence is increasingly more inclusive. That is, if \rho\succeq_n \nu, then \rho\succeq_ \nu for all k \geq n. Further, there exists \rho, \nu such that \rho\succeq_ \nu but not \rho\succeq_n \nu. Stochastic dominance could trace back to (Blackwell, 1953), but it was not developed until 1969–1970.


Statewise dominance

The simplest case of stochastic dominance is statewise dominance (also known as state-by-state dominance), defined as follows: : Random variable A is statewise dominant over random variable B if A gives at least as good a result in every state (every possible set of outcomes), and a strictly better result in at least one state. For example, if a dollar is added to one or more prizes in a lottery, the new lottery statewise dominates the old one because it yields a better payout regardless of the specific numbers realized by the lottery. Similarly, if a risk insurance policy has a lower premium and a better coverage than another policy, then with or without damage, the outcome is better. Anyone who prefers more to less (in the standard terminology, anyone who has
monotonic In mathematics, a monotonic function (or monotone function) is a function between ordered sets that preserves or reverses the given order. This concept first arose in calculus, and was later generalized to the more abstract setting of ord ...
ally increasing preferences) will always prefer a statewise dominant gamble.


First-order

Statewise dominance is implied by first-order stochastic dominance (FSD), which is defined as: : Random variable A has first-order stochastic dominance over random variable B if for any outcome ''x'', A gives at least as high a probability of receiving at least ''x'' as does B, and for some ''x'', A gives a higher probability of receiving at least ''x''. In notation form, P \ge xge P \ge x/math> for all ''x'', and for some ''x'', P \ge xP \ge x/math>. In terms of the cumulative distribution functions of the two random variables, A dominating B means that F_A(x) \le F_B(x) for all ''x'', with strict inequality at some ''x''.


Equivalent definitions

Let \rho, \nu be two probability distributions on \R, such that \mathbb E_ X, _are_both_finite,_then_the_following_conditions_are_equivalent,_thus_they_may_all_serve_as_the_definition_of_first-order_stochastic_dominance: *_For_any_u:_\R_\to_\R_that_is_non-decreasing,_\mathbb_E_
(X) An emoticon (, , rarely , ), short for "emotion icon", also known simply as an emote, is a pictorial representation of a facial expression using characters—usually punctuation marks, numbers, and letters—to express a person's feelings, ...
\geq_\mathbb_E_
(X) An emoticon (, , rarely , ), short for "emotion icon", also known simply as an emote, is a pictorial representation of a facial expression using characters—usually punctuation marks, numbers, and letters—to express a person's feelings, ...
*_F_\rho(t)_\leq_F_\nu(t),_\quad_\forall_t_\in_\R. *_There_exists_two_random_variables_X\sim_\rho,_Y_\sim_\nu,_such_that_X_=_Y_+_\delta,_where_\delta_\geq_0. The_first_definition_states_that_a_gamble_\rho_first-order_stochastically_dominates_gamble_\nu_
if_and_only_if In logic and related fields such as mathematics and philosophy, "if and only if" (shortened as "iff") is a biconditional logical connective between statements, where either both statements are true or both are false. The connective is b ...
_every_
expected_utility The expected utility hypothesis is a popular concept in economics that serves as a reference guide for decisions when the payoff is uncertain. The theory recommends which option rational individuals should choose in a complex situation, based on the ...
_maximizer_with_an_increasing_
utility_function As a topic of economics, utility is used to model worth or value. Its usage has evolved significantly over time. The term was introduced initially as a measure of pleasure or happiness as part of the theory of utilitarianism by moral philosoph ...
_prefers_gamble_\rho_over_gamble_\nu. The_third_definition_states_that_we_can_construct_a_pair_of_gambles_X,_Y_with_distributions_\mu,_\nu,_such_that_gamble_X_always_pays_at_least_as_much_as_gamble_Y._More_concretely,_construct_first_a_uniformly_distributed_Z\sim_Uniform(0,_1),_then_use_the_
inverse_transform_sampling Inverse transform sampling (also known as inversion sampling, the inverse probability integral transform, the inverse transformation method, Smirnov transform, or the golden ruleAalto University, N. Hyvönen, Computational methods in inverse probl ...
_to_get_X_=_F_X^(Z),_Y_=_F_Y^(Z),_then_X_\geq_Y_for_any_Z. Pictorially,_the_second_and_third_definition_are_equivalent,_because_we_can_go_from_the_graphed_density_function_of_A_to_that_of_B_both_by_pushing_it_upwards_and_pushing_it_leftwards.


__Extended_example_

Consider_three_gambles_over_a_single_toss_of_a_fair_six-sided_die: :_ \begin \text_&_1_&_2_&_3_&_4_&_5_&_6_\\ \hline \text\$_&_1_&_1_&_2_&_2_&_2_&_2_\\ \text\$_&_1_&_1_&_1_&_2_&_2_&_2_\\ \text\$_&_3_&_3_&_3_&_1_&_1_&_1_\\ \hline \end Gamble_A_statewise_dominates_gamble_B_because_A_gives_at_least_as_good_a_yield_in_all_possible_states_(outcomes_of_the_die_roll)_and_gives_a_strictly_better_yield_in_one_of_them_(state_3)._Since_A_statewise_dominates_B,_it_also_first-order_dominates_B. Gamble_C_does_not_statewise_dominate_B_because_B_gives_a_better_yield_in_states_4_through_6,_but_C_first-order_stochastically_dominates_B_because_Pr(B_≥_1)_=_Pr(C_≥_1)_=_1,_Pr(B_≥_2)_=_Pr(C_≥_2)_=_3/6,_and_Pr(B_≥_3)_=_0_while_Pr(C_≥_3)_=_3/6_>_Pr(B_≥_3). Gambles_A_and_C_cannot_be_ordered_relative_to_each_other_on_the_basis_of_first-order_stochastic_dominance_because_Pr(A_≥_2)_=_4/6_>_Pr(C_≥_2)_=_3/6_while_on_the_other_hand_Pr(C_≥_3)_=_3/6_>_Pr(A_≥_3)_=_0. In_general,_although_when_one_gamble_first-order_stochastically_dominates_a_second_gamble,_the_expected_value_of_the_payoff_under_the_first_will_be_greater_than_the_expected_value_of_the_payoff_under_the_second,_the_converse_is_not_true:_one_cannot_order_lotteries_with_regard_to_stochastic_dominance_simply_by_comparing_the_means_of_their_probability_distributions._For_instance,_in_the_above_example_C_has_a_higher_mean_(2)_than_does_A_(5/3),_yet_C_does_not_first-order_dominate_A.


_Second-order

The_other_commonly_used_type_of_stochastic_dominance_is_second-order_stochastic_dominance._Roughly_speaking,_for_two_gambles_\rho_and_\nu,_gamble_\rho_has_second-order_stochastic_dominance_over_gamble_\nu_if_the_former_is_more_predictable_(i.e._involves_less_risk)_and_has_at_least_as_high_a_mean.__All_
risk-averse In economics and finance, risk aversion is the tendency of people to prefer outcomes with low uncertainty to those outcomes with high uncertainty, even if the average outcome of the latter is equal to or higher in monetary value than the more ce ...
_ expected-utility_maximizers_(that_is,_those_with_increasing_and_concave_utility_functions)_prefer_a_second-order_stochastically_dominant_gamble_to_a_dominated_one._Second-order_dominance_describes_the_shared_preferences_of_a_smaller_class_of_decision-makers_(those_for_whom_more_is_better_''and''_who_are_averse_to_risk,_rather_than_''all''_those_for_whom_more_is_better)_than_does_first-order_dominance. In_terms_of_cumulative_distribution_functions_F_\rho_and_F_\nu,_\rho_is_second-order_stochastically_dominant_over_\nu_if_and_only_if_\int_^x_[F_\nu(t)_-_F_\rho(t)]_\,_dt_\geq_0_for_all_x,_with_strict_inequality_at_some_x._Equivalently,_\rho_dominates_\nu_in_the_second_order_if_and_only_if_\mathbb_E_
(X) An emoticon (, , rarely , ), short for "emotion icon", also known simply as an emote, is a pictorial representation of a facial expression using characters—usually punctuation marks, numbers, and letters—to express a person's feelings, ...
\geq_\mathbb_E_[u(X)]_for_all_nondecreasing_and_concave_function, concave_utility_functions_u(x). Second-order_stochastic_dominance_can_also_be_expressed_as_follows:_Gamble_\rho_second-order_stochastically_dominates_\nu_if_and_only_if_there_exist_some_gambles_y_and_z_such_that__x_\nu_\overset__(x_\rho_+_y_+_z),_with_y_always_less_than_or_equal_to_zero,_and_with_\mathbb_E(z\mid_x_\rho+y)=0_for_all_values_of_x_\rho+y._Here_the_introduction_of_random_variable_y_makes_\nu_first-order_stochastically_dominated_by_\rho_(making_\nu_disliked_by_those_with_an_increasing_utility_function),_and_the_introduction_of_random_variable_z_introduces_a_mean-preserving_spread_in_\nu_which_is_disliked_by_those_with_concave_utility._Note_that_if_\rho_and_\nu_have_the_same_mean_(so_that_the_random_variable_y_degenerates_to_the_fixed_number_0),_then_\nu_is_a_mean-preserving_spread_of_\rho.


__Equivalent_definitions_

Let_\rho,_\nu_be_two_probability_distributions_on_\R,_such_that_\mathbb_E_[, X, ],_\mathbb_E_ X, _are_both_finite,_then_the_following_conditions_are_equivalent,_thus_they_may_all_serve_as_the_definition_of_second-order_stochastic_dominance: *_For_any_u:_\R_\to_\R_that_is_non-decreasing,_and_(not_necessarily_strictly)_concave,\mathbb_E_
(X) An emoticon (, , rarely , ), short for "emotion icon", also known simply as an emote, is a pictorial representation of a facial expression using characters—usually punctuation marks, numbers, and letters—to express a person's feelings, ...
\geq_\mathbb_E_
(X) An emoticon (, , rarely , ), short for "emotion icon", also known simply as an emote, is a pictorial representation of a facial expression using characters—usually punctuation marks, numbers, and letters—to express a person's feelings, ...
*_\int_^t_F_\rho(x)_dx_\leq_\int_^t_F_\nu(x)_dx,_\quad_\forall_t_\in_\R. *_There_exists_two_random_variables_X\sim_\rho,_Y_\sim_\nu,_such_that_X_=_Y_+_\delta_+_\epsilon,_where_\delta_\geq_0_and_\mathbb_E[\epsilon, _Y+\delta]_=_0. These_are_analogous_with_the_equivalent_definitions_of_first-order_stochastic_dominance,_given_above.


_Sufficient_conditions

*_First-order_stochastic_dominance_of_''A''_over_''B''_is_a_sufficient_condition_for_second-order_dominance_of_''A''_over_''B''. *_If_''B''_is_a_mean-preserving_spread_of_''A'',_then_''A''_second-order_stochastically_dominates_''B''.


_Necessary_conditions

*_\mathbb_E_\rho(x)_\geq_\mathbb_E_\nu(x)_is_a_necessary_condition_for_''A''_to_second-order_stochastically_dominate_''B''. *_\min_\rho(x)\geq_\min_\nu(x)_is_a_necessary_condition_for_''A''_to_second-order_dominate_''B''._The_condition_implies_that_the_left_tail_of_F_\nu_must_be_thicker_than_the_left_tail_of_F_\rho.


_Third-order

Let_F_\rho_and_F_\nu_be_the_cumulative_distribution_functions_of_two_distinct_investments_\rho_and_\nu._\rho_dominates_\nu_in_the_third_order_if_and_only_if_both *_\int_^x_\left(\int_^z_[F_\nu(t)_-_F_\rho(t)]_\,_dt\right)_dz_\geq_0_\text_x, *_\mathbb_E_\rho(x)_\geq_\mathbb_E_\nu(x)_. Equivalently,_\rho_dominates_\nu_in_the_third_order_if_and_only_if_\mathbb_E_\rho_U(x)_\geq_\mathbb_E_\nu_U(x)_for_all_U\in_D_3._ The_set_D_3_has_two_equivalent_definitions: *_the_set_of_nondecreasing,_concave_utility_functions_that_are_Skewness, positively_skewed_(that_is,_have_a_nonnegative_third_derivative_throughout). *_the_set_of_nondecreasing,_concave_utility_functions,_such_that_for_any_random_variable_Z,_the_Risk_premium, risk-premium_function_\pi_u(x,_Z)_is_a_monotonically_nonincreasing_function_of_x. Here,_\pi_u(x,_Z)_is_defined_as_the_solution_to_the_problemu(x_+_\mathbb_E[Z]_-_\pi)_=_\mathbb_E_[u(x_+_Z)].See_more_details_at_risk_premium_page.


_Sufficient_condition

*_Second-order_dominance_is_a_sufficient_condition.


_Necessary_conditions

*_\mathbb_E_\rho(\log(x))\geq_\mathbb_E_\nu(\log(x))_is_a_necessary_condition._The_condition_implies_that_the_geometric_mean_of_\rho_must_be_greater_than_or_equal_to_the_geometric_mean_of_\nu. *_\min_\rho(x)\geq\min_\nu(x)_is_a_necessary_condition._The_condition_implies_that_the_left_tail_of_F_\nu_must_be_thicker_than_the_left_tail_of_F_\rho.


_Higher-order

Higher_orders_of_stochastic_dominance_have_also_been_analyzed,_as_have_generalizations_of_the_dual_relationship_between_stochastic_dominance_orderings_and_classes_of_preference_functions. Arguably_the_most_powerful_dominance_criterion_relies_on_the_accepted_economic_assumption_of_Risk_aversion#Absolute_risk_aversion, decreasing_absolute_risk_aversion. This_involves_several_analytical_challenges_and_a_research_effort_is_on_its_way_to_address_those. Formally,_the_n-th-order_stochastic_dominance_is_defined_as_ *_For_any_probability_distribution_\rho_on_[0,_\infty),_define_the_functions_inductively: F^1_\rho(t)_=_F_\rho(t),_\quad_F^2_\rho(t)_=_\int_0^t_F^1_\rho(x)dx,_\quad_\cdots *_For_any_two_probability_distributions_\rho,_\nu_on_[0,_\infty),_non-strict_and_strict_n-th-order_stochastic_dominance_is_defined_as\rho_\succeq_n_\nu_\quad_\text_\quad_F^n_\rho_\geq_F^n_\nu_\text__[0,_\infty)\rho_\succ_n_\nu_\quad_\text_\quad\rho_\succeq_n_\nu_\text_\rho_\neq_\nu These_relations_are_transitive_and_increasingly_more_inclusive._That_is,_if_\rho_\succeq_n_\nu,_then_\rho_\succeq__\nu_for_all_k_\geq_n._Further,_there_exists_\rho,_\nu_such_that_\rho_\succeq__\nu_but_not_\rho_\succeq_n_\nu. Define_the_n-th_moment_by_\mu_k(\rho)_=_\mathbb_E_[X^k]_=_\int_x^k_dF_\rho(x),_then


_Constraints

Stochastic_dominance_relations_may_be_used_as_constraints_in_problems_of_mathematical_optimization,_in_particular_stochastic_programming._In_a_problem_of_maximizing_a_real_functional__f(X)_over_random_variables__X__in_a_set__X_0__we_may_additionally_require_that__X__stochastically_dominates_a_fixed_random_''benchmark''__B_._In_these_problems,_utility_functions_play_the_role_of_Lagrange_multipliers_associated_with_ stochastic_dominance_constraints._Under_appropriate_conditions,_the_solution_of_the_problem_is_also_a_(possibly_local)_solution_of_the_problem_to_maximize _f(X)_+_\mathbb_E[u(X)_-_u(B)]__over__X__in__X_0_,_where__u(x)__is_a_certain_utility_function._If_the first_order_stochastic_dominance_constraint_is_employed,_the_utility_function__u(x)__is_monotonic_function, nondecreasing;_ if_the_second_order_stochastic_dominance_constraint_is_used,__u(x)__is_monotonic_function, nondecreasing_and_concave_function, concave._A_system_of_linear_equations_can_test_whether_a_given_solution_if_efficient_for_any_such_utility_function. Third-order_stochastic_dominance_constraints_can_be_dealt_with_using_convex_quadratically_constrained_programming_(QCP).


_See_also

*Modern_portfolio_theory *Marginal_conditional_stochastic_dominance *Responsive_set_extension_-_equivalent_to_stochastic_dominance_in_the_context_of_preference_relations. *Quantum_catalyst *Ordinal_Pareto_efficiency *Lexicographic_dominance


_References

{{DEFAULTSORT:Stochastic_Dominance Random_variable_ordering].html" ;"title="X, ], \mathbb E_[, X, ] are both finite, then the following conditions are equivalent, thus they may all serve as the definition of first-order stochastic dominance: * For any u: \R \to \R that is non-decreasing, \mathbb E_[u(X)] \geq \mathbb E_[u(X)] * F_\rho(t) \leq F_\nu(t), \quad \forall t \in \R. * There exists two random variables X\sim \rho, Y \sim \nu, such that X = Y + \delta, where \delta \geq 0. The first definition states that a gamble \rho first-order stochastically dominates gamble \nu if and only if every expected utility hypothesis, expected utility maximizer with an increasing utility, utility function prefers gamble \rho over gamble \nu. The third definition states that we can construct a pair of gambles X, Y with distributions \mu, \nu, such that gamble X always pays at least as much as gamble Y. More concretely, construct first a uniformly distributed Z\sim Uniform(0, 1), then use the inverse transform sampling to get X = F_X^(Z), Y = F_Y^(Z), then X \geq Y for any Z. Pictorially, the second and third definition are equivalent, because we can go from the graphed density function of A to that of B both by pushing it upwards and pushing it leftwards.


Extended example

Consider three gambles over a single toss of a fair six-sided die: : \begin \text & 1 & 2 & 3 & 4 & 5 & 6 \\ \hline \text\$ & 1 & 1 & 2 & 2 & 2 & 2 \\ \text\$ & 1 & 1 & 1 & 2 & 2 & 2 \\ \text\$ & 3 & 3 & 3 & 1 & 1 & 1 \\ \hline \end Gamble A statewise dominates gamble B because A gives at least as good a yield in all possible states (outcomes of the die roll) and gives a strictly better yield in one of them (state 3). Since A statewise dominates B, it also first-order dominates B. Gamble C does not statewise dominate B because B gives a better yield in states 4 through 6, but C first-order stochastically dominates B because Pr(B ≥ 1) = Pr(C ≥ 1) = 1, Pr(B ≥ 2) = Pr(C ≥ 2) = 3/6, and Pr(B ≥ 3) = 0 while Pr(C ≥ 3) = 3/6 > Pr(B ≥ 3). Gambles A and C cannot be ordered relative to each other on the basis of first-order stochastic dominance because Pr(A ≥ 2) = 4/6 > Pr(C ≥ 2) = 3/6 while on the other hand Pr(C ≥ 3) = 3/6 > Pr(A ≥ 3) = 0. In general, although when one gamble first-order stochastically dominates a second gamble, the expected value of the payoff under the first will be greater than the expected value of the payoff under the second, the converse is not true: one cannot order lotteries with regard to stochastic dominance simply by comparing the means of their probability distributions. For instance, in the above example C has a higher mean (2) than does A (5/3), yet C does not first-order dominate A.


Second-order

The other commonly used type of stochastic dominance is second-order stochastic dominance. Roughly speaking, for two gambles \rho and \nu, gamble \rho has second-order stochastic dominance over gamble \nu if the former is more predictable (i.e. involves less risk) and has at least as high a mean. All risk aversion, risk-averse Expected utility hypothesis, expected-utility maximizers (that is, those with increasing and concave utility functions) prefer a second-order stochastically dominant gamble to a dominated one. Second-order dominance describes the shared preferences of a smaller class of decision-makers (those for whom more is better ''and'' who are averse to risk, rather than ''all'' those for whom more is better) than does first-order dominance. In terms of cumulative distribution functions F_\rho and F_\nu, \rho is second-order stochastically dominant over \nu if and only if \int_^x [F_\nu(t) - F_\rho(t)] \, dt \geq 0 for all x, with strict inequality at some x. Equivalently, \rho dominates \nu in the second order if and only if \mathbb E_[u(X)] \geq \mathbb E_[u(X)] for all nondecreasing and concave function, concave utility functions u(x). Second-order stochastic dominance can also be expressed as follows: Gamble \rho second-order stochastically dominates \nu if and only if there exist some gambles y and z such that x_\nu \overset (x_\rho + y + z), with y always less than or equal to zero, and with \mathbb E(z\mid x_\rho+y)=0 for all values of x_\rho+y. Here the introduction of random variable y makes \nu first-order stochastically dominated by \rho (making \nu disliked by those with an increasing utility function), and the introduction of random variable z introduces a mean-preserving spread in \nu which is disliked by those with concave utility. Note that if \rho and \nu have the same mean (so that the random variable y degenerates to the fixed number 0), then \nu is a mean-preserving spread of \rho.


Equivalent definitions

Let \rho, \nu be two probability distributions on \R, such that \mathbb E_[, X, ], \mathbb E_[, X, ] are both finite, then the following conditions are equivalent, thus they may all serve as the definition of second-order stochastic dominance: * For any u: \R \to \R that is non-decreasing, and (not necessarily strictly) concave,\mathbb E_[u(X)] \geq \mathbb E_[u(X)] * \int_^t F_\rho(x) dx \leq \int_^t F_\nu(x) dx, \quad \forall t \in \R. * There exists two random variables X\sim \rho, Y \sim \nu, such that X = Y + \delta + \epsilon, where \delta \geq 0 and \mathbb E[\epsilon, Y+\delta] = 0. These are analogous with the equivalent definitions of first-order stochastic dominance, given above.


Sufficient conditions

* First-order stochastic dominance of ''A'' over ''B'' is a sufficient condition for second-order dominance of ''A'' over ''B''. * If ''B'' is a mean-preserving spread of ''A'', then ''A'' second-order stochastically dominates ''B''.


Necessary conditions

* \mathbb E_\rho(x) \geq \mathbb E_\nu(x) is a necessary condition for ''A'' to second-order stochastically dominate ''B''. * \min_\rho(x)\geq \min_\nu(x) is a necessary condition for ''A'' to second-order dominate ''B''. The condition implies that the left tail of F_\nu must be thicker than the left tail of F_\rho.


Third-order

Let F_\rho and F_\nu be the cumulative distribution functions of two distinct investments \rho and \nu. \rho dominates \nu in the third order if and only if both * \int_^x \left(\int_^z [F_\nu(t) - F_\rho(t)] \, dt\right) dz \geq 0 \text x, * \mathbb E_\rho(x) \geq \mathbb E_\nu(x) . Equivalently, \rho dominates \nu in the third order if and only if \mathbb E_\rho U(x) \geq \mathbb E_\nu U(x) for all U\in D_3. The set D_3 has two equivalent definitions: * the set of nondecreasing, concave utility functions that are Skewness, positively skewed (that is, have a nonnegative third derivative throughout). * the set of nondecreasing, concave utility functions, such that for any random variable Z, the Risk premium, risk-premium function \pi_u(x, Z) is a monotonically nonincreasing function of x. Here, \pi_u(x, Z) is defined as the solution to the problemu(x + \mathbb E[Z] - \pi) = \mathbb E [u(x + Z)].See more details at risk premium page.


Sufficient condition

* Second-order dominance is a sufficient condition.


Necessary conditions

* \mathbb E_\rho(\log(x))\geq \mathbb E_\nu(\log(x)) is a necessary condition. The condition implies that the geometric mean of \rho must be greater than or equal to the geometric mean of \nu. * \min_\rho(x)\geq\min_\nu(x) is a necessary condition. The condition implies that the left tail of F_\nu must be thicker than the left tail of F_\rho.


Higher-order

Higher orders of stochastic dominance have also been analyzed, as have generalizations of the dual relationship between stochastic dominance orderings and classes of preference functions. Arguably the most powerful dominance criterion relies on the accepted economic assumption of Risk aversion#Absolute risk aversion, decreasing absolute risk aversion. This involves several analytical challenges and a research effort is on its way to address those. Formally, the n-th-order stochastic dominance is defined as * For any probability distribution \rho on [0, \infty), define the functions inductively: F^1_\rho(t) = F_\rho(t), \quad F^2_\rho(t) = \int_0^t F^1_\rho(x)dx, \quad \cdots * For any two probability distributions \rho, \nu on [0, \infty), non-strict and strict n-th-order stochastic dominance is defined as\rho \succeq_n \nu \quad \text \quad F^n_\rho \geq F^n_\nu \text [0, \infty)\rho \succ_n \nu \quad \text \quad\rho \succeq_n \nu \text \rho \neq \nu These relations are transitive and increasingly more inclusive. That is, if \rho \succeq_n \nu, then \rho \succeq_ \nu for all k \geq n. Further, there exists \rho, \nu such that \rho \succeq_ \nu but not \rho \succeq_n \nu. Define the n-th moment by \mu_k(\rho) = \mathbb E_[X^k] = \int x^k dF_\rho(x), then


Constraints

Stochastic dominance relations may be used as constraints in problems of mathematical optimization, in particular stochastic programming. In a problem of maximizing a real functional f(X) over random variables X in a set X_0 we may additionally require that X stochastically dominates a fixed random ''benchmark'' B . In these problems, utility functions play the role of Lagrange multipliers associated with stochastic dominance constraints. Under appropriate conditions, the solution of the problem is also a (possibly local) solution of the problem to maximize f(X) + \mathbb E[u(X) - u(B)] over X in X_0 , where u(x) is a certain utility function. If the first order stochastic dominance constraint is employed, the utility function u(x) is monotonic function, nondecreasing; if the second order stochastic dominance constraint is used, u(x) is monotonic function, nondecreasing and concave function, concave. A system of linear equations can test whether a given solution if efficient for any such utility function. Third-order stochastic dominance constraints can be dealt with using convex quadratically constrained programming (QCP).


See also

*Modern portfolio theory *Marginal conditional stochastic dominance *Responsive set extension - equivalent to stochastic dominance in the context of preference relations. *Quantum catalyst *Ordinal Pareto efficiency *Lexicographic dominance


References

{{DEFAULTSORT:Stochastic Dominance Random variable ordering]">X, \mathbb E_[, X, ] are both finite, then the following conditions are equivalent, thus they may all serve as the definition of first-order stochastic dominance: * For any u: \R \to \R that is non-decreasing, \mathbb E_[u(X)] \geq \mathbb E_[u(X)] * F_\rho(t) \leq F_\nu(t), \quad \forall t \in \R. * There exists two random variables X\sim \rho, Y \sim \nu, such that X = Y + \delta, where \delta \geq 0. The first definition states that a gamble \rho first-order stochastically dominates gamble \nu if and only if every expected utility hypothesis, expected utility maximizer with an increasing utility, utility function prefers gamble \rho over gamble \nu. The third definition states that we can construct a pair of gambles X, Y with distributions \mu, \nu, such that gamble X always pays at least as much as gamble Y. More concretely, construct first a uniformly distributed Z\sim Uniform(0, 1), then use the inverse transform sampling to get X = F_X^(Z), Y = F_Y^(Z), then X \geq Y for any Z. Pictorially, the second and third definition are equivalent, because we can go from the graphed density function of A to that of B both by pushing it upwards and pushing it leftwards.


Extended example

Consider three gambles over a single toss of a fair six-sided die: : \begin \text & 1 & 2 & 3 & 4 & 5 & 6 \\ \hline \text\$ & 1 & 1 & 2 & 2 & 2 & 2 \\ \text\$ & 1 & 1 & 1 & 2 & 2 & 2 \\ \text\$ & 3 & 3 & 3 & 1 & 1 & 1 \\ \hline \end Gamble A statewise dominates gamble B because A gives at least as good a yield in all possible states (outcomes of the die roll) and gives a strictly better yield in one of them (state 3). Since A statewise dominates B, it also first-order dominates B. Gamble C does not statewise dominate B because B gives a better yield in states 4 through 6, but C first-order stochastically dominates B because Pr(B ≥ 1) = Pr(C ≥ 1) = 1, Pr(B ≥ 2) = Pr(C ≥ 2) = 3/6, and Pr(B ≥ 3) = 0 while Pr(C ≥ 3) = 3/6 > Pr(B ≥ 3). Gambles A and C cannot be ordered relative to each other on the basis of first-order stochastic dominance because Pr(A ≥ 2) = 4/6 > Pr(C ≥ 2) = 3/6 while on the other hand Pr(C ≥ 3) = 3/6 > Pr(A ≥ 3) = 0. In general, although when one gamble first-order stochastically dominates a second gamble, the expected value of the payoff under the first will be greater than the expected value of the payoff under the second, the converse is not true: one cannot order lotteries with regard to stochastic dominance simply by comparing the means of their probability distributions. For instance, in the above example C has a higher mean (2) than does A (5/3), yet C does not first-order dominate A.


Second-order

The other commonly used type of stochastic dominance is second-order stochastic dominance. Roughly speaking, for two gambles \rho and \nu, gamble \rho has second-order stochastic dominance over gamble \nu if the former is more predictable (i.e. involves less risk) and has at least as high a mean. All risk aversion, risk-averse Expected utility hypothesis, expected-utility maximizers (that is, those with increasing and concave utility functions) prefer a second-order stochastically dominant gamble to a dominated one. Second-order dominance describes the shared preferences of a smaller class of decision-makers (those for whom more is better ''and'' who are averse to risk, rather than ''all'' those for whom more is better) than does first-order dominance. In terms of cumulative distribution functions F_\rho and F_\nu, \rho is second-order stochastically dominant over \nu if and only if \int_^x [F_\nu(t) - F_\rho(t)] \, dt \geq 0 for all x, with strict inequality at some x. Equivalently, \rho dominates \nu in the second order if and only if \mathbb E_[u(X)] \geq \mathbb E_[u(X)] for all nondecreasing and concave function, concave utility functions u(x). Second-order stochastic dominance can also be expressed as follows: Gamble \rho second-order stochastically dominates \nu if and only if there exist some gambles y and z such that x_\nu \overset (x_\rho + y + z), with y always less than or equal to zero, and with \mathbb E(z\mid x_\rho+y)=0 for all values of x_\rho+y. Here the introduction of random variable y makes \nu first-order stochastically dominated by \rho (making \nu disliked by those with an increasing utility function), and the introduction of random variable z introduces a mean-preserving spread in \nu which is disliked by those with concave utility. Note that if \rho and \nu have the same mean (so that the random variable y degenerates to the fixed number 0), then \nu is a mean-preserving spread of \rho.


Equivalent definitions

Let \rho, \nu be two probability distributions on \R, such that \mathbb E_ X, _are_both_finite,_then_the_following_conditions_are_equivalent,_thus_they_may_all_serve_as_the_definition_of_first-order_stochastic_dominance: *_For_any_u:_\R_\to_\R_that_is_non-decreasing,_\mathbb_E_
(X) An emoticon (, , rarely , ), short for "emotion icon", also known simply as an emote, is a pictorial representation of a facial expression using characters—usually punctuation marks, numbers, and letters—to express a person's feelings, ...
\geq_\mathbb_E_
(X) An emoticon (, , rarely , ), short for "emotion icon", also known simply as an emote, is a pictorial representation of a facial expression using characters—usually punctuation marks, numbers, and letters—to express a person's feelings, ...
*_F_\rho(t)_\leq_F_\nu(t),_\quad_\forall_t_\in_\R. *_There_exists_two_random_variables_X\sim_\rho,_Y_\sim_\nu,_such_that_X_=_Y_+_\delta,_where_\delta_\geq_0. The_first_definition_states_that_a_gamble_\rho_first-order_stochastically_dominates_gamble_\nu_
if_and_only_if In logic and related fields such as mathematics and philosophy, "if and only if" (shortened as "iff") is a biconditional logical connective between statements, where either both statements are true or both are false. The connective is b ...
_every_
expected_utility The expected utility hypothesis is a popular concept in economics that serves as a reference guide for decisions when the payoff is uncertain. The theory recommends which option rational individuals should choose in a complex situation, based on the ...
_maximizer_with_an_increasing_
utility_function As a topic of economics, utility is used to model worth or value. Its usage has evolved significantly over time. The term was introduced initially as a measure of pleasure or happiness as part of the theory of utilitarianism by moral philosoph ...
_prefers_gamble_\rho_over_gamble_\nu. The_third_definition_states_that_we_can_construct_a_pair_of_gambles_X,_Y_with_distributions_\mu,_\nu,_such_that_gamble_X_always_pays_at_least_as_much_as_gamble_Y._More_concretely,_construct_first_a_uniformly_distributed_Z\sim_Uniform(0,_1),_then_use_the_
inverse_transform_sampling Inverse transform sampling (also known as inversion sampling, the inverse probability integral transform, the inverse transformation method, Smirnov transform, or the golden ruleAalto University, N. Hyvönen, Computational methods in inverse probl ...
_to_get_X_=_F_X^(Z),_Y_=_F_Y^(Z),_then_X_\geq_Y_for_any_Z. Pictorially,_the_second_and_third_definition_are_equivalent,_because_we_can_go_from_the_graphed_density_function_of_A_to_that_of_B_both_by_pushing_it_upwards_and_pushing_it_leftwards.


__Extended_example_

Consider_three_gambles_over_a_single_toss_of_a_fair_six-sided_die: :_ \begin \text_&_1_&_2_&_3_&_4_&_5_&_6_\\ \hline \text\$_&_1_&_1_&_2_&_2_&_2_&_2_\\ \text\$_&_1_&_1_&_1_&_2_&_2_&_2_\\ \text\$_&_3_&_3_&_3_&_1_&_1_&_1_\\ \hline \end Gamble_A_statewise_dominates_gamble_B_because_A_gives_at_least_as_good_a_yield_in_all_possible_states_(outcomes_of_the_die_roll)_and_gives_a_strictly_better_yield_in_one_of_them_(state_3)._Since_A_statewise_dominates_B,_it_also_first-order_dominates_B. Gamble_C_does_not_statewise_dominate_B_because_B_gives_a_better_yield_in_states_4_through_6,_but_C_first-order_stochastically_dominates_B_because_Pr(B_≥_1)_=_Pr(C_≥_1)_=_1,_Pr(B_≥_2)_=_Pr(C_≥_2)_=_3/6,_and_Pr(B_≥_3)_=_0_while_Pr(C_≥_3)_=_3/6_>_Pr(B_≥_3). Gambles_A_and_C_cannot_be_ordered_relative_to_each_other_on_the_basis_of_first-order_stochastic_dominance_because_Pr(A_≥_2)_=_4/6_>_Pr(C_≥_2)_=_3/6_while_on_the_other_hand_Pr(C_≥_3)_=_3/6_>_Pr(A_≥_3)_=_0. In_general,_although_when_one_gamble_first-order_stochastically_dominates_a_second_gamble,_the_expected_value_of_the_payoff_under_the_first_will_be_greater_than_the_expected_value_of_the_payoff_under_the_second,_the_converse_is_not_true:_one_cannot_order_lotteries_with_regard_to_stochastic_dominance_simply_by_comparing_the_means_of_their_probability_distributions._For_instance,_in_the_above_example_C_has_a_higher_mean_(2)_than_does_A_(5/3),_yet_C_does_not_first-order_dominate_A.


_Second-order

The_other_commonly_used_type_of_stochastic_dominance_is_second-order_stochastic_dominance._Roughly_speaking,_for_two_gambles_\rho_and_\nu,_gamble_\rho_has_second-order_stochastic_dominance_over_gamble_\nu_if_the_former_is_more_predictable_(i.e._involves_less_risk)_and_has_at_least_as_high_a_mean.__All_
risk-averse In economics and finance, risk aversion is the tendency of people to prefer outcomes with low uncertainty to those outcomes with high uncertainty, even if the average outcome of the latter is equal to or higher in monetary value than the more ce ...
_ expected-utility_maximizers_(that_is,_those_with_increasing_and_concave_utility_functions)_prefer_a_second-order_stochastically_dominant_gamble_to_a_dominated_one._Second-order_dominance_describes_the_shared_preferences_of_a_smaller_class_of_decision-makers_(those_for_whom_more_is_better_''and''_who_are_averse_to_risk,_rather_than_''all''_those_for_whom_more_is_better)_than_does_first-order_dominance. In_terms_of_cumulative_distribution_functions_F_\rho_and_F_\nu,_\rho_is_second-order_stochastically_dominant_over_\nu_if_and_only_if_\int_^x_[F_\nu(t)_-_F_\rho(t)]_\,_dt_\geq_0_for_all_x,_with_strict_inequality_at_some_x._Equivalently,_\rho_dominates_\nu_in_the_second_order_if_and_only_if_\mathbb_E_
(X) An emoticon (, , rarely , ), short for "emotion icon", also known simply as an emote, is a pictorial representation of a facial expression using characters—usually punctuation marks, numbers, and letters—to express a person's feelings, ...
\geq_\mathbb_E_[u(X)]_for_all_nondecreasing_and_concave_function, concave_utility_functions_u(x). Second-order_stochastic_dominance_can_also_be_expressed_as_follows:_Gamble_\rho_second-order_stochastically_dominates_\nu_if_and_only_if_there_exist_some_gambles_y_and_z_such_that__x_\nu_\overset__(x_\rho_+_y_+_z),_with_y_always_less_than_or_equal_to_zero,_and_with_\mathbb_E(z\mid_x_\rho+y)=0_for_all_values_of_x_\rho+y._Here_the_introduction_of_random_variable_y_makes_\nu_first-order_stochastically_dominated_by_\rho_(making_\nu_disliked_by_those_with_an_increasing_utility_function),_and_the_introduction_of_random_variable_z_introduces_a_mean-preserving_spread_in_\nu_which_is_disliked_by_those_with_concave_utility._Note_that_if_\rho_and_\nu_have_the_same_mean_(so_that_the_random_variable_y_degenerates_to_the_fixed_number_0),_then_\nu_is_a_mean-preserving_spread_of_\rho.


__Equivalent_definitions_

Let_\rho,_\nu_be_two_probability_distributions_on_\R,_such_that_\mathbb_E_[, X, ],_\mathbb_E_ X, _are_both_finite,_then_the_following_conditions_are_equivalent,_thus_they_may_all_serve_as_the_definition_of_second-order_stochastic_dominance:
*_For_any_u:_\R_\to_\R_that_is_non-decreasing,_and_(not_necessarily_strictly)_concave,\mathbb_E_
(X) An emoticon (, , rarely , ), short for "emotion icon", also known simply as an emote, is a pictorial representation of a facial expression using characters—usually punctuation marks, numbers, and letters—to express a person's feelings, ...
\geq_\mathbb_E_
(X) An emoticon (, , rarely , ), short for "emotion icon", also known simply as an emote, is a pictorial representation of a facial expression using characters—usually punctuation marks, numbers, and letters—to express a person's feelings, ...
*_\int_^t_F_\rho(x)_dx_\leq_\int_^t_F_\nu(x)_dx,_\quad_\forall_t_\in_\R. *_There_exists_two_random_variables_X\sim_\rho,_Y_\sim_\nu,_such_that_X_=_Y_+_\delta_+_\epsilon,_where_\delta_\geq_0_and_\mathbb_E[\epsilon, _Y+\delta]_=_0. These_are_analogous_with_the_equivalent_definitions_of_first-order_stochastic_dominance,_given_above.


_Sufficient_conditions

*_First-order_stochastic_dominance_of_''A''_over_''B''_is_a_sufficient_condition_for_second-order_dominance_of_''A''_over_''B''. *_If_''B''_is_a_mean-preserving_spread_of_''A'',_then_''A''_second-order_stochastically_dominates_''B''.


_Necessary_conditions

*_\mathbb_E_\rho(x)_\geq_\mathbb_E_\nu(x)_is_a_necessary_condition_for_''A''_to_second-order_stochastically_dominate_''B''. *_\min_\rho(x)\geq_\min_\nu(x)_is_a_necessary_condition_for_''A''_to_second-order_dominate_''B''._The_condition_implies_that_the_left_tail_of_F_\nu_must_be_thicker_than_the_left_tail_of_F_\rho.


_Third-order

Let_F_\rho_and_F_\nu_be_the_cumulative_distribution_functions_of_two_distinct_investments_\rho_and_\nu._\rho_dominates_\nu_in_the_third_order_if_and_only_if_both *_\int_^x_\left(\int_^z_[F_\nu(t)_-_F_\rho(t)]_\,_dt\right)_dz_\geq_0_\text_x, *_\mathbb_E_\rho(x)_\geq_\mathbb_E_\nu(x)_. Equivalently,_\rho_dominates_\nu_in_the_third_order_if_and_only_if_\mathbb_E_\rho_U(x)_\geq_\mathbb_E_\nu_U(x)_for_all_U\in_D_3._ The_set_D_3_has_two_equivalent_definitions: *_the_set_of_nondecreasing,_concave_utility_functions_that_are_Skewness, positively_skewed_(that_is,_have_a_nonnegative_third_derivative_throughout). *_the_set_of_nondecreasing,_concave_utility_functions,_such_that_for_any_random_variable_Z,_the_Risk_premium, risk-premium_function_\pi_u(x,_Z)_is_a_monotonically_nonincreasing_function_of_x. Here,_\pi_u(x,_Z)_is_defined_as_the_solution_to_the_problemu(x_+_\mathbb_E[Z]_-_\pi)_=_\mathbb_E_[u(x_+_Z)].See_more_details_at_risk_premium_page.


_Sufficient_condition

*_Second-order_dominance_is_a_sufficient_condition.


_Necessary_conditions

*_\mathbb_E_\rho(\log(x))\geq_\mathbb_E_\nu(\log(x))_is_a_necessary_condition._The_condition_implies_that_the_geometric_mean_of_\rho_must_be_greater_than_or_equal_to_the_geometric_mean_of_\nu. *_\min_\rho(x)\geq\min_\nu(x)_is_a_necessary_condition._The_condition_implies_that_the_left_tail_of_F_\nu_must_be_thicker_than_the_left_tail_of_F_\rho.


_Higher-order

Higher_orders_of_stochastic_dominance_have_also_been_analyzed,_as_have_generalizations_of_the_dual_relationship_between_stochastic_dominance_orderings_and_classes_of_preference_functions. Arguably_the_most_powerful_dominance_criterion_relies_on_the_accepted_economic_assumption_of_Risk_aversion#Absolute_risk_aversion, decreasing_absolute_risk_aversion. This_involves_several_analytical_challenges_and_a_research_effort_is_on_its_way_to_address_those. Formally,_the_n-th-order_stochastic_dominance_is_defined_as_ *_For_any_probability_distribution_\rho_on_[0,_\infty),_define_the_functions_inductively: F^1_\rho(t)_=_F_\rho(t),_\quad_F^2_\rho(t)_=_\int_0^t_F^1_\rho(x)dx,_\quad_\cdots *_For_any_two_probability_distributions_\rho,_\nu_on_[0,_\infty),_non-strict_and_strict_n-th-order_stochastic_dominance_is_defined_as\rho_\succeq_n_\nu_\quad_\text_\quad_F^n_\rho_\geq_F^n_\nu_\text__[0,_\infty)\rho_\succ_n_\nu_\quad_\text_\quad\rho_\succeq_n_\nu_\text_\rho_\neq_\nu These_relations_are_transitive_and_increasingly_more_inclusive._That_is,_if_\rho_\succeq_n_\nu,_then_\rho_\succeq__\nu_for_all_k_\geq_n._Further,_there_exists_\rho,_\nu_such_that_\rho_\succeq__\nu_but_not_\rho_\succeq_n_\nu. Define_the_n-th_moment_by_\mu_k(\rho)_=_\mathbb_E_[X^k]_=_\int_x^k_dF_\rho(x),_then


_Constraints

Stochastic_dominance_relations_may_be_used_as_constraints_in_problems_of_mathematical_optimization,_in_particular_stochastic_programming._In_a_problem_of_maximizing_a_real_functional__f(X)_over_random_variables__X__in_a_set__X_0__we_may_additionally_require_that__X__stochastically_dominates_a_fixed_random_''benchmark''__B_._In_these_problems,_utility_functions_play_the_role_of_Lagrange_multipliers_associated_with_ stochastic_dominance_constraints._Under_appropriate_conditions,_the_solution_of_the_problem_is_also_a_(possibly_local)_solution_of_the_problem_to_maximize _f(X)_+_\mathbb_E[u(X)_-_u(B)]__over__X__in__X_0_,_where__u(x)__is_a_certain_utility_function._If_the first_order_stochastic_dominance_constraint_is_employed,_the_utility_function__u(x)__is_monotonic_function, nondecreasing;_ if_the_second_order_stochastic_dominance_constraint_is_used,__u(x)__is_monotonic_function, nondecreasing_and_concave_function, concave._A_system_of_linear_equations_can_test_whether_a_given_solution_if_efficient_for_any_such_utility_function. Third-order_stochastic_dominance_constraints_can_be_dealt_with_using_convex_quadratically_constrained_programming_(QCP).


_See_also

*Modern_portfolio_theory *Marginal_conditional_stochastic_dominance *Responsive_set_extension_-_equivalent_to_stochastic_dominance_in_the_context_of_preference_relations. *Quantum_catalyst *Ordinal_Pareto_efficiency *Lexicographic_dominance


_References

{{DEFAULTSORT:Stochastic_Dominance Random_variable_ordering].html" ;"title="X, ], \mathbb E_[, X, ] are both finite, then the following conditions are equivalent, thus they may all serve as the definition of first-order stochastic dominance: * For any u: \R \to \R that is non-decreasing, \mathbb E_[u(X)] \geq \mathbb E_[u(X)] * F_\rho(t) \leq F_\nu(t), \quad \forall t \in \R. * There exists two random variables X\sim \rho, Y \sim \nu, such that X = Y + \delta, where \delta \geq 0. The first definition states that a gamble \rho first-order stochastically dominates gamble \nu if and only if every expected utility hypothesis, expected utility maximizer with an increasing utility, utility function prefers gamble \rho over gamble \nu. The third definition states that we can construct a pair of gambles X, Y with distributions \mu, \nu, such that gamble X always pays at least as much as gamble Y. More concretely, construct first a uniformly distributed Z\sim Uniform(0, 1), then use the inverse transform sampling to get X = F_X^(Z), Y = F_Y^(Z), then X \geq Y for any Z. Pictorially, the second and third definition are equivalent, because we can go from the graphed density function of A to that of B both by pushing it upwards and pushing it leftwards.


Extended example

Consider three gambles over a single toss of a fair six-sided die: : \begin \text & 1 & 2 & 3 & 4 & 5 & 6 \\ \hline \text\$ & 1 & 1 & 2 & 2 & 2 & 2 \\ \text\$ & 1 & 1 & 1 & 2 & 2 & 2 \\ \text\$ & 3 & 3 & 3 & 1 & 1 & 1 \\ \hline \end Gamble A statewise dominates gamble B because A gives at least as good a yield in all possible states (outcomes of the die roll) and gives a strictly better yield in one of them (state 3). Since A statewise dominates B, it also first-order dominates B. Gamble C does not statewise dominate B because B gives a better yield in states 4 through 6, but C first-order stochastically dominates B because Pr(B ≥ 1) = Pr(C ≥ 1) = 1, Pr(B ≥ 2) = Pr(C ≥ 2) = 3/6, and Pr(B ≥ 3) = 0 while Pr(C ≥ 3) = 3/6 > Pr(B ≥ 3). Gambles A and C cannot be ordered relative to each other on the basis of first-order stochastic dominance because Pr(A ≥ 2) = 4/6 > Pr(C ≥ 2) = 3/6 while on the other hand Pr(C ≥ 3) = 3/6 > Pr(A ≥ 3) = 0. In general, although when one gamble first-order stochastically dominates a second gamble, the expected value of the payoff under the first will be greater than the expected value of the payoff under the second, the converse is not true: one cannot order lotteries with regard to stochastic dominance simply by comparing the means of their probability distributions. For instance, in the above example C has a higher mean (2) than does A (5/3), yet C does not first-order dominate A.


Second-order

The other commonly used type of stochastic dominance is second-order stochastic dominance. Roughly speaking, for two gambles \rho and \nu, gamble \rho has second-order stochastic dominance over gamble \nu if the former is more predictable (i.e. involves less risk) and has at least as high a mean. All risk aversion, risk-averse Expected utility hypothesis, expected-utility maximizers (that is, those with increasing and concave utility functions) prefer a second-order stochastically dominant gamble to a dominated one. Second-order dominance describes the shared preferences of a smaller class of decision-makers (those for whom more is better ''and'' who are averse to risk, rather than ''all'' those for whom more is better) than does first-order dominance. In terms of cumulative distribution functions F_\rho and F_\nu, \rho is second-order stochastically dominant over \nu if and only if \int_^x [F_\nu(t) - F_\rho(t)] \, dt \geq 0 for all x, with strict inequality at some x. Equivalently, \rho dominates \nu in the second order if and only if \mathbb E_[u(X)] \geq \mathbb E_[u(X)] for all nondecreasing and concave function, concave utility functions u(x). Second-order stochastic dominance can also be expressed as follows: Gamble \rho second-order stochastically dominates \nu if and only if there exist some gambles y and z such that x_\nu \overset (x_\rho + y + z), with y always less than or equal to zero, and with \mathbb E(z\mid x_\rho+y)=0 for all values of x_\rho+y. Here the introduction of random variable y makes \nu first-order stochastically dominated by \rho (making \nu disliked by those with an increasing utility function), and the introduction of random variable z introduces a mean-preserving spread in \nu which is disliked by those with concave utility. Note that if \rho and \nu have the same mean (so that the random variable y degenerates to the fixed number 0), then \nu is a mean-preserving spread of \rho.


Equivalent definitions

Let \rho, \nu be two probability distributions on \R, such that \mathbb E_[, X, ], \mathbb E_[, X, ] are both finite, then the following conditions are equivalent, thus they may all serve as the definition of second-order stochastic dominance: * For any u: \R \to \R that is non-decreasing, and (not necessarily strictly) concave,\mathbb E_[u(X)] \geq \mathbb E_[u(X)] * \int_^t F_\rho(x) dx \leq \int_^t F_\nu(x) dx, \quad \forall t \in \R. * There exists two random variables X\sim \rho, Y \sim \nu, such that X = Y + \delta + \epsilon, where \delta \geq 0 and \mathbb E[\epsilon, Y+\delta] = 0. These are analogous with the equivalent definitions of first-order stochastic dominance, given above.


Sufficient conditions

* First-order stochastic dominance of ''A'' over ''B'' is a sufficient condition for second-order dominance of ''A'' over ''B''. * If ''B'' is a mean-preserving spread of ''A'', then ''A'' second-order stochastically dominates ''B''.


Necessary conditions

* \mathbb E_\rho(x) \geq \mathbb E_\nu(x) is a necessary condition for ''A'' to second-order stochastically dominate ''B''. * \min_\rho(x)\geq \min_\nu(x) is a necessary condition for ''A'' to second-order dominate ''B''. The condition implies that the left tail of F_\nu must be thicker than the left tail of F_\rho.


Third-order

Let F_\rho and F_\nu be the cumulative distribution functions of two distinct investments \rho and \nu. \rho dominates \nu in the third order if and only if both * \int_^x \left(\int_^z [F_\nu(t) - F_\rho(t)] \, dt\right) dz \geq 0 \text x, * \mathbb E_\rho(x) \geq \mathbb E_\nu(x) . Equivalently, \rho dominates \nu in the third order if and only if \mathbb E_\rho U(x) \geq \mathbb E_\nu U(x) for all U\in D_3. The set D_3 has two equivalent definitions: * the set of nondecreasing, concave utility functions that are Skewness, positively skewed (that is, have a nonnegative third derivative throughout). * the set of nondecreasing, concave utility functions, such that for any random variable Z, the Risk premium, risk-premium function \pi_u(x, Z) is a monotonically nonincreasing function of x. Here, \pi_u(x, Z) is defined as the solution to the problemu(x + \mathbb E[Z] - \pi) = \mathbb E [u(x + Z)].See more details at risk premium page.


Sufficient condition

* Second-order dominance is a sufficient condition.


Necessary conditions

* \mathbb E_\rho(\log(x))\geq \mathbb E_\nu(\log(x)) is a necessary condition. The condition implies that the geometric mean of \rho must be greater than or equal to the geometric mean of \nu. * \min_\rho(x)\geq\min_\nu(x) is a necessary condition. The condition implies that the left tail of F_\nu must be thicker than the left tail of F_\rho.


Higher-order

Higher orders of stochastic dominance have also been analyzed, as have generalizations of the dual relationship between stochastic dominance orderings and classes of preference functions. Arguably the most powerful dominance criterion relies on the accepted economic assumption of Risk aversion#Absolute risk aversion, decreasing absolute risk aversion. This involves several analytical challenges and a research effort is on its way to address those. Formally, the n-th-order stochastic dominance is defined as * For any probability distribution \rho on [0, \infty), define the functions inductively: F^1_\rho(t) = F_\rho(t), \quad F^2_\rho(t) = \int_0^t F^1_\rho(x)dx, \quad \cdots * For any two probability distributions \rho, \nu on [0, \infty), non-strict and strict n-th-order stochastic dominance is defined as\rho \succeq_n \nu \quad \text \quad F^n_\rho \geq F^n_\nu \text [0, \infty)\rho \succ_n \nu \quad \text \quad\rho \succeq_n \nu \text \rho \neq \nu These relations are transitive and increasingly more inclusive. That is, if \rho \succeq_n \nu, then \rho \succeq_ \nu for all k \geq n. Further, there exists \rho, \nu such that \rho \succeq_ \nu but not \rho \succeq_n \nu. Define the n-th moment by \mu_k(\rho) = \mathbb E_[X^k] = \int x^k dF_\rho(x), then


Constraints

Stochastic dominance relations may be used as constraints in problems of mathematical optimization, in particular stochastic programming. In a problem of maximizing a real functional f(X) over random variables X in a set X_0 we may additionally require that X stochastically dominates a fixed random ''benchmark'' B . In these problems, utility functions play the role of Lagrange multipliers associated with stochastic dominance constraints. Under appropriate conditions, the solution of the problem is also a (possibly local) solution of the problem to maximize f(X) + \mathbb E[u(X) - u(B)] over X in X_0 , where u(x) is a certain utility function. If the first order stochastic dominance constraint is employed, the utility function u(x) is monotonic function, nondecreasing; if the second order stochastic dominance constraint is used, u(x) is monotonic function, nondecreasing and concave function, concave. A system of linear equations can test whether a given solution if efficient for any such utility function. Third-order stochastic dominance constraints can be dealt with using convex quadratically constrained programming (QCP).


See also

*Modern portfolio theory *Marginal conditional stochastic dominance *Responsive set extension - equivalent to stochastic dominance in the context of preference relations. *Quantum catalyst *Ordinal Pareto efficiency *Lexicographic dominance


References

{{DEFAULTSORT:Stochastic Dominance Random variable ordering]">X, \mathbb E_[, X, ] are both finite, then the following conditions are equivalent, thus they may all serve as the definition of second-order stochastic dominance: * For any u: \R \to \R that is non-decreasing, and (not necessarily strictly) concave,\mathbb E_[u(X)] \geq \mathbb E_[u(X)] * \int_^t F_\rho(x) dx \leq \int_^t F_\nu(x) dx, \quad \forall t \in \R. * There exists two random variables X\sim \rho, Y \sim \nu, such that X = Y + \delta + \epsilon, where \delta \geq 0 and \mathbb E[\epsilon, Y+\delta] = 0. These are analogous with the equivalent definitions of first-order stochastic dominance, given above.


Sufficient conditions

* First-order stochastic dominance of ''A'' over ''B'' is a sufficient condition for second-order dominance of ''A'' over ''B''. * If ''B'' is a mean-preserving spread of ''A'', then ''A'' second-order stochastically dominates ''B''.


Necessary conditions

* \mathbb E_\rho(x) \geq \mathbb E_\nu(x) is a necessary condition for ''A'' to second-order stochastically dominate ''B''. * \min_\rho(x)\geq \min_\nu(x) is a necessary condition for ''A'' to second-order dominate ''B''. The condition implies that the left tail of F_\nu must be thicker than the left tail of F_\rho.


Third-order

Let F_\rho and F_\nu be the cumulative distribution functions of two distinct investments \rho and \nu. \rho dominates \nu in the third order if and only if both * \int_^x \left(\int_^z [F_\nu(t) - F_\rho(t)] \, dt\right) dz \geq 0 \text x, * \mathbb E_\rho(x) \geq \mathbb E_\nu(x) . Equivalently, \rho dominates \nu in the third order if and only if \mathbb E_\rho U(x) \geq \mathbb E_\nu U(x) for all U\in D_3. The set D_3 has two equivalent definitions: * the set of nondecreasing, concave utility functions that are Skewness, positively skewed (that is, have a nonnegative third derivative throughout). * the set of nondecreasing, concave utility functions, such that for any random variable Z, the Risk premium, risk-premium function \pi_u(x, Z) is a monotonically nonincreasing function of x. Here, \pi_u(x, Z) is defined as the solution to the problemu(x + \mathbb E[Z] - \pi) = \mathbb E [u(x + Z)].See more details at risk premium page.


Sufficient condition

* Second-order dominance is a sufficient condition.


Necessary conditions

* \mathbb E_\rho(\log(x))\geq \mathbb E_\nu(\log(x)) is a necessary condition. The condition implies that the geometric mean of \rho must be greater than or equal to the geometric mean of \nu. * \min_\rho(x)\geq\min_\nu(x) is a necessary condition. The condition implies that the left tail of F_\nu must be thicker than the left tail of F_\rho.


Higher-order

Higher orders of stochastic dominance have also been analyzed, as have generalizations of the dual relationship between stochastic dominance orderings and classes of preference functions. Arguably the most powerful dominance criterion relies on the accepted economic assumption of Risk aversion#Absolute risk aversion, decreasing absolute risk aversion. This involves several analytical challenges and a research effort is on its way to address those. Formally, the n-th-order stochastic dominance is defined as * For any probability distribution \rho on [0, \infty), define the functions inductively: F^1_\rho(t) = F_\rho(t), \quad F^2_\rho(t) = \int_0^t F^1_\rho(x)dx, \quad \cdots * For any two probability distributions \rho, \nu on [0, \infty), non-strict and strict n-th-order stochastic dominance is defined as\rho \succeq_n \nu \quad \text \quad F^n_\rho \geq F^n_\nu \text [0, \infty)\rho \succ_n \nu \quad \text \quad\rho \succeq_n \nu \text \rho \neq \nu These relations are transitive and increasingly more inclusive. That is, if \rho \succeq_n \nu, then \rho \succeq_ \nu for all k \geq n. Further, there exists \rho, \nu such that \rho \succeq_ \nu but not \rho \succeq_n \nu. Define the n-th moment by \mu_k(\rho) = \mathbb E_[X^k] = \int x^k dF_\rho(x), then


Constraints

Stochastic dominance relations may be used as constraints in problems of mathematical optimization, in particular stochastic programming. In a problem of maximizing a real functional f(X) over random variables X in a set X_0 we may additionally require that X stochastically dominates a fixed random ''benchmark'' B . In these problems, utility functions play the role of Lagrange multipliers associated with stochastic dominance constraints. Under appropriate conditions, the solution of the problem is also a (possibly local) solution of the problem to maximize f(X) + \mathbb E[u(X) - u(B)] over X in X_0 , where u(x) is a certain utility function. If the first order stochastic dominance constraint is employed, the utility function u(x) is monotonic function, nondecreasing; if the second order stochastic dominance constraint is used, u(x) is monotonic function, nondecreasing and concave function, concave. A system of linear equations can test whether a given solution if efficient for any such utility function. Third-order stochastic dominance constraints can be dealt with using convex quadratically constrained programming (QCP).


See also

*Modern portfolio theory *Marginal conditional stochastic dominance *Responsive set extension - equivalent to stochastic dominance in the context of preference relations. *Quantum catalyst *Ordinal Pareto efficiency *Lexicographic dominance


References

{{DEFAULTSORT:Stochastic Dominance Random variable ordering