Overview
Definition
Motivation
The classical definition of a sheaf begins with a topological space ''X''. A sheaf associates information to the open sets of ''X''. This information can be phrased abstractly by letting ''O''(''X'') be the category whose objects are the open subsets ''U'' of ''X'' and whose morphisms are the inclusion maps ''V'' → ''U'' of open sets ''U'' and ''V'' of ''X''. We will call such maps ''open immersions'', just as in the context of schemes. Then a presheaf on ''X'' is aSieves
In a Grothendieck topology, the notion of a collection of open subsets of ''U'' stable under inclusion is replaced by the notion of a sieve. If ''c'' is any given object in ''C'', a sieve on ''c'' is a subfunctor of the functor Hom(−, ''c''); (this is the Yoneda embedding applied to ''c''). In the case of ''O''(''X''), a sieve ''S'' on an open set ''U'' selects a collection of open subsets of ''U'' that is stable under inclusion. More precisely, consider that for any open subset ''V'' of ''U'', ''S''(''V'') will be a subset of Hom(''V'', ''U''), which has only one element, the open immersion ''V'' → ''U''. Then ''V'' will be considered "selected" by ''S'' if and only if ''S''(''V'') is nonempty. If ''W'' is a subset of ''V'', then there is a morphism ''S''(''V'') → ''S''(''W'') given by composition with the inclusion ''W'' → ''V''. If ''S''(''V'') is non-empty, it follows that ''S''(''W'') is also non-empty. If ''S'' is a sieve on ''X'', and ''f'': ''Y'' → ''X'' is a morphism, then left composition by ''f'' gives a sieve on ''Y'' called the pullback of ''S'' along ''f'', denoted by ''f''''S''. It is defined as the fibered product ''S'' ×Hom(−, ''X'') Hom(−, ''Y'') together with its natural embedding in Hom(−, ''Y''). More concretely, for each object ''Z'' of ''C'', ''f''''S''(''Z'') = , and ''f''''S'' inherits its action on morphisms by being a subfunctor of Hom(−, ''Y''). In the classical example, the pullback of a collection of subsets of ''U'' along an inclusion ''W'' → ''U'' is the collection .Grothendieck topology
A Grothendieck topology ''J'' on a category ''C'' is a collection, ''for each object c of C'', of distinguished sieves on ''c'', denoted by ''J''(''c'') and called covering sieves of ''c''. This selection will be subject to certain axioms, stated below. Continuing the previous example, a sieve ''S'' on an open set ''U'' in ''O''(''X'') will be a covering sieve if and only if ''U'' is the union of all the open sets ''V''; in other words, if and only if ''S'' gives us a collection of open sets that cover ''U'' in the classical sense.Axioms
The conditions we impose on a Grothendieck topology are: * (T 1) (Base change) If ''S'' is a covering sieve on ''X'', and ''f'': ''Y'' → ''X'' is a morphism, then the pullback ''f''''S'' is a covering sieve on ''Y''. * (T 2) (Local character) Let ''S'' be a covering sieve on ''X'', and let ''T'' be any sieve on ''X''. Suppose that for each object ''Y'' of ''C'' and each arrow ''f'': ''Y'' → ''X'' in ''S''(''Y''), the pullback sieve ''f''''T'' is a covering sieve on ''Y''. Then ''T'' is a covering sieve on ''X''. * (T 3) (Identity) Hom(−, ''X'') is a covering sieve on ''X'' for any object ''X'' in ''C''. The base change axiom corresponds to the idea that if covers ''U'', then should cover ''U'' ∩ ''V''. The local character axiom corresponds to the idea that if covers ''U'' and ''j Ji'' covers ''Ui'' for each ''i'', then the collection for all ''i'' and ''j'' should cover ''U''. Lastly, the identity axiom corresponds to the idea that any set is covered by itself via the identity map.Grothendieck pretopologies
In fact, it is possible to put these axioms in another form where their geometric character is more apparent, assuming that the underlying category ''C'' contains certain fibered products. In this case, instead of specifying sieves, we can specify that certain collections of maps with a common codomain should cover their codomain. These collections are called covering families. If the collection of all covering families satisfies certain axioms, then we say that they form a Grothendieck pretopology. These axioms are: * (PT 0) (Existence of fibered products) For all objects ''X'' of ''C'', and for all morphisms ''X''0 → ''X'' that appear in some covering family of ''X'', and for all morphisms ''Y'' → ''X'', the fibered product ''X''0 ×''X'' ''Y'' exists. * (PT 1) (Stability under base change) For all objects ''X'' of ''C'', all morphisms ''Y'' → ''X'', and all covering families , the family is a covering family. * (PT 2) (Local character) If is a covering family, and if for all α, is a covering family, then the family of composites is a covering family. * (PT 3) (Isomorphisms) If ''f'': ''Y'' → ''X'' is an isomorphism, then is a covering family. For any pretopology, the collection of all sieves that contain a covering family from the pretopology is always a Grothendieck topology. For categories with fibered products, there is a converse. Given a collection of arrows , we construct a sieve ''S'' by letting ''S''(''Y'') be the set of all morphisms ''Y'' → ''X'' that factor through some arrow ''X''''α'' → ''X''. This is called the sieve generated by . Now choose a topology. Say that is a covering family if and only if the sieve that it generates is a covering sieve for the given topology. It is easy to check that this defines a pretopology. (PT 3) is sometimes replaced by a weaker axiom: * (PT 3') (Identity) If 1''X'' : ''X'' → ''X'' is the identity arrow, then is a covering family. (PT 3) implies (PT 3'), but not conversely. However, suppose that we have a collection of covering families that satisfies (PT 0) through (PT 2) and (PT 3'), but not (PT 3). These families generate a pretopology. The topology generated by the original collection of covering families is then the same as the topology generated by the pretopology, because the sieve generated by an isomorphism ''Y'' → ''X'' is Hom(−, ''X''). Consequently, if we restrict our attention to topologies, (PT 3) and (PT 3') are equivalent.Sites and sheaves
Let ''C'' be a category and let ''J'' be a Grothendieck topology on ''C''. The pair (''C'', ''J'') is called a site. A presheaf on a category is a contravariant functor from ''C'' to the category of all sets. Note that for this definition ''C'' is not required to have a topology. A sheaf on a site, however, should allow gluing, just like sheaves in classical topology. Consequently, we define a sheaf on a site to be a presheaf ''F'' such that for all objects ''X'' and all covering sieves ''S'' on ''X'', the natural map Hom(Hom(−, ''X''), ''F'') → Hom(''S'', ''F''), induced by the inclusion of ''S'' into Hom(−, ''X''), is a bijection. Halfway in between a presheaf and a sheaf is the notion of a separated presheaf, where the natural map above is required to be only an injection, not a bijection, for all sieves ''S''. A morphism of presheaves or of sheaves is a natural transformation of functors. The category of all sheaves on ''C'' is the topos defined by the site (''C'', ''J''). Using the Yoneda lemma, it is possible to show that a presheaf on the category ''O''(''X'') is a sheaf on the topology defined above if and only if it is a sheaf in the classical sense. Sheaves on a pretopology have a particularly simple description: For each covering family , the diagram : must be an equalizer. For a separated presheaf, the first arrow need only be injective. Similarly, one can define presheaves and sheaves ofExamples of sites
The discrete and indiscrete topologies
Let C be any category. To define the discrete topology, we declare all sieves to be covering sieves. If C has all fibered products, this is equivalent to declaring all families to be covering families. To define the indiscrete topology, also known as the coarse or chaotic topology, we declare only the sieves of the form Hom(−, ''X'') to be covering sieves. The indiscrete topology is generated by the pretopology that has only isomorphisms for covering families. A sheaf on the indiscrete site is the same thing as a presheaf.The canonical topology
Let C be any category. The Yoneda embedding gives a functor Hom(−, ''X'') for each object ''X'' of C. The canonical topology is the biggest (finest) topology such that every representable presheaf, i.e. presheaf of the form Hom(−, ''X''), is a sheaf. A covering sieve or covering family for this site is said to be ''strictly universally epimorphic'' because it consists of the legs of a colimit cone (under the full diagram on the domains of its constituent morphisms) and these colimits are stable under pullbacks along morphisms in C. A topology that is less fine than the canonical topology, that is, for which every covering sieve is strictly universally epimorphic, is called subcanonical. Subcanonical sites are exactly the sites for which every presheaf of the form Hom(−, ''X'') is a sheaf. Most sites encountered in practice are subcanonical.Small site associated to a topological space
We repeat the example that we began with above. Let ''X'' be a topological space. We defined ''O''(''X'') to be the category whose objects are the open sets of ''X'' and whose morphisms are inclusions of open sets. Note that for an open set ''U'' and a sieve ''S'' on ''U'', the set ''S''(''V'') contains either zero or one element for every open set ''V''. The covering sieves on an object ''U'' of ''O''(''X'') are those sieves ''S'' satisfying the following condition: *If ''W'' is the union of all the sets ''V'' such that ''S''(''V'') is non-empty, then ''W'' = ''U''. This notion of cover matches the usual notion in point-set topology. This topology can also naturally be expressed as a pretopology. We say that a family of inclusions is a covering family if and only if the union ''V''''α'' equals ''U''. This site is called the small site associated to a topological space ''X''.Big site associated to a topological space
Let ''Spc'' be the category of all topological spaces. Given any family of functions , we say that it is a surjective family or that the morphisms ''u''''α'' are jointly surjective if ''u''''α''(''V''''α'') equals ''X''. We define a pretopology on ''Spc'' by taking the covering families to be surjective families all of whose members are open immersions. Let ''S'' be a sieve on ''Spc''. ''S'' is a covering sieve for this topology if and only if: *For all ''Y'' and every morphism ''f'' : ''Y'' → ''X'' in ''S''(''Y''), there exists a ''V'' and a ''g'' : ''V'' → ''X'' such that ''g'' is an open immersion, ''g'' is in ''S''(''V''), and ''f'' factors through ''g''. *If ''W'' is the union of all the sets ''f''(''Y''), where ''f'' : ''Y'' → ''X'' is in ''S''(''Y''), then ''W'' = ''X''. Fix a topological space ''X''. Consider the comma category ''Spc/X'' of topological spaces with a fixed continuous map to ''X''. The topology on ''Spc'' induces a topology on ''Spc/X''. The covering sieves and covering families are almost exactly the same; the only difference is that now all the maps involved commute with the fixed maps to ''X''. This is the big site associated to a topological space ''X'' . Notice that ''Spc'' is the big site associated to the one point space. This site was first considered byThe big and small sites of a manifold
Let ''M'' be aTopologies on the category of schemes
The category of schemes, denoted ''Sch'', has a tremendous number of useful topologies. A complete understanding of some questions may require examining a scheme using several different topologies. All of these topologies have associated small and big sites. The big site is formed by taking the entire category of schemes and their morphisms, together with the covering sieves specified by the topology. The small site over a given scheme is formed by only taking the objects and morphisms that are part of a cover of the given scheme. The most elementary of these is the Zariski topology. Let ''X'' be a scheme. ''X'' has an underlying topological space, and this topological space determines a Grothendieck topology. The Zariski topology on ''Sch'' is generated by the pretopology whose covering families are jointly surjective families of scheme-theoretic open immersions. The covering sieves ''S'' for ''Zar'' are characterized by the following two properties: *For all ''Y'' and every morphism ''f'' : ''Y'' → ''X'' in ''S''(''Y''), there exists a ''V'' and a ''g'' : ''V'' → ''X'' such that ''g'' is an open immersion, ''g'' is in ''S''(''V''), and ''f'' factors through ''g''. *If ''W'' is the union of all the sets ''f''(''Y''), where ''f'' : ''Y'' → ''X'' is in ''S''(''Y''), then ''W'' = ''X''. Despite their outward similarities, the topology on ''Zar'' is ''not'' the restriction of the topology on ''Spc''! This is because there are morphisms of schemes that are topologically open immersions but that are not scheme-theoretic open immersions. For example, let ''A'' be a non- reduced ring and let ''N'' be its ideal of nilpotents. The quotient map ''A'' → ''A/N'' induces a map Spec ''A/N'' → Spec ''A'', which is the identity on underlying topological spaces. To be a scheme-theoretic open immersion it must also induce an isomorphism on structure sheaves, which this map does not do. In fact, this map is a closed immersion. TheContinuous and cocontinuous functors
There are two natural types of functors between sites. They are given by functors that are compatible with the topology in a certain sense.Continuous functors
If (''C'', ''J'') and (''D'', ''K'') are sites and ''u'' : ''C'' → ''D'' is a functor, then ''u'' is continuous if for every sheaf ''F'' on ''D'' with respect to the topology ''K'', the presheaf ''Fu'' is a sheaf with respect to the topology ''J''. Continuous functors induce functors between the corresponding topoi by sending a sheaf ''F'' to ''Fu''. These functors are called pushforwards. If and denote the topoi associated to ''C'' and ''D'', then the pushforward functor is . ''u''''s'' admits a left adjoint ''u''''s'' called the pullback. ''u''''s'' need not preserve limits, even finite limits. In the same way, ''u'' sends a sieve on an object ''X'' of ''C'' to a sieve on the object ''uX'' of ''D''. A continuous functor sends covering sieves to covering sieves. If ''J'' is the topology defined by a pretopology, and if ''u'' commutes with fibered products, then ''u'' is continuous if and only if it sends covering sieves to covering sieves and if and only if it sends covering families to covering families. In general, it is ''not'' sufficient for ''u'' to send covering sieves to covering sieves (see SGA IV 3, 1.9.3).Cocontinuous functors
Again, let (''C'', ''J'') and (''D'', ''K'') be sites and ''v'' : ''C'' → ''D'' be a functor. If ''X'' is an object of ''C'' and ''R'' is a sieve on ''vX'', then ''R'' can be pulled back to a sieve ''S'' as follows: A morphism ''f'' : ''Z'' → ''X'' is in ''S'' if and only if ''v''(''f'') : ''vZ'' → ''vX'' is in ''R''. This defines a sieve. ''v'' is cocontinuous if and only if for every object ''X'' of ''C'' and every covering sieve ''R'' of ''vX'', the pullback ''S'' of ''R'' is a covering sieve on ''X''. Composition with ''v'' sends a presheaf ''F'' on ''D'' to a presheaf ''Fv'' on ''C'', but if ''v'' is cocontinuous, this need not send sheaves to sheaves. However, this functor on presheaf categories, usually denoted , admits a right adjoint . Then ''v'' is cocontinuous if and only if sends sheaves to sheaves, that is, if and only if it restricts to a functor . In this case, the composite of with the associated sheaf functor is a left adjoint of ''v''* denoted ''v''*. Furthermore, ''v''* preserves finite limits, so the adjoint functors ''v''* and ''v''* determine a geometric morphism of topoi .Morphisms of sites
A continuous functor ''u'' : ''C'' → ''D'' is a morphism of sites ''D'' → ''C'' (''not'' ''C'' → ''D'') if ''u''''s'' preserves finite limits. In this case, ''u''''s'' and ''u''''s'' determine a geometric morphism of topoi . The reasoning behind the convention that a continuous functor ''C'' → ''D'' is said to determine a morphism of sites in the opposite direction is that this agrees with the intuition coming from the case of topological spaces. A continuous map of topological spaces ''X'' → ''Y'' determines a continuous functor ''O''(''Y'') → ''O''(''X''). Since the original map on topological spaces is said to send ''X'' to ''Y'', the morphism of sites is said to as well. A particular case of this happens when a continuous functor admits a left adjoint. Suppose that ''u'' : ''C'' → ''D'' and ''v'' : ''D'' → ''C'' are functors with ''u'' right adjoint to ''v''. Then ''u'' is continuous if and only if ''v'' is cocontinuous, and when this happens, ''u''''s'' is naturally isomorphic to ''v''* and ''u''''s'' is naturally isomorphic to ''v''*. In particular, ''u'' is a morphism of sites.See also
* Fibered category * Lawvere–Tierney topologyNotes
References
* * * * * *External links