The propositional calculus is a branch of
logic
Logic is the study of correct reasoning. It includes both formal and informal logic. Formal logic is the study of deductively valid inferences or logical truths. It examines how conclusions follow from premises based on the structure o ...
.
It is also called propositional logic,
statement logic,
sentential calculus,
sentential logic,
or sometimes zeroth-order logic.
Sometimes, it is called ''first-order'' propositional logic
to contrast it with
System F, but it should not be confused with
first-order logic. It deals with
propositions (which can be
true or false)
and relations between propositions,
including the construction of arguments based on them.
Compound propositions are formed by connecting propositions by
logical connectives representing the
truth functions of
conjunction,
disjunction
In logic, disjunction (also known as logical disjunction, logical or, logical addition, or inclusive disjunction) is a logical connective typically notated as \lor and read aloud as "or". For instance, the English language sentence "it is ...
,
implication,
biconditional, and
negation
In logic, negation, also called the logical not or logical complement, is an operation (mathematics), operation that takes a Proposition (mathematics), proposition P to another proposition "not P", written \neg P, \mathord P, P^\prime or \over ...
.
Some sources include other connectives, as in the table below.
Unlike
first-order logic, propositional logic does not deal with non-logical objects, predicates about them, or
quantifiers. However, all the machinery of propositional logic is included in first-order logic and higher-order logics. In this sense, propositional logic is the foundation of first-order logic and higher-order logic.
Propositional logic is typically studied with a
formal language, in which propositions are represented by letters, which are called ''
propositional variables''. These are then used, together with symbols for connectives, to make ''
propositional formula''. Because of this, the propositional variables are called ''
atomic formulas'' of a formal propositional language.
While the atomic propositions are typically represented by letters of the
alphabet
An alphabet is a standard set of letter (alphabet), letters written to represent particular sounds in a spoken language. Specifically, letters largely correspond to phonemes as the smallest sound segments that can distinguish one word from a ...
,
there is a variety of notations to represent the logical connectives. The following table shows the main notational variants for each of the connectives in propositional logic.
The most thoroughly researched branch of propositional logic is classical truth-functional propositional logic,
in which formulas are interpreted as having precisely one of two possible
truth value
In logic and mathematics, a truth value, sometimes called a logical value, is a value indicating the relation of a proposition to truth, which in classical logic has only two possible values ('' true'' or '' false''). Truth values are used in ...
s, the truth value of ''true'' or the truth value of ''false''.
The
principle of bivalence and the
law of excluded middle are upheld. By comparison with
first-order logic, truth-functional propositional logic is considered to be ''zeroth-order logic''.
History
Although propositional logic had been hinted by earlier philosophers,
Chrysippus is often credited with development of a deductive system for propositional logic as his main achievement in the 3rd century BC
which was expanded by his successor
Stoics. The logic was focused on
proposition
A proposition is a statement that can be either true or false. It is a central concept in the philosophy of language, semantics, logic, and related fields. Propositions are the object s denoted by declarative sentences; for example, "The sky ...
s. This was different from the traditional
syllogistic logic, which focused on
terms. However, most of the original writings were lost
and, at some time between the 3rd and 6th century CE, Stoic logic faded into oblivion, to be resurrected only in the 20th century, in the wake of the (re)-discovery of propositional logic.
Symbolic logic
Logic is the study of correct reasoning. It includes both formal and informal logic. Formal logic is the study of deductively valid inferences or logical truths. It examines how conclusions follow from premises based on the structure o ...
, which would come to be important to refine propositional logic, was first developed by the 17th/18th-century mathematician
Gottfried Leibniz
Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz (or Leibnitz; – 14 November 1716) was a German polymath active as a mathematician, philosopher, scientist and diplomat who is credited, alongside Isaac Newton, Sir Isaac Newton, with the creation of calculus in ad ...
, whose
calculus ratiocinator was, however, unknown to the larger logical community. Consequently, many of the advances achieved by Leibniz were recreated by logicians like
George Boole
George Boole ( ; 2 November 1815 – 8 December 1864) was a largely self-taught English mathematician, philosopher and logician, most of whose short career was spent as the first professor of mathematics at Queen's College, Cork in Ireland. H ...
and
Augustus De Morgan, completely independent of Leibniz.
Gottlob Frege's predicate logic
First-order logic, also called predicate logic, predicate calculus, or quantificational logic, is a collection of formal systems used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. First-order logic uses quantified variables ove ...
builds upon propositional logic, and has been described as combining "the distinctive features of syllogistic logic and propositional logic."
Consequently, predicate logic ushered in a new era in logic's history; however, advances in propositional logic were still made after Frege, including
natural deduction,
truth trees and
truth tables. Natural deduction was invented by
Gerhard Gentzen and
Stanisław Jaśkowski. Truth trees were invented by
Evert Willem Beth.
The invention of truth tables, however, is of uncertain attribution.
Within works by Frege
and
Bertrand Russell
Bertrand Arthur William Russell, 3rd Earl Russell, (18 May 1872 – 2 February 1970) was a British philosopher, logician, mathematician, and public intellectual. He had influence on mathematics, logic, set theory, and various areas of analytic ...
,
are ideas influential to the invention of truth tables. The actual tabular structure (being formatted as a table), itself, is generally credited to either
Ludwig Wittgenstein
Ludwig Josef Johann Wittgenstein ( ; ; 26 April 1889 – 29 April 1951) was an Austrian philosopher who worked primarily in logic, the philosophy of mathematics, the philosophy of mind, and the philosophy of language.
From 1929 to 1947, Witt ...
or
Emil Post
Emil Leon Post (; February 11, 1897 – April 21, 1954) was an American mathematician and logician. He is best known for his work in the field that eventually became known as computability theory.
Life
Post was born in Augustów, Suwałki Govern ...
(or both, independently).
Besides Frege and Russell, others credited with having ideas preceding truth tables include Philo, Boole,
Charles Sanders Peirce
Charles Sanders Peirce ( ; September 10, 1839 – April 19, 1914) was an American scientist, mathematician, logician, and philosopher who is sometimes known as "the father of pragmatism". According to philosopher Paul Weiss (philosopher), Paul ...
,
and
Ernst Schröder. Others credited with the tabular structure include
Jan Łukasiewicz
Jan Łukasiewicz (; 21 December 1878 – 13 February 1956) was a Polish logician and philosopher who is best known for Polish notation and Łukasiewicz logic. His work centred on philosophical logic, mathematical logic and history of logi ...
,
Alfred North Whitehead,
William Stanley Jevons,
John Venn
John Venn, Fellow of the Royal Society, FRS, Fellow of the Society of Antiquaries of London, FSA (4 August 1834 – 4 April 1923) was an English mathematician, logician and philosopher noted for introducing Venn diagrams, which are used in l ...
, and
Clarence Irving Lewis.
Ultimately, some have concluded, like John Shosky, that "It is far from clear that any one person should be given the title of 'inventor' of truth-tables".
Sentences
Propositional logic, as currently studied in universities, is a specification of a standard of
logical consequence
Logical consequence (also entailment or logical implication) is a fundamental concept in logic which describes the relationship between statement (logic), statements that hold true when one statement logically ''follows from'' one or more stat ...
in which only the meanings of
propositional connectives are considered in evaluating the conditions for the truth of a sentence, or whether a sentence logically follows from some other sentence or group of sentences.
Declarative sentences
Propositional logic deals with statements, which are defined as declarative sentences having truth value.
Examples of statements might include:
* ''
Wikipedia
Wikipedia is a free content, free Online content, online encyclopedia that is written and maintained by a community of volunteers, known as Wikipedians, through open collaboration and the wiki software MediaWiki. Founded by Jimmy Wales and La ...
is a free online encyclopedia that anyone can edit.''
* ''
London
London is the Capital city, capital and List of urban areas in the United Kingdom, largest city of both England and the United Kingdom, with a population of in . London metropolitan area, Its wider metropolitan area is the largest in Wester ...
is the capital of
England
England is a Countries of the United Kingdom, country that is part of the United Kingdom. It is located on the island of Great Britain, of which it covers about 62%, and List of islands of England, more than 100 smaller adjacent islands. It ...
.''
* ''All
Wikipedia editors speak at least three
language
Language is a structured system of communication that consists of grammar and vocabulary. It is the primary means by which humans convey meaning, both in spoken and signed language, signed forms, and may also be conveyed through writing syste ...
s.''
Declarative sentences are contrasted with
question
A question is an utterance which serves as a request for information. Questions are sometimes distinguished from interrogatives, which are the grammar, grammatical forms, typically used to express them. Rhetorical questions, for instance, are i ...
s, such as "What is Wikipedia?", and
imperative statements, such as "Please add
citation
A citation is a reference to a source. More precisely, a citation is an abbreviated alphanumeric expression embedded in the body of an intellectual work that denotes an entry in the bibliographic references section of the work for the purpose o ...
s to support the claims in this article.".
Such non-declarative sentences have no
truth value
In logic and mathematics, a truth value, sometimes called a logical value, is a value indicating the relation of a proposition to truth, which in classical logic has only two possible values ('' true'' or '' false''). Truth values are used in ...
,
and are only dealt with in
nonclassical logics, called
erotetic and
imperative logics.
Compounding sentences with connectives
In propositional logic, a statement can contain one or more other statements as parts.
''Compound sentences'' are formed from simpler sentences and express relationships among the constituent sentences.
This is done by combining them with
logical connectives:
the main types of compound sentences are
negation
In logic, negation, also called the logical not or logical complement, is an operation (mathematics), operation that takes a Proposition (mathematics), proposition P to another proposition "not P", written \neg P, \mathord P, P^\prime or \over ...
s,
conjunctions,
disjunctions,
implications, and
biconditionals,
which are formed by using the corresponding connectives to connect propositions.
In
English, these connectives are expressed by the words "and" (
conjunction), "or" (
disjunction
In logic, disjunction (also known as logical disjunction, logical or, logical addition, or inclusive disjunction) is a logical connective typically notated as \lor and read aloud as "or". For instance, the English language sentence "it is ...
), "not" (
negation
In logic, negation, also called the logical not or logical complement, is an operation (mathematics), operation that takes a Proposition (mathematics), proposition P to another proposition "not P", written \neg P, \mathord P, P^\prime or \over ...
), "if" (
material conditional
The material conditional (also known as material implication) is a binary operation commonly used in logic. When the conditional symbol \to is interpreted as material implication, a formula P \to Q is true unless P is true and Q is false.
M ...
), and "if and only if" (
biconditional).
Examples of such compound sentences might include:
* ''Wikipedia is a free online encyclopedia that anyone can edit, and
millions already have.'' (conjunction)
* ''It is not true that all Wikipedia editors speak at least three languages.'' (negation)
* ''Either London is the capital of England, or London is the capital of the
United Kingdom
The United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland, commonly known as the United Kingdom (UK) or Britain, is a country in Northwestern Europe, off the coast of European mainland, the continental mainland. It comprises England, Scotlan ...
, or both.'' (disjunction)
If sentences lack any logical connectives, they are called ''simple sentences'',
or ''atomic sentences'';
if they contain one or more logical connectives, they are called ''compound sentences'',
or ''molecular sentences''.
''Sentential connectives'' are a broader category that includes logical connectives.
Sentential connectives are any linguistic particles that bind sentences to create a new compound sentence,
or that inflect a single sentence to create a new sentence.
A ''logical connective'', or ''propositional connective'', is a kind of sentential connective with the characteristic feature that, when the original sentences it operates on are (or express)
proposition
A proposition is a statement that can be either true or false. It is a central concept in the philosophy of language, semantics, logic, and related fields. Propositions are the object s denoted by declarative sentences; for example, "The sky ...
s, the new sentence that results from its application also is (or expresses) a
proposition
A proposition is a statement that can be either true or false. It is a central concept in the philosophy of language, semantics, logic, and related fields. Propositions are the object s denoted by declarative sentences; for example, "The sky ...
.
Philosophers disagree about what exactly a proposition is,
as well as about which sentential connectives in natural languages should be counted as logical connectives.
Sentential connectives are also called ''sentence-functors'',
and logical connectives are also called ''truth-functors''.
Arguments
An
argument
An argument is a series of sentences, statements, or propositions some of which are called premises and one is the conclusion. The purpose of an argument is to give reasons for one's conclusion via justification, explanation, and/or persu ...
is defined as a
pair of things, namely a set of sentences, called the premises, and a sentence, called the conclusion.
The conclusion is claimed to ''follow from'' the premises,
and the premises are claimed to ''support'' the conclusion.
Example argument
The following is an example of an argument within the scope of propositional logic:
:Premise 1: ''If'' it's raining, ''then'' it's cloudy.
:Premise 2: It's raining.
:Conclusion: It's cloudy.
The
logical form of this argument is known as
modus ponens,
which is a
classically valid form.
So, in classical logic, the argument is ''valid'', although it may or may not be ''
sound
In physics, sound is a vibration that propagates as an acoustic wave through a transmission medium such as a gas, liquid or solid.
In human physiology and psychology, sound is the ''reception'' of such waves and their ''perception'' by the br ...
'', depending on the
meteorological facts in a given context. This example argument will be reused when explaining .
Validity and soundness
An argument is valid if, and only if, it is ''necessary'' that, if all its premises are true, its conclusion is true.
Alternatively, an argument is valid if, and only if, it is ''impossible'' for all the premises to be true while the conclusion is false.
Validity is contrasted with ''soundness''.
An argument is sound if, and only if, it is valid and all its premises are true.
Otherwise, it is ''unsound''.
Logic, in general, aims to precisely specify valid arguments.
This is done by defining a valid argument as one in which its conclusion is a
logical consequence
Logical consequence (also entailment or logical implication) is a fundamental concept in logic which describes the relationship between statement (logic), statements that hold true when one statement logically ''follows from'' one or more stat ...
of its premises,
which, when this is understood as ''semantic consequence'', means that there is no ''case'' in which the premises are true but the conclusion is not true
– see below.
Formalization
Propositional logic is typically studied through a
formal system in which
formulas of a
formal language are
interpreted to represent
propositions. This formal language is the basis for
proof systems, which allow a conclusion to be derived from premises if, and only if, it is a
logical consequence
Logical consequence (also entailment or logical implication) is a fundamental concept in logic which describes the relationship between statement (logic), statements that hold true when one statement logically ''follows from'' one or more stat ...
of them. This section will show how this works by formalizing the . The formal language for a propositional calculus will be fully specified in , and an overview of proof systems will be given in .
Propositional variables
Since propositional logic is not concerned with the structure of propositions beyond the point where they cannot be decomposed any more by logical connectives,
it is typically studied by replacing such ''atomic'' (indivisible) statements with letters of the alphabet, which are interpreted as variables representing statements (
''propositional variables'').
With propositional variables, the would then be symbolized as follows:
:Premise 1:
:Premise 2:
:Conclusion:
When is interpreted as "It's raining" and as "it's cloudy" these symbolic expressions correspond exactly with the original expression in natural language. Not only that, but they will also correspond with any other inference with the same
logical form.
When a formal system is used to represent formal logic, only statement letters (usually capital roman letters such as
,
and
) are represented directly. The natural language propositions that arise when they're interpreted are outside the scope of the system, and the relation between the formal system and its interpretation is likewise outside the formal system itself.
Gentzen notation
If we assume that the validity of
modus ponens has been accepted as an
axiom
An axiom, postulate, or assumption is a statement that is taken to be true, to serve as a premise or starting point for further reasoning and arguments. The word comes from the Ancient Greek word (), meaning 'that which is thought worthy or ...
, then the same can also be depicted like this:
:
This method of displaying it is
Gentzen's notation for
natural deduction and
sequent calculus.
The premises are shown above a line, called the inference line,
separated by a comma, which indicates ''combination'' of premises.
The conclusion is written below the inference line.
The inference line represents ''syntactic consequence'',
sometimes called ''deductive consequence'',
> which is also symbolized with ⊢.
So the above can also be written in one line as
.
Syntactic consequence is contrasted with ''semantic consequence'',
which is symbolized with ⊧.
In this case, the conclusion follows ''syntactically'' because the
natural deduction inference rule of
modus ponens has been assumed. For more on inference rules, see the sections on proof systems below.
Language
The
language
Language is a structured system of communication that consists of grammar and vocabulary. It is the primary means by which humans convey meaning, both in spoken and signed language, signed forms, and may also be conveyed through writing syste ...
(commonly called
)
of a propositional calculus is defined in terms of:
# a set of primitive symbols, called ''
atomic formulas'', ''atomic sentences'',
''atoms,''
''placeholders'', ''prime formulas'',
''proposition letters'', ''sentence letters'',
or ''variables'', and
# a set of operator symbols, called ''connectives'',
''
logical connectives'',
''logical operators'',
''truth-functional connectives,''
''truth-functors'',
or ''propositional connectives''.
A ''
well-formed formula
In mathematical logic, propositional logic and predicate logic, a well-formed formula, abbreviated WFF or wff, often simply formula, is a finite sequence of symbols from a given alphabet that is part of a formal language.
The abbreviation wf ...
'' is any atomic formula, or any formula that can be built up from atomic formulas by means of operator symbols according to the rules of the grammar. The language
, then, is defined either as being ''identical to'' its set of well-formed formulas,
or as ''containing'' that set (together with, for instance, its set of connectives and variables).
Usually the syntax of
is defined recursively by just a few definitions, as seen next; some authors explicitly include ''parentheses'' as punctuation marks when defining their language's syntax,
while others use them without comment.
Syntax
Given a set of atomic propositional variables
,
,
, ..., and a set of propositional connectives
,
,
, ...,
,
,
, ...,
,
,
, ..., a formula of propositional logic is
defined recursively by these definitions:
:Definition 1: Atomic propositional variables are formulas.
:Definition 2: If
is a propositional connective, and
A, B, C, …
is a sequence of m, possibly but not necessarily atomic, possibly but not necessarily distinct, formulas, then the result of applying
to
A, B, C, …
is a formula.
:Definition 3: Nothing else is a formula.
Writing the result of applying
to
A, B, C, …
in functional notation, as
(A, B, C, …), we have the following as examples of well-formed formulas:
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
What was given as ''Definition 2'' above, which is responsible for the composition of formulas, is referred to by
Colin Howson as the ''principle of composition''.
It is this
recursion
Recursion occurs when the definition of a concept or process depends on a simpler or previous version of itself. Recursion is used in a variety of disciplines ranging from linguistics to logic. The most common application of recursion is in m ...
in the definition of a language's syntax which justifies the use of the word "atomic" to refer to propositional variables, since all formulas in the language
are built up from the atoms as ultimate building blocks.
Composite formulas (all formulas besides atoms) are called ''molecules'',
or ''molecular sentences''.
(This is an imperfect analogy with
chemistry
Chemistry is the scientific study of the properties and behavior of matter. It is a physical science within the natural sciences that studies the chemical elements that make up matter and chemical compound, compounds made of atoms, molecules a ...
, since a chemical molecule may sometimes have only one atom, as in
monatomic gases.)
The definition that "nothing else is a formula", given above as ''Definition 3'', excludes any formula from the language which is not specifically required by the other definitions in the syntax.
In particular, it excludes ''infinitely long'' formulas from being
well-formed.
It is sometimes called the ''Closure Clause''.
CF grammar in BNF
An alternative to the syntax definitions given above is to write a
context-free (CF) grammar for the language
in
Backus-Naur form (BNF).
This is more common in
computer science
Computer science is the study of computation, information, and automation. Computer science spans Theoretical computer science, theoretical disciplines (such as algorithms, theory of computation, and information theory) to Applied science, ...
than in
philosophy
Philosophy ('love of wisdom' in Ancient Greek) is a systematic study of general and fundamental questions concerning topics like existence, reason, knowledge, Value (ethics and social sciences), value, mind, and language. It is a rational an ...
.
It can be done in many ways,
of which a particularly brief one, for the common set of five connectives, is this single clause:
:
This clause, due to its
self-referential
Self-reference is a concept that involves referring to oneself or one's own attributes, characteristics, or actions. It can occur in language, logic, mathematics, philosophy, and other fields.
In natural language, natural or formal languages, ...
nature (since
is in some branches of the definition of
), also acts as a
recursive definition, and therefore specifies the entire language. To expand it to add
modal operators, one need only add …
to the end of the clause.
Constants and schemata
Mathematicians sometimes distinguish between propositional constants,
propositional variables, and schemata. ''Propositional constants'' represent some particular proposition,
while ''propositional variables'' range over the set of all atomic propositions.
Schemata, or ''schematic letters'', however, range over all formulas.
(Schematic letters are also called ''metavariables''.)
It is common to represent propositional constants by , , and , propositional variables by , , and , and schematic letters are often Greek letters, most often , , and .
However, some authors recognize only two "propositional constants" in their formal system: the special symbol
, called "truth", which always evaluates to ''True'', and the special symbol
, called "falsity", which always evaluates to ''False''.
Other authors also include these symbols, with the same meaning, but consider them to be "zero-place truth-functors",
or equivalently, "
nullary
In logic
Logic is the study of correct reasoning. It includes both formal and informal logic. Formal logic is the study of deductively valid inferences or logical truths. It examines how conclusions follow from premises based on the ...
connectives".
Semantics
To serve as a model of the logic of a given
natural language, a formal language must be semantically interpreted.
In
classical logic
Classical logic (or standard logic) or Frege–Russell logic is the intensively studied and most widely used class of deductive logic. Classical logic has had much influence on analytic philosophy.
Characteristics
Each logical system in this c ...
, all propositions evaluate to exactly one of two
truth-values: ''True'' or ''False''.
For example, "
Wikipedia
Wikipedia is a free content, free Online content, online encyclopedia that is written and maintained by a community of volunteers, known as Wikipedians, through open collaboration and the wiki software MediaWiki. Founded by Jimmy Wales and La ...
is a
free online encyclopedia
An online encyclopedia, also called an Internet encyclopedia, is a digital encyclopedia accessible through the Internet. Some examples include pre-World Wide Web services that offered the '' Academic American Encyclopedia'' beginning in 1980, Enc ...
that anyone can edit"
evaluates to ''True'',
while "Wikipedia is a
paper
Paper is a thin sheet material produced by mechanically or chemically processing cellulose fibres derived from wood, Textile, rags, poaceae, grasses, Feces#Other uses, herbivore dung, or other vegetable sources in water. Once the water is dra ...
encyclopedia
An encyclopedia is a reference work or compendium providing summaries of knowledge, either general or special, in a particular field or discipline. Encyclopedias are divided into article (publishing), articles or entries that are arranged Alp ...
"
evaluates to ''False''.
In other respects, the following formal semantics can apply to the language of any propositional logic, but the assumptions that there are only two semantic values (
''bivalence''), that only one of the two is assigned to each formula in the language (
''noncontradiction''), and that every formula gets assigned a value (
''excluded middle''), are distinctive features of classical logic.
To learn about
nonclassical logics with more than two truth-values, and their unique semantics, one may consult the articles on "
Many-valued logic
Many-valued logic (also multi- or multiple-valued logic) is a propositional calculus in which there are more than two truth values. Traditionally, in Aristotle's Term logic, logical calculus, there were only two possible values (i.e., "true" and ...
", "
Three-valued logic", "
Finite-valued logic", and "
Infinite-valued logic".
Interpretation (case) and argument
For a given language
, an interpretation,
valuation,
Boolean valuation,
or case,
is an
assignment of ''semantic values'' to each formula of
.
For a formal language of classical logic, a case is defined as an ''assignment'', to each formula of
, of one or the other, but not both, of the
truth value
In logic and mathematics, a truth value, sometimes called a logical value, is a value indicating the relation of a proposition to truth, which in classical logic has only two possible values ('' true'' or '' false''). Truth values are used in ...
s, namely
truth
Truth or verity is the Property (philosophy), property of being in accord with fact or reality.Merriam-Webster's Online Dictionarytruth, 2005 In everyday language, it is typically ascribed to things that aim to represent reality or otherwise cor ...
(T, or 1) and
falsity (F, or 0).
An interpretation that follows the rules of classical logic is sometimes called a Boolean valuation.
An interpretation of a formal language for classical logic is often expressed in terms of
truth tables.
Since each formula is only assigned a single truth-value, an interpretation may be viewed as a
function, whose
domain is
, and whose
range is its set of semantic values
,
or
.
For
distinct propositional symbols there are
distinct possible interpretations. For any particular symbol
, for example, there are
possible interpretations: either
is assigned T, or
is assigned F. And for the pair
,
there are
possible interpretations: either both are assigned T, or both are assigned F, or
is assigned T and
is assigned F, or
is assigned F and
is assigned T.
Since
has
, that is,
denumerably many propositional symbols, there are
, and therefore
uncountably many distinct possible interpretations of
as a whole.
Where
is an interpretation and
and
represent formulas, the definition of an ''argument'', given in , may then be stated as a pair
, where
is the set of premises and
is the conclusion. The definition of an argument's ''validity'', i.e. its property that
, can then be stated as its ''absence of a counterexample'', where a counterexample is defined as a case
in which the argument's premises
are all true but the conclusion
is not true.
As will be seen in , this is the same as to say that the conclusion is a ''semantic consequence'' of the premises.
Propositional connective semantics
An interpretation assigns semantic values to
atomic formulas directly.
Molecular formulas are assigned a ''function'' of the value of their constituent atoms, according to the connective used;
the connectives are defined in such a way that the
truth-value of a sentence formed from atoms with connectives depends on the truth-values of the atoms that they're applied to, and ''only'' on those.
This assumption is referred to by
Colin Howson as the assumption of the ''
truth-functionality of the
connectives''.
Semantics via. truth tables
Since logical connectives are defined semantically only in terms of the
truth value
In logic and mathematics, a truth value, sometimes called a logical value, is a value indicating the relation of a proposition to truth, which in classical logic has only two possible values ('' true'' or '' false''). Truth values are used in ...
s that they take when the
propositional variables that they're applied to take either of the
two possible truth values,
the semantic definition of the connectives is usually represented as a
truth table
A truth table is a mathematical table used in logic—specifically in connection with Boolean algebra, Boolean functions, and propositional calculus—which sets out the functional values of logical expressions on each of their functional arg ...
for each of the connectives,
as seen below:
This table covers each of the main five
logical connectives:
conjunction (here notated
),
disjunction
In logic, disjunction (also known as logical disjunction, logical or, logical addition, or inclusive disjunction) is a logical connective typically notated as \lor and read aloud as "or". For instance, the English language sentence "it is ...
(),
implication (),
biconditional () and
negation
In logic, negation, also called the logical not or logical complement, is an operation (mathematics), operation that takes a Proposition (mathematics), proposition P to another proposition "not P", written \neg P, \mathord P, P^\prime or \over ...
, (¬''p'', or ¬''q'', as the case may be). It is sufficient for determining the semantics of each of these operators.
For more truth tables for more different kinds of connectives, see the article "
Truth table
A truth table is a mathematical table used in logic—specifically in connection with Boolean algebra, Boolean functions, and propositional calculus—which sets out the functional values of logical expressions on each of their functional arg ...
".
Semantics via assignment expressions
Some authors (viz., all the authors cited in this subsection) write out the connective semantics using a list of statements instead of a table. In this format, where
is the interpretation of
, the five connectives are defined as:
*
if, and only if,
*
if, and only if,
and
*
if, and only if,
or
*
if, and only if, it is true that, if
, then
*
if, and only if, it is true that
if, and only if,
Instead of
, the interpretation of
may be written out as
,
or, for definitions such as the above,
may be written simply as the English sentence "
is given the value
".
Yet other authors
may prefer to speak of a
Tarskian model for the language, so that instead they'll use the notation
, which is equivalent to saying
, where
is the interpretation function for
.
Connective definition methods
Some of these connectives may be defined in terms of others: for instance, implication,
, may be defined in terms of disjunction and negation, as
;
and disjunction may be defined in terms of negation and conjunction, as
.
In fact, a ''
truth-functionally complete'' system, in the sense that all and only the classical propositional tautologies are theorems, may be derived using only disjunction and negation (as
Russell,
Whitehead, and
Hilbert
David Hilbert (; ; 23 January 1862 – 14 February 1943) was a German mathematician and philosophy of mathematics, philosopher of mathematics and one of the most influential mathematicians of his time.
Hilbert discovered and developed a broad ...
did), or using only implication and negation (as
Frege did), or using only conjunction and negation, or even using only a single connective for "not and" (the
Sheffer stroke),
as
Jean Nicod did.
A ''joint denial'' connective (
logical NOR) will also suffice, by itself, to define all other connectives. Besides NOR and NAND, no other connectives have this property.
Some authors, namely
Howson and Cunningham,
distinguish equivalence from the biconditional. (As to equivalence, Howson calls it "truth-functional equivalence", while Cunningham calls it "logical equivalence".) Equivalence is symbolized with ⇔ and is a metalanguage symbol, while a biconditional is symbolized with ↔ and is a logical connective in the object language
. Regardless, an equivalence or biconditional is true if, and only if, the formulas connected by it are assigned the same semantic value under every interpretation. Other authors often do not make this distinction, and may use the word "equivalence",
and/or the symbol ⇔,
to denote their object language's biconditional connective.
Semantic truth, validity, consequence
Given
and
as
formulas (or sentences) of a language
, and
as an interpretation (or case) of
, then the following definitions apply:
* Truth-in-a-case:
A sentence
of
is ''true under an interpretation''
if
assigns the truth value T to
.
If
is
true under
, then
is called a ''model'' of
.
* Falsity-in-a-case:
is ''false under an interpretation''
if, and only if,
is true under
.
This is the "truth of negation" definition of falsity-in-a-case.
Falsity-in-a-case may also be defined by the "complement" definition:
is ''false under an interpretation''
if, and only if,
is not true under
.
In
classical logic
Classical logic (or standard logic) or Frege–Russell logic is the intensively studied and most widely used class of deductive logic. Classical logic has had much influence on analytic philosophy.
Characteristics
Each logical system in this c ...
, these definitions are equivalent, but in
nonclassical logics, they are not.
* Semantic consequence: A sentence
of
is a ''
semantic consequence'' (
) of a sentence
if there is no interpretation under which
is true and
is not true.
* Valid formula (tautology): A sentence
of
is ''logically valid'' (
), or a ''tautology'',
ref name="ms32
if it is true under every interpretation,
or ''true in every case.''
* Consistent sentence: A sentence of
is ''
consistent'' if it is true under at least one interpretation. It is ''inconsistent'' if it is not consistent.
An inconsistent formula is also called ''self-contradictory'',
and said to be a ''self-contradiction'',
or simply a ''contradiction'',
although this latter name is sometimes reserved specifically for statements of the form
.
For interpretations (cases)
of
, these definitions are sometimes given:
* Complete case: A case
is ''complete'' if, and only if, either
is true-in-
or
is true-in-
, for any
in
.
* Consistent case: A case
is ''consistent'' if, and only if, there is no
in
such that both
and
are true-in-
.
For
classical logic
Classical logic (or standard logic) or Frege–Russell logic is the intensively studied and most widely used class of deductive logic. Classical logic has had much influence on analytic philosophy.
Characteristics
Each logical system in this c ...
, which assumes that all cases are complete and consistent,
the following theorems apply:
* For any given interpretation, a given formula is either true or false under it.
* No formula is both true and false under the same interpretation.
*
is true under
if, and only if,
is false under
;
is true under
if, and only if,
is not true under
.
* If
and
are both true under
, then
is true under
.
* If
and
, then
.
*
is true under
if, and only if, either
is not true under
, or
is true under
.
*
if, and only if,
is
logically valid, that is,
if, and only if,
.
Proof systems
Proof systems in propositional logic can be broadly classified into ''semantic proof systems'' and ''syntactic proof systems'',
according to the kind of
logical consequence
Logical consequence (also entailment or logical implication) is a fundamental concept in logic which describes the relationship between statement (logic), statements that hold true when one statement logically ''follows from'' one or more stat ...
that they rely on: semantic proof systems rely on semantic consequence (
),
whereas syntactic proof systems rely on syntactic consequence (
).
Semantic consequence deals with the truth values of propositions in all possible interpretations, whereas syntactic consequence concerns the derivation of conclusions from premises based on rules and axioms within a formal system.
This section gives a very brief overview of the kinds of proof systems, with
anchors to the relevant sections of this article on each one, as well as to the separate Wikipedia articles on each one.
Semantic proof systems

Semantic proof systems rely on the concept of semantic consequence, symbolized as
, which indicates that if
is true, then
must also be true in every possible interpretation.
Truth tables
A
truth table
A truth table is a mathematical table used in logic—specifically in connection with Boolean algebra, Boolean functions, and propositional calculus—which sets out the functional values of logical expressions on each of their functional arg ...
is a semantic proof method used to determine the truth value of a propositional logic expression in every possible scenario.
By exhaustively listing the truth values of its constituent atoms, a truth table can show whether a proposition is true, false, tautological, or contradictory.
See .
Semantic tableaux
A
semantic tableau is another semantic proof technique that systematically explores the truth of a proposition.
It constructs a tree where each branch represents a possible interpretation of the propositions involved.
If every branch leads to a contradiction, the original proposition is considered to be a contradiction, and its negation is considered a
tautology.
See .
Syntactic proof systems

Syntactic proof systems, in contrast, focus on the formal manipulation of symbols according to specific rules. The notion of syntactic consequence,
, signifies that
can be derived from
using the rules of the formal system.
Axiomatic systems
An
axiomatic system is a set of axioms or assumptions from which other statements (theorems) are logically derived.
In propositional logic, axiomatic systems define a base set of propositions considered to be self-evidently true, and theorems are proved by applying deduction rules to these axioms.
See .
Natural deduction
Natural deduction is a syntactic method of proof that emphasizes the derivation of conclusions from premises through the use of intuitive rules reflecting ordinary reasoning.
Each rule reflects a particular logical connective and shows how it can be introduced or eliminated.
See .
Sequent calculus
The
sequent calculus is a formal system that represents logical deductions as sequences or "sequents" of formulas.
Developed by
Gerhard Gentzen, this approach focuses on the structural properties of logical deductions and provides a powerful framework for proving statements within propositional logic.
Semantic proof via truth tables
Taking advantage of the semantic concept of validity (truth in every interpretation), it is possible to prove a formula's validity by using a
truth table
A truth table is a mathematical table used in logic—specifically in connection with Boolean algebra, Boolean functions, and propositional calculus—which sets out the functional values of logical expressions on each of their functional arg ...
, which gives every possible interpretation (assignment of truth values to variables) of a formula.
If, and only if, all the lines of a truth table come out true, the formula is semantically valid (true in every interpretation).
Further, if (and only if)
is valid, then
is inconsistent.
For instance, this table shows that "" is not valid:
The computation of the last column of the third line may be displayed as follows:
Further, using the theorem that
if, and only if,
is valid,
we can use a truth table to prove that a formula is a semantic consequence of a set of formulas:
if, and only if, we can produce a truth table that comes out all true for the formula
(that is, if
).
Semantic proof via tableaux
Since truth tables have 2
n lines for n variables, they can be tiresomely long for large values of n.
Analytic tableaux are a more efficient, but nevertheless mechanical,
semantic proof method; they take advantage of the fact that "we learn nothing about the validity of the inference from examining the truth-value distributions which make either the premises false or the conclusion true: the only relevant distributions when considering deductive validity are clearly just those which make the premises true or the conclusion false."
Analytic tableaux for propositional logic are fully specified by the rules that are stated in schematic form below.
These rules use "signed formulas", where a signed formula is an expression
or
, where
is a (unsigned) formula of the language
.
(Informally,
is read "
is true", and
is read "
is false".)
Their formal semantic definition is that "under any interpretation, a signed formula
is called true if
is true, and false if
is false, whereas a signed formula
is called false if
is true, and true if
is false."
In this notation, rule 2 means that
yields both
, whereas
''branches'' into
. The notation is to be understood analogously for rules 3 and 4.
Often, in tableaux for
classical logic
Classical logic (or standard logic) or Frege–Russell logic is the intensively studied and most widely used class of deductive logic. Classical logic has had much influence on analytic philosophy.
Characteristics
Each logical system in this c ...
, the ''signed formula'' notation is simplified so that
is written simply as
, and
as
, which accounts for naming rule 1 the "''Rule of Double Negation''".
One constructs a tableau for a set of formulas by applying the rules to produce more lines and tree branches until every line has been used, producing a ''complete'' tableau. In some cases, a branch can come to contain both
and
for some
, which is to say, a contradiction. In that case, the branch is said to close.
If every branch in a tree closes, the tree itself is said to close.
In virtue of the rules for construction of tableaux, a closed tree is a proof that the original formula, or set of formulas, used to construct it was itself self-contradictory, and therefore false.
Conversely, a tableau can also prove that a logical formula is
tautologous: if a formula is tautologous, its negation is a contradiction, so a tableau built from its negation will close.
To construct a tableau for an argument
, one first writes out the set of premise formulas,
, with one formula on each line, signed with
(that is,
for each
in the set);
and together with those formulas (the order is unimportant), one also writes out the conclusion,
, signed with
(that is,
).
One then produces a truth tree (analytic tableau) by using all those lines according to the rules.
A closed tree will be proof that the argument was valid, in virtue of the fact that
if, and only if,
is inconsistent (also written as
).
List of classically valid argument forms
Using semantic checking methods, such as truth tables or semantic tableaux, to check for tautologies and semantic consequences, it can be shown that, in classical logic, the following classical argument forms are semantically valid, i.e., these tautologies and semantic consequences hold.
We use
⟚
to denote equivalence of
and
, that is, as an abbreviation for both
and
;
as an aid to reading the symbols, a description of each formula is given. The description reads the symbol ⊧ (called the "double turnstile") as "therefore", which is a common reading of it,
although many authors prefer to read it as "entails",
or as "models".
Syntactic proof via natural deduction
Natural deduction, since it is a method of syntactical proof, is specified by providing ''inference rules'' (also called ''rules of proof'')
for a language with the typical set of connectives
; no axioms are used other than these rules.
The rules are covered below, and a proof example is given afterwards.
Notation styles
Different authors vary to some extent regarding which inference rules they give, which will be noted. More striking to the look and feel of a proof, however, is the variation in notation styles. The , which was covered earlier for a short argument, can actually be stacked to produce large tree-shaped natural deduction proofs
—not to be confused with "truth trees", which is another name for
analytic tableaux.
There is also a style due to
Stanisław Jaśkowski, where the formulas in the proof are written inside various nested boxes,
and there is a simplification of Jaśkowski's style due to
Fredric Fitch (
Fitch notation), where the boxes are simplified to simple horizontal lines beneath the introductions of suppositions, and vertical lines to the left of the lines that are under the supposition.
Lastly, there is the only notation style which will actually be used in this article, which is due to
Patrick Suppes,
but was much popularized by
E.J. Lemmon and
Benson Mates.
This method has the advantage that, graphically, it is the least intensive to produce and display, which made it a natural choice for the
editor who wrote this part of the article, who did not understand the complex
LaTeX
Latex is an emulsion (stable dispersion) of polymer microparticles in water. Latices are found in nature, but synthetic latices are common as well.
In nature, latex is found as a wikt:milky, milky fluid, which is present in 10% of all floweri ...
commands that would be required to produce proofs in the other methods.
A proof, then, laid out in accordance with the
Suppes–Lemmon notation style,
is a sequence of lines containing sentences,
where each sentence is either an assumption, or the result of applying a rule of proof to earlier sentences in the sequence.
Each line of proof is made up of a sentence of proof, together with its annotation, its assumption set, and the current line number.
The assumption set lists the assumptions on which the given sentence of proof depends, which are referenced by the line numbers.
The annotation specifies which rule of proof was applied, and to which earlier lines, to yield the current sentence.
See the .
Inference rules
Natural deduction inference rules, due ultimately to
Gentzen, are given below.
There are ten primitive rules of proof, which are the rule ''assumption'', plus four pairs of introduction and elimination rules for the binary connectives, and the rule ''reductio ad adbsurdum''.
Disjunctive Syllogism can be used as an easier alternative to the proper ∨-elimination,
and MTT and DN are commonly given rules,
although they are not primitive.
Natural deduction proof example
The proof below
derives
from
and
using only MPP and RAA, which shows that MTT is not a primitive rule, since it can be derived from those two other rules.
Syntactic proof via axioms
It is possible to perform proofs axiomatically, which means that certain
tautologies are taken as self-evident and various others are deduced from them using
modus ponens as an
inference rule, as well as a ''rule of
substitution'', which permits replacing any
well-formed formula
In mathematical logic, propositional logic and predicate logic, a well-formed formula, abbreviated WFF or wff, often simply formula, is a finite sequence of symbols from a given alphabet that is part of a formal language.
The abbreviation wf ...
with any of it.
Alternatively, one uses axiom schemas instead of axioms, and no rule of substitution is used.
This section gives the axioms of some historically notable axiomatic systems for propositional logic. For more examples, as well as metalogical theorems that are specific to such axiomatic systems (such as their completeness and consistency), see the article
Axiomatic system (logic).
Frege's ''Begriffsschrift''
Although axiomatic proof has been used since the famous
Ancient Greek
Ancient Greek (, ; ) includes the forms of the Greek language used in ancient Greece and the classical antiquity, ancient world from around 1500 BC to 300 BC. It is often roughly divided into the following periods: Mycenaean Greek (), Greek ...
textbook,
Euclid
Euclid (; ; BC) was an ancient Greek mathematician active as a geometer and logician. Considered the "father of geometry", he is chiefly known for the '' Elements'' treatise, which established the foundations of geometry that largely domina ...
's ''
Elements of Geometry'', in propositional logic it dates back to
Gottlob Frege
Friedrich Ludwig Gottlob Frege (; ; 8 November 1848 – 26 July 1925) was a German philosopher, logician, and mathematician. He was a mathematics professor at the University of Jena, and is understood by many to be the father of analytic philos ...
's
1879 ''
Begriffsschrift''.
Frege's system used only
implication and
negation
In logic, negation, also called the logical not or logical complement, is an operation (mathematics), operation that takes a Proposition (mathematics), proposition P to another proposition "not P", written \neg P, \mathord P, P^\prime or \over ...
as connectives.
It had six axioms:
* Proposition 1:
* Proposition 2:
* Proposition 8:
* Proposition 28:
* Proposition 31:
* Proposition 41:
These were used by Frege together with modus ponens and a rule of substitution (which was used but never precisely stated) to yield a complete and consistent axiomatization of classical truth-functional propositional logic.
Łukasiewicz's P2
Jan Łukasiewicz
Jan Łukasiewicz (; 21 December 1878 – 13 February 1956) was a Polish logician and philosopher who is best known for Polish notation and Łukasiewicz logic. His work centred on philosophical logic, mathematical logic and history of logi ...
showed that, in Frege's system, "the third axiom is superfluous since it can be derived from the preceding two axioms, and that the last three axioms can be replaced by the single sentence
".
Which, taken out of Łukasiewicz's
Polish notation
Polish notation (PN), also known as normal Polish notation (NPN), Łukasiewicz notation, Warsaw notation, Polish prefix notation, Eastern Notation or simply prefix notation, is a mathematical notation in which Operation (mathematics), operator ...
into modern notation, means
. Hence, Łukasiewicz is credited
with this system of three axioms:
*
*
*
Just like Frege's system, this system uses a substitution rule and uses modus ponens as an inference rule.
The exact same system was given (with an explicit substitution rule) by
Alonzo Church
Alonzo Church (June 14, 1903 – August 11, 1995) was an American computer scientist, mathematician, logician, and philosopher who made major contributions to mathematical logic and the foundations of theoretical computer science. He is bes ...
,
who referred to it as the system P
2 and helped popularize it.
Schematic form of P2
One may avoid using the rule of substitution by giving the axioms in schematic form, using them to generate an infinite set of axioms. Hence, using Greek letters to represent schemata (metalogical variables that may stand for any
well-formed formula
In mathematical logic, propositional logic and predicate logic, a well-formed formula, abbreviated WFF or wff, often simply formula, is a finite sequence of symbols from a given alphabet that is part of a formal language.
The abbreviation wf ...
s), the axioms are given as:
*
*
*
The schematic version of P
2 is attributed to
John von Neumann
John von Neumann ( ; ; December 28, 1903 – February 8, 1957) was a Hungarian and American mathematician, physicist, computer scientist and engineer. Von Neumann had perhaps the widest coverage of any mathematician of his time, in ...
,
and is used in the
Metamath "set.mm" formal proof database.
It has also been attributed to
Hilbert
David Hilbert (; ; 23 January 1862 – 14 February 1943) was a German mathematician and philosophy of mathematics, philosopher of mathematics and one of the most influential mathematicians of his time.
Hilbert discovered and developed a broad ...
,
and named
in this context.
Proof example in P2
As an example, a proof of
in P
2 is given below. First, the axioms are given names:
:(A1)
:(A2)
:(A3)
And the proof is as follows:
#
(instance of (A1))
#
(instance of (A2))
#
(from (1) and (2) by
modus ponens)
#
(instance of (A1))
#
(from (4) and (3) by modus ponens)
Solvers
One notable difference between propositional calculus and predicate calculus is that satisfiability of a propositional formula is
decidable.
Deciding satisfiability of propositional logic formulas is an
NP-complete problem. However, practical methods exist (e.g.,
DPLL algorithm, 1962;
Chaff algorithm, 2001) that are very fast for many useful cases. Recent work has extended the
SAT solver algorithms to work with propositions containing
arithmetic expressions; these are the
SMT solvers.
See also
Higher logical levels
*
First-order logic
*
Second-order propositional logic
*
Second-order logic
*
Higher-order logic
Related topics
*
Boolean algebra (logic)
*
Boolean algebra (structure)
*
Boolean algebra topics
*
Boolean domain
*
Boolean function
*
Boolean-valued function
*
Categorical logic
*
Combinational logic
*
Combinatory logic
*
Conceptual graph
*
Disjunctive syllogism
*
Entitative graph
An existential graph is a type of diagrammatic or visual notation for logical expressions, created by Charles Sanders Peirce, who wrote on graphical logic as early as 1882, and continued to develop the method until his death in 1914. They include ...
*
Equational logic
*
Existential graph
*
Implicational propositional calculus
*
Intuitionistic propositional calculus
*
Jean Buridan
* ''
Laws of Form
''Laws of Form'' (hereinafter ''LoF'') is a book by G. Spencer-Brown, published in 1969, that straddles the boundary between mathematics and philosophy. ''LoF'' describes three distinct logical systems:
* The primary arithmetic (described in Ch ...
''
*
List of logic symbols
In logic, a set of symbols is commonly used to express logical representation. The following table lists many common symbols, together with their name, how they should be read out loud, and the related field of mathematics. Additionally, the sub ...
*
Logical graph
*
Logical NOR
*
Logical value
*
Mathematical logic
Mathematical logic is the study of Logic#Formal logic, formal logic within mathematics. Major subareas include model theory, proof theory, set theory, and recursion theory (also known as computability theory). Research in mathematical logic com ...
*
Operation (mathematics)
In mathematics, an operation is a function from a set to itself. For example, an operation on real numbers will take in real numbers and return a real number. An operation can take zero or more input values (also called "'' operands''" or "arg ...
*
Paul of Venice
*
Peirce's law
*
Peter of Spain (author)
*
Propositional formula
*
Symmetric difference
*
Tautology (rule of inference)
*
Truth function
*
Truth table
A truth table is a mathematical table used in logic—specifically in connection with Boolean algebra, Boolean functions, and propositional calculus—which sets out the functional values of logical expressions on each of their functional arg ...
*
Walter Burley
*
William of Sherwood
Notes
References
Further reading
* Brown, Frank Markham (2003), ''Boolean Reasoning: The Logic of Boolean Equations'', 1st edition, Kluwer Academic Publishers, Norwell, MA. 2nd edition, Dover Publications, Mineola, NY.
*
Chang, C.C. and
Keisler, H.J. (1973), ''Model Theory'', North-Holland, Amsterdam, Netherlands.
* Kohavi, Zvi (1978), ''Switching and Finite Automata Theory'', 1st edition, McGraw–Hill, 1970. 2nd edition, McGraw–Hill, 1978.
*
Korfhage, Robert R. (1974), ''Discrete Computational Structures'', Academic Press, New York, NY.
*
Lambek, J. and Scott, P.J. (1986), ''Introduction to Higher Order Categorical Logic'', Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, UK.
* Mendelson, Elliot (1964), ''Introduction to Mathematical Logic'', D. Van Nostrand Company.
Related works
*
External links
*
*
Formal Predicate Calculus contains a systematic formal development with axiomatic proof
*
forall x: an introduction to formal logic', by
P.D. Magnus, covers formal semantics and
proof theory
Proof theory is a major branchAccording to , proof theory is one of four domains mathematical logic, together with model theory, axiomatic set theory, and recursion theory. consists of four corresponding parts, with part D being about "Proof The ...
for sentential logic.
Chapter 2 / Propositional Logicfro
Logic In ActionPropositional sequent calculus proveron Project Nayuki. (''note'': implication can be input in the form
!X, Y
, and a sequent can be a single formula prefixed with
>
and having no commas)
Propositional Logic - A Generative GrammarA Propositional Calculator that helps to understand simple expressions
{{Authority control
Logical calculi
Boolean algebra
Classical logic
Analytic philosophy