In
set theory
Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies Set (mathematics), sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory – as a branch of mathema ...
and related branches of
mathematics
Mathematics is a field of study that discovers and organizes methods, Mathematical theory, theories and theorems that are developed and Mathematical proof, proved for the needs of empirical sciences and mathematics itself. There are many ar ...
, the von Neumann universe, or von Neumann hierarchy of sets, denoted by ''V'', is the
class
Class, Classes, or The Class may refer to:
Common uses not otherwise categorized
* Class (biology), a taxonomic rank
* Class (knowledge representation), a collection of individuals or objects
* Class (philosophy), an analytical concept used d ...
of
hereditary well-founded sets. This collection, which is formalized by
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory
In set theory, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, named after mathematicians Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, is an axiomatic system that was proposed in the early twentieth century in order to formulate a theory of sets free of paradoxes suc ...
(ZFC), is often used to provide an interpretation or motivation of the axioms of ZFC. The concept is named after
John von Neumann
John von Neumann ( ; ; December 28, 1903 – February 8, 1957) was a Hungarian and American mathematician, physicist, computer scientist and engineer. Von Neumann had perhaps the widest coverage of any mathematician of his time, in ...
, although it was first published by
Ernst Zermelo in 1930.
The rank of a well-founded set is defined inductively as the smallest
ordinal number
In set theory, an ordinal number, or ordinal, is a generalization of ordinal numerals (first, second, th, etc.) aimed to extend enumeration to infinite sets.
A finite set can be enumerated by successively labeling each element with the leas ...
greater than the ranks of all members of the set. In particular, the rank of the
empty set
In mathematics, the empty set or void set is the unique Set (mathematics), set having no Element (mathematics), elements; its size or cardinality (count of elements in a set) is 0, zero. Some axiomatic set theories ensure that the empty set exi ...
is zero, and every ordinal has a rank equal to itself. The sets in ''V'' are divided into the
transfinite hierarchy ''V
α'', called the cumulative hierarchy, based on their rank.
Definition
The cumulative hierarchy is a collection of sets ''V''
α
indexed by the class of
ordinal number
In set theory, an ordinal number, or ordinal, is a generalization of ordinal numerals (first, second, th, etc.) aimed to extend enumeration to infinite sets.
A finite set can be enumerated by successively labeling each element with the leas ...
s; in particular, ''V''
α is the set of all sets having ranks less than α. Thus there is one set ''V''
α for each ordinal number α. ''V''
α may be defined by
transfinite recursion as follows:
* Let ''V''
0 be the
empty set
In mathematics, the empty set or void set is the unique Set (mathematics), set having no Element (mathematics), elements; its size or cardinality (count of elements in a set) is 0, zero. Some axiomatic set theories ensure that the empty set exi ...
:
* For any
ordinal number
In set theory, an ordinal number, or ordinal, is a generalization of ordinal numerals (first, second, th, etc.) aimed to extend enumeration to infinite sets.
A finite set can be enumerated by successively labeling each element with the leas ...
β, let ''V''
β+1 be the
power set
In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is po ...
of ''V''
β:
* For any
limit ordinal λ, let ''V''
λ be the
union of all the ''V''-stages so far:
A crucial fact about this definition is that there is a single formula φ(α,''x'') in the language of ZFC that states "the set ''x'' is in ''V''
α".
The sets ''V''
α are called stages or ranks.
The class ''V'' is defined to be the union of all the ''V''-stages:
Rank of a set
The rank of a set ''S'' is the smallest α such that
In other words,
is the set of sets with rank ≤α. The stage ''V''
α can also be characterized as the set of sets with rank strictly less than α, regardless of whether α is 0, a successor ordinal, or a limit ordinal:
This gives an equivalent definition of ''V''
α by transfinite recursion.
Substituting the above definition of ''V''
α back into the definition of the rank of a set gives a self-contained recursive definition:
In other words,
Finite and low cardinality stages of the hierarchy
The first five von Neumann stages ''V''
0 to ''V''
4 may be visualized as follows. (An empty box represents the empty set. A box containing only an empty box represents the set containing only the empty set, and so forth.)

This sequence exhibits
tetrational growth. The set ''V''
5 contains 2
16 = 65536 elements; the set ''V''
6 contains 2
65536 elements, which very substantially exceeds the
number of atoms in the known universe; and for any natural ''n'', the set ''V''
''n''+1 contains 2 ⇈ ''n'' elements using
Knuth's up-arrow notation. So the finite stages of the cumulative hierarchy cannot be written down explicitly after stage 5. The set ''V''
ω has the same cardinality as ω. The set ''V''
ω+1 has the same cardinality as the set of real numbers.
Applications and interpretations
Applications of ''V'' as models for set theories
If ω is the set of
natural number
In mathematics, the natural numbers are the numbers 0, 1, 2, 3, and so on, possibly excluding 0. Some start counting with 0, defining the natural numbers as the non-negative integers , while others start with 1, defining them as the positive in ...
s, then ''V''
ω is the set of
hereditarily finite sets, which is a
model
A model is an informative representation of an object, person, or system. The term originally denoted the plans of a building in late 16th-century English, and derived via French and Italian ultimately from Latin , .
Models can be divided in ...
of set theory without the
axiom of infinity.
''V''
ω+ω is the
universe
The universe is all of space and time and their contents. It comprises all of existence, any fundamental interaction, physical process and physical constant, and therefore all forms of matter and energy, and the structures they form, from s ...
of "ordinary mathematics", and is a model of
Zermelo set theory (but not a model of
ZF). A simple argument in favour of the adequacy of ''V''
ω+ω is the observation that ''V''
ω+1 is adequate for the integers, while ''V''
ω+2 is adequate for the real numbers, and most other normal mathematics can be built as relations of various kinds from these sets without needing the
axiom of replacement to go outside ''V''
ω+ω.
If κ is an
inaccessible cardinal, then ''V''
κ is a model of
Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory
In set theory, Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory, named after mathematicians Ernst Zermelo and Abraham Fraenkel, is an axiomatic system that was proposed in the early twentieth century in order to formulate a theory of sets free of paradoxes suc ...
(ZFC) itself, and ''V''
κ+1 is a model of
Morse–Kelley set theory. (Note that every ZFC model is also a ZF model, and every ZF model is also a Z model.)
Interpretation of ''V'' as the "set of all sets"
V is not "the
set of all (naive) sets" for two reasons. First, it is not a set; although each individual stage ''V''
α is a set, their union ''V'' is a
proper class
Proper may refer to:
Mathematics
* Proper map, in topology, a property of continuous function between topological spaces, if inverse images of compact subsets are compact
* Proper morphism, in algebraic geometry, an analogue of a proper map f ...
. Second, the sets in ''V'' are only the well-founded sets. The
axiom of foundation (or regularity) demands that every set be well founded and hence in ''V'', and thus in ZFC every set is in ''V''. But other axiom systems may omit the axiom of foundation or replace it by a strong negation (an example is
Aczel's anti-foundation axiom). These non-well-founded set theories are not commonly employed, but are still possible to study.
A third objection to the "set of all sets" interpretation is that not all sets are necessarily "pure sets", which are constructed from the empty set using power sets and unions. Zermelo proposed in 1908 the inclusion of
urelements, from which he constructed a transfinite recursive hierarchy in 1930.
Such urelements are used extensively in
model theory
In mathematical logic, model theory is the study of the relationship between theory (mathematical logic), formal theories (a collection of Sentence (mathematical logic), sentences in a formal language expressing statements about a Structure (mat ...
, particularly in Fraenkel-Mostowski models.
[.]
Hilbert's paradox
The von Neumann universe satisfies the following two properties:
*
for every ''set''
.
*
for every ''subset''
.
Indeed, if
, then
for some ordinal
. Any stage is a
transitive set
In set theory, a branch of mathematics, a set A is called transitive if either of the following equivalent conditions holds:
* whenever x \in A, and y \in x, then y \in A.
* whenever x \in A, and x is not an urelement, then x is a subset of A.
S ...
, hence every
is already
, and so every subset of
is a subset of
. Therefore,
and
. For unions of subsets, if
, then for every
, let
be the smallest ordinal for which
. Because by assumption
is a set, we can form the limit
. The stages are cumulative, and therefore again every
is
. Then every
is also
, and so
and
.
Hilbert's paradox implies that no set with the above properties exists . For suppose
was a set. Then
would be a subset of itself, and
would belong to
, and so would
. But more generally, if
, then
. Hence,
, which is impossible in models of ZFC such as
itself.
Interestingly,
is a subset of
if, and only if,
is a member of
. Therefore, we can consider what happens if the union condition is replaced with
. In this case, there are no known contradictions, and any
Grothendieck universe satisfies the new pair of properties. However, whether Grothendieck universes exist is a question beyond ZFC.
''V'' and the axiom of regularity
The formula ''V'' = ⋃
α''V''
α is often considered to be a theorem, not a definition.
Roitman states (without references) that the realization that the
axiom of regularity is equivalent to the equality of the universe of ZF sets to the cumulative hierarchy is due to von Neumann.
[. See page 79.]
The existential status of ''V''
Since the class ''V'' may be considered to be the arena for most of mathematics, it is important to establish that it "exists" in some sense. Since existence is a difficult concept, one typically replaces the existence question with the consistency question, that is, whether the concept is free of contradictions. A major obstacle is posed by
Gödel's incompleteness theorems
Gödel's incompleteness theorems are two theorems of mathematical logic that are concerned with the limits of in formal axiomatic theories. These results, published by Kurt Gödel in 1931, are important both in mathematical logic and in the phi ...
, which effectively imply the impossibility of proving the consistency of ZF set theory in ZF set theory itself, provided that it is in fact consistent.
The integrity of the von Neumann universe depends fundamentally on the integrity of the
ordinal number
In set theory, an ordinal number, or ordinal, is a generalization of ordinal numerals (first, second, th, etc.) aimed to extend enumeration to infinite sets.
A finite set can be enumerated by successively labeling each element with the leas ...
s, which act as the rank parameter in the construction, and the integrity of
transfinite induction, by which both the ordinal numbers and the von Neumann universe are constructed. The integrity of the ordinal number construction may be said to rest upon von Neumann's 1923 and 1928 papers. The integrity of the construction of ''V'' by transfinite induction may be said to have then been established in Zermelo's 1930 paper.
History
The cumulative type hierarchy, also known as the von Neumann universe, is claimed by Gregory H. Moore (1982) to be inaccurately attributed to
von Neumann.
[. See page 279 for the assertion of the false attribution to von Neumann. See pages 270 and 281 for the attribution to Zermelo.] The first publication of the von Neumann universe was by
Ernst Zermelo in 1930.
[. See particularly pages 36–40.]
Existence and uniqueness of the general transfinite recursive definition of sets was demonstrated in 1928 by von Neumann for both Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory and von Neumann's own set theory (which later developed into
NBG set theory). In neither of these papers did he apply his transfinite recursive method to construct the universe of all sets. The presentations of the von Neumann universe by Bernays
[. See pages 203–209.] and Mendelson
[. See page 202.] both give credit to von Neumann for the transfinite induction construction method, although not for its application to the construction of the universe of ordinary sets.
The notation ''V'' is not a tribute to the name of von Neumann. It was used for the universe of sets in 1889 by Peano, the letter ''V'' signifying "Verum", which he used both as a logical symbol and to denote the class of all individuals.
[. See pages VIII and XI.] Peano's notation ''V'' was adopted also by Whitehead and Russell for the class of all sets in 1910.
[. See page 229.] The ''V'' notation (for the class of all sets) was not used by von Neumann in his 1920s papers about ordinal numbers and transfinite induction. Paul Cohen
[. See page 88.] explicitly attributes his use of the letter ''V'' (for the class of all sets) to a 1940 paper by Gödel,
[.] although Gödel most likely obtained the notation from earlier sources such as Whitehead and Russell.
Philosophical perspectives
There are two approaches to understanding the relationship of the von Neumann universe V to ZFC (along with many variations of each approach, and shadings between them). Roughly, formalists will tend to view V as something that flows from the ZFC axioms (for example, ZFC proves that every set is in V). On the other hand, realists are more likely to see the von Neumann hierarchy as something directly accessible to the intuition, and the axioms of ZFC as propositions for whose truth in V we can give direct intuitive arguments in natural language. A possible middle position is that the mental picture of the von Neumann hierarchy provides the ZFC axioms with a motivation (so that they are not arbitrary), but does not necessarily describe objects with real existence.
See also
*
Universe (mathematics)
*
Constructible universe
*
Grothendieck universe
*
Inaccessible cardinal
*
S (set theory)
Notes
References
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
* . English translation:
*
*
*
*
{{Mathematical logic
John von Neumann
Set-theoretic universes