HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In mathematics, and in particular
model theory In mathematical logic, model theory is the study of the relationship between formal theories (a collection of sentences in a formal language expressing statements about a mathematical structure), and their models (those structures in which the ...
, a prime model is a model that is as simple as possible. Specifically, a model P is prime if it admits an
elementary embedding In model theory, a branch of mathematical logic, two structures ''M'' and ''N'' of the same signature ''σ'' are called elementarily equivalent if they satisfy the same first-order ''σ''-sentences. If ''N'' is a substructure of ''M'', one ofte ...
into any model M to which it is
elementarily equivalent In model theory, a branch of mathematical logic, two structures ''M'' and ''N'' of the same signature ''σ'' are called elementarily equivalent if they satisfy the same first-order ''σ''-sentences. If ''N'' is a substructure of ''M'', one ofte ...
(that is, into any model M satisfying the same
complete theory In mathematical logic, a theory is complete if it is consistent and for every closed formula in the theory's language, either that formula or its negation is provable. That is, for every sentence \varphi, the theory T contains the sentence or its ...
as P).


Cardinality

In contrast with the notion of
saturated model In mathematical logic, and particularly in its subfield model theory, a saturated model ''M'' is one that realizes as many complete types as may be "reasonably expected" given its size. For example, an ultrapower model of the hyperreals is \al ...
, prime models are restricted to very specific cardinalities by the
Löwenheim–Skolem theorem In mathematical logic, the Löwenheim–Skolem theorem is a theorem on the existence and cardinality of models, named after Leopold Löwenheim and Thoralf Skolem. The precise formulation is given below. It implies that if a countable first-orde ...
. If L is a
first-order language First-order logic—also known as predicate logic, quantificational logic, and first-order predicate calculus—is a collection of formal systems used in mathematics, philosophy, linguistics, and computer science. First-order logic uses quantif ...
with cardinality \kappa and T is a complete theory over L, then this theorem guarantees a model for T of cardinality \max(\kappa,\aleph_0). Therefore no prime model of T can have larger cardinality since at the very least it must be elementarily embedded in such a model. This still leaves much ambiguity in the actual cardinality. In the case of countable languages, all prime models are at most countably infinite.


Relationship with saturated models

There is a duality between the definitions of prime and saturated models. Half of this duality is discussed in the article on
saturated model In mathematical logic, and particularly in its subfield model theory, a saturated model ''M'' is one that realizes as many complete types as may be "reasonably expected" given its size. For example, an ultrapower model of the hyperreals is \al ...
s, while the other half is as follows. While a saturated model realizes as many
type Type may refer to: Science and technology Computing * Typing, producing text via a keyboard, typewriter, etc. * Data type, collection of values used for computations. * File type * TYPE (DOS command), a command to display contents of a file. * Ty ...
s as possible, a prime model realizes as few as possible: it is an atomic model, realizing only the types that cannot be omitted and omitting the remainder. This may be interpreted in the sense that a prime model admits "no frills": any characteristic of a model that is optional is ignored in it. For example, the model \langle , S\rangle is a prime model of the theory of the natural numbers ''N'' with a successor operation ''S''; a non-prime model might be \langle + , S\rangle , meaning that there is a ''copy'' of the full integers that lies disjoint from the original copy of the natural numbers within this model; in this add-on, arithmetic works as usual. These models are elementarily equivalent; their theory admits the following axiomatization (verbally): # There is a unique element that is not the successor of any element; # No two distinct elements have the same successor; # No element satisfies ''S''''n''(''x'') = ''x'' with ''n'' > 0. These are, in fact, two of
Peano's axioms In mathematical logic, the Peano axioms, also known as the Dedekind–Peano axioms or the Peano postulates, are axioms for the natural numbers presented by the 19th century Italian mathematician Giuseppe Peano. These axioms have been used nea ...
, while the third follows from the first by induction (another of Peano's axioms). Any model of this theory consists of disjoint copies of the full integers in addition to the natural numbers, since once one generates a submodel from 0 all remaining points admit both predecessors and successors indefinitely. This is the outline of a proof that \langle , S\rangle is a prime model.


References

* {{Mathematical logic Mathematical logic Model theory