
In
mathematics
Mathematics is a field of study that discovers and organizes methods, Mathematical theory, theories and theorems that are developed and Mathematical proof, proved for the needs of empirical sciences and mathematics itself. There are many ar ...
, the natural numbers are the numbers
0,
1,
2,
3, and so on, possibly excluding 0.
Some start counting with 0, defining the natural numbers as the non-negative integers , while others start with 1, defining them as the positive integers Some authors acknowledge both definitions whenever convenient.
Sometimes, the whole numbers are the natural numbers as well as zero. In other cases, the ''whole numbers'' refer to all of the
integers, including negative integers. The counting numbers are another term for the natural numbers, particularly in primary education, and are ambiguous as well although typically start at 1.
The natural numbers are used for counting things, like "there are ''six'' coins on the table", in which case they are called ''
cardinal number
In mathematics, a cardinal number, or cardinal for short, is what is commonly called the number of elements of a set. In the case of a finite set, its cardinal number, or cardinality is therefore a natural number. For dealing with the cas ...
s''. They are also used to put things in order, like "this is the ''third'' largest city in the country", which are called ''
ordinal number
In set theory, an ordinal number, or ordinal, is a generalization of ordinal numerals (first, second, th, etc.) aimed to extend enumeration to infinite sets.
A finite set can be enumerated by successively labeling each element with the leas ...
s''. Natural numbers are also used as labels, like
jersey numbers on a sports team, where they serve as ''
nominal numbers'' and do not have mathematical properties.
The natural numbers form a
set, commonly symbolized as a bold or
blackboard bold . Many other
number sets are built from the natural numbers. For example, the
integers are made by adding 0 and negative numbers. The
rational numbers add fractions, and the
real numbers add all infinite decimals.
Complex numbers add the
square root of . This chain of extensions canonically
embeds the natural numbers in the other number systems.
Natural numbers are studied in different areas of math.
Number theory
Number theory is a branch of pure mathematics devoted primarily to the study of the integers and arithmetic functions. Number theorists study prime numbers as well as the properties of mathematical objects constructed from integers (for example ...
looks at things like how numbers divide evenly (
divisibility), or how
prime number
A prime number (or a prime) is a natural number greater than 1 that is not a Product (mathematics), product of two smaller natural numbers. A natural number greater than 1 that is not prime is called a composite number. For example, 5 is prime ...
s are spread out.
Combinatorics studies counting and arranging numbered objects, such as
partitions and
enumerations.
History
Ancient roots
The most primitive method of representing a natural number is to use one's fingers, as in
finger counting. Putting down a
tally mark for each object is another primitive method. Later, a set of objects could be tested for equality, excess or shortage—by striking out a mark and removing an object from the set.
The first major advance in abstraction was the use of
numerals to represent numbers. This allowed systems to be developed for recording large numbers. The ancient
Egyptians
Egyptians (, ; , ; ) are an ethnic group native to the Nile, Nile Valley in Egypt. Egyptian identity is closely tied to Geography of Egypt, geography. The population is concentrated in the Nile Valley, a small strip of cultivable land stretchi ...
developed a powerful system of numerals with distinct
hieroglyphs for 1, 10, and all powers of 10 up to over 1 million. A stone carving from
Karnak, dating back from around 1500 BCE and now at the
Louvre
The Louvre ( ), or the Louvre Museum ( ), is a national art museum in Paris, France, and one of the most famous museums in the world. It is located on the Rive Droite, Right Bank of the Seine in the city's 1st arrondissement of Paris, 1st arron ...
in Paris, depicts 276 as 2 hundreds, 7 tens, and 6 ones; and similarly for the number 4,622. The
Babylonia
Babylonia (; , ) was an Ancient history, ancient Akkadian language, Akkadian-speaking state and cultural area based in the city of Babylon in central-southern Mesopotamia (present-day Iraq and parts of Kuwait, Syria and Iran). It emerged as a ...
ns had a
place-value system based essentially on the numerals for 1 and 10, using base sixty, so that the symbol for sixty was the same as the symbol for one—its value being determined from context.
A much later advance was the development of the idea that can be considered as a number, with its own numeral. The use of a 0
digit in place-value notation (within other numbers) dates back as early as 700 BCE by the Babylonians, who omitted such a digit when it would have been the last symbol in the number. The
Olmec and
Maya civilizations used 0 as a separate number as early as the , but this usage did not spread beyond
Mesoamerica
Mesoamerica is a historical region and cultural area that begins in the southern part of North America and extends to the Pacific coast of Central America, thus comprising the lands of central and southern Mexico, all of Belize, Guatemala, El S ...
. The use of a numeral 0 in modern times originated with the Indian mathematician
Brahmagupta
Brahmagupta ( – ) was an Indian Indian mathematics, mathematician and Indian astronomy, astronomer. He is the author of two early works on mathematics and astronomy: the ''Brāhmasphuṭasiddhānta'' (BSS, "correctly established Siddhanta, do ...
in 628 CE. However, 0 had been used as a number in the medieval
computus (the calculation of the date of Easter), beginning with
Dionysius Exiguus in 525 CE, without being denoted by a numeral. Standard
Roman numerals
Roman numerals are a numeral system that originated in ancient Rome and remained the usual way of writing numbers throughout Europe well into the Late Middle Ages. Numbers are written with combinations of letters from the Latin alphabet, eac ...
do not have a symbol for 0; instead, ''nulla'' (or the genitive form ''nullae'') from , the Latin word for "none", was employed to denote a 0 value.
The first systematic study of numbers as
abstractions is usually credited to the
Greek philosophers
Pythagoras and
Archimedes. Some Greek mathematicians treated the number 1 differently than larger numbers, sometimes even not as a number at all.
Euclid, for example, defined a unit first and then a number as a multitude of units, thus by his definition, a unit is not a number and there are no unique numbers (e.g., any two units from indefinitely many units is a 2).
However, in the definition of
perfect number
In number theory, a perfect number is a positive integer that is equal to the sum of its positive proper divisors, that is, divisors excluding the number itself. For instance, 6 has proper divisors 1, 2 and 3, and 1 + 2 + 3 = 6, so 6 is a perfec ...
which comes shortly afterward, Euclid treats 1 as a number like any other.
Independent studies on numbers also occurred at around the same time in
India
India, officially the Republic of India, is a country in South Asia. It is the List of countries and dependencies by area, seventh-largest country by area; the List of countries by population (United Nations), most populous country since ...
, China, and
Mesoamerica
Mesoamerica is a historical region and cultural area that begins in the southern part of North America and extends to the Pacific coast of Central America, thus comprising the lands of central and southern Mexico, all of Belize, Guatemala, El S ...
.
Emergence as a term
Nicolas Chuquet used the term ''progression naturelle'' (natural progression) in 1484. The earliest known use of "natural number" as a complete English phrase is in 1763.
The 1771 Encyclopaedia Britannica defines natural numbers in the logarithm article.
Starting at 0 or 1 has long been a matter of definition. In 1727,
Bernard Le Bovier de Fontenelle wrote that his notions of distance and element led to defining the natural numbers as including or excluding 0. In 1889,
Giuseppe Peano
Giuseppe Peano (; ; 27 August 1858 – 20 April 1932) was an Italian mathematician and glottologist. The author of over 200 books and papers, he was a founder of mathematical logic and set theory, to which he contributed much Mathematical notati ...
used N for the positive integers and started at 1, but he later changed to using N
0 and N
1. Historically, most definitions have excluded 0,
but many mathematicians such as
George A. Wentworth,
Bertrand Russell
Bertrand Arthur William Russell, 3rd Earl Russell, (18 May 1872 – 2 February 1970) was a British philosopher, logician, mathematician, and public intellectual. He had influence on mathematics, logic, set theory, and various areas of analytic ...
,
Nicolas Bourbaki,
Paul Halmos,
Stephen Cole Kleene, and
John Horton Conway have preferred to include 0.
Mathematicians have noted tendencies in which definition is used, such as algebra texts including 0,
number theory and analysis texts excluding 0,
logic and set theory texts including 0, dictionaries excluding 0,
school books (through high-school level) excluding 0, and upper-division college-level books including 0.
There are exceptions to each of these tendencies and as of 2023 no formal survey has been conducted. Arguments raised include
division by zero and the size of the
empty set
In mathematics, the empty set or void set is the unique Set (mathematics), set having no Element (mathematics), elements; its size or cardinality (count of elements in a set) is 0, zero. Some axiomatic set theories ensure that the empty set exi ...
.
Computer language
A computer language is a formal language used to communicate with a computer. Types of computer languages include:
* Software construction#Construction languages, Construction language – all forms of communication by which a human can Comput ...
s often
start from zero when enumerating items like
loop counters and
string- or
array-elements. Including 0 began to rise in popularity in the 1960s.
The
ISO 31-11 standard included 0 in the natural numbers in its first edition in 1978 and this has continued through its present edition as
ISO 80000-2.
[
]
Formal construction
In 19th century Europe, there was mathematical and philosophical discussion about the exact nature of the natural numbers. Henri Poincaré stated that axioms can only be demonstrated in their finite application, and concluded that it is "the power of the mind" which allows conceiving of the indefinite repetition of the same act. Leopold Kronecker
Leopold Kronecker (; 7 December 1823 – 29 December 1891) was a German mathematician who worked on number theory, abstract algebra and logic, and criticized Georg Cantor's work on set theory. Heinrich Weber quoted Kronecker
as having said, ...
summarized his belief as "God made the integers, all else is the work of man".
The constructivists saw a need to improve upon the logical rigor in the foundations of mathematics
Foundations of mathematics are the mathematical logic, logical and mathematics, mathematical framework that allows the development of mathematics without generating consistency, self-contradictory theories, and to have reliable concepts of theo ...
. In the 1860s, Hermann Grassmann suggested a recursive definition for natural numbers, thus stating they were not really natural—but a consequence of definitions. Later, two classes of such formal definitions emerged, using set theory and Peano's axioms respectively. Later still, they were shown to be equivalent in most practical applications.
Set-theoretical definitions of natural numbers were initiated by Frege. He initially defined a natural number as the class of all sets that are in one-to-one correspondence with a particular set. However, this definition turned out to lead to paradoxes, including Russell's paradox. To avoid such paradoxes, the formalism was modified so that a natural number is defined as a particular set, and any set that can be put into one-to-one correspondence with that set is said to have that number of elements.
In 1881, Charles Sanders Peirce provided the first axiomatization of natural-number arithmetic. In 1888, Richard Dedekind proposed another axiomatization of natural-number arithmetic, and in 1889, Peano published a simplified version of Dedekind's axioms in his book ''The principles of arithmetic presented by a new method'' (). This approach is now called Peano arithmetic. It is based on an axiomatization of the properties of ordinal number
In set theory, an ordinal number, or ordinal, is a generalization of ordinal numerals (first, second, th, etc.) aimed to extend enumeration to infinite sets.
A finite set can be enumerated by successively labeling each element with the leas ...
s: each natural number has a successor and every non-zero natural number has a unique predecessor. Peano arithmetic is equiconsistent with several weak systems of set theory
Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies Set (mathematics), sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory – as a branch of mathema ...
. One such system is ZFC with the axiom of infinity replaced by its negation. Theorems that can be proved in ZFC but cannot be proved using the Peano Axioms include Goodstein's theorem.
Notation
The set of all natural numbers is standardly denoted or Older texts have occasionally employed as the symbol for this set.
Since natural numbers may contain or not, it may be important to know which version is referred to. This is often specified by the context, but may also be done by using a subscript or a superscript in the notation, such as:
* Naturals without zero:
* Naturals with zero:
Alternatively, since the natural numbers naturally form a subset of the integers (often they may be referred to as the positive, or the non-negative integers, respectively. To be unambiguous about whether 0 is included or not, sometimes a superscript "" or "+" is added in the former case, and a subscript (or superscript) "0" is added in the latter case:
:
:
Properties
This section uses the convention .
Addition
Given the set of natural numbers and the successor function sending each natural number to the next one, one can define addition
Addition (usually signified by the Plus and minus signs#Plus sign, plus symbol, +) is one of the four basic Operation (mathematics), operations of arithmetic, the other three being subtraction, multiplication, and Division (mathematics), divis ...
of natural numbers recursively by setting and for all , . Thus, , , and so on. The algebraic structure is a commutative
In mathematics, a binary operation is commutative if changing the order of the operands does not change the result. It is a fundamental property of many binary operations, and many mathematical proofs depend on it. Perhaps most familiar as a pr ...
monoid with identity element 0. It is a free monoid on one generator. This commutative monoid satisfies the cancellation property, so it can be embedded in a group. The smallest group containing the natural numbers is the integers.
If 1 is defined as , then . That is, is simply the successor of .
Multiplication
Analogously, given that addition has been defined, a multiplication
Multiplication is one of the four elementary mathematical operations of arithmetic, with the other ones being addition, subtraction, and division (mathematics), division. The result of a multiplication operation is called a ''Product (mathem ...
operator can be defined via and . This turns into a free commutative monoid with identity element 1; a generator set for this monoid is the set of prime number
A prime number (or a prime) is a natural number greater than 1 that is not a Product (mathematics), product of two smaller natural numbers. A natural number greater than 1 that is not prime is called a composite number. For example, 5 is prime ...
s.
Relationship between addition and multiplication
Addition and multiplication are compatible, which is expressed in the distribution law: . These properties of addition and multiplication make the natural numbers an instance of a commutative
In mathematics, a binary operation is commutative if changing the order of the operands does not change the result. It is a fundamental property of many binary operations, and many mathematical proofs depend on it. Perhaps most familiar as a pr ...
semiring. Semirings are an algebraic generalization of the natural numbers where multiplication is not necessarily commutative. The lack of additive inverses, which is equivalent to the fact that is not closed under subtraction (that is, subtracting one natural from another does not always result in another natural), means that is ''not'' a ring; instead it is a semiring (also known as a ''rig'').
If the natural numbers are taken as "excluding 0", and "starting at 1", the definitions of + and × are as above, except that they begin with and . Furthermore, has no identity element.
Order
In this section, juxtaposed variables such as indicate the product , and the standard order of operations is assumed.
A total order on the natural numbers is defined by letting if and only if there exists another natural number where . This order is compatible with the arithmetical operations in the following sense: if , and are natural numbers and , then and .
An important property of the natural numbers is that they are well-ordered: every non-empty set of natural numbers has a least element. The rank among well-ordered sets is expressed by an ordinal number
In set theory, an ordinal number, or ordinal, is a generalization of ordinal numerals (first, second, th, etc.) aimed to extend enumeration to infinite sets.
A finite set can be enumerated by successively labeling each element with the leas ...
; for the natural numbers, this is denoted as (omega).
Division
In this section, juxtaposed variables such as indicate the product , and the standard order of operations is assumed.
While it is in general not possible to divide one natural number by another and get a natural number as result, the procedure of ''division with remainder'' or Euclidean division is available as a substitute: for any two natural numbers and with there are natural numbers and such that
:
The number is called the '' quotient'' and is called the '' remainder'' of the division of by . The numbers and are uniquely determined by and . This Euclidean division is key to the several other properties ( divisibility), algorithms (such as the Euclidean algorithm), and ideas in number theory.
Algebraic properties satisfied by the natural numbers
The addition (+) and multiplication (×) operations on natural numbers as defined above have several algebraic properties:
* Closure under addition and multiplication: for all natural numbers and , both and are natural numbers.
* Associativity: for all natural numbers , , and , and .
* Commutativity: for all natural numbers and , and .
* Existence of identity elements: for every natural number , and .
** If the natural numbers are taken as "excluding 0", and "starting at 1", then for every natural number , . However, the "existence of additive identity element" property is not satisfied
* Distributivity of multiplication over addition for all natural numbers , , and , .
* No nonzero zero divisors: if and are natural numbers such that , then or (or both).
Generalizations
Two important generalizations of natural numbers arise from the two uses of counting and ordering: cardinal number
In mathematics, a cardinal number, or cardinal for short, is what is commonly called the number of elements of a set. In the case of a finite set, its cardinal number, or cardinality is therefore a natural number. For dealing with the cas ...
s and ordinal number
In set theory, an ordinal number, or ordinal, is a generalization of ordinal numerals (first, second, th, etc.) aimed to extend enumeration to infinite sets.
A finite set can be enumerated by successively labeling each element with the leas ...
s.
* A natural number can be used to express the size of a finite set; more precisely, a cardinal number is a measure for the size of a set, which is even suitable for infinite sets. The numbering of cardinals usually begins at zero, to accommodate the empty set
In mathematics, the empty set or void set is the unique Set (mathematics), set having no Element (mathematics), elements; its size or cardinality (count of elements in a set) is 0, zero. Some axiomatic set theories ensure that the empty set exi ...
. This concept of "size" relies on maps between sets, such that two sets have the same size, exactly if there exists a bijection between them. The set of natural numbers itself, and any bijective image of it, is said to be '' countably infinite'' and to have cardinality aleph-null ().
* Natural numbers are also used as linguistic ordinal numbers: "first", "second", "third", and so forth. The numbering of ordinals usually begins at zero, to accommodate the order type of the empty set
In mathematics, the empty set or void set is the unique Set (mathematics), set having no Element (mathematics), elements; its size or cardinality (count of elements in a set) is 0, zero. Some axiomatic set theories ensure that the empty set exi ...
. This way they can be assigned to the elements of a totally ordered finite set, and also to the elements of any well-ordered countably infinite set without limit points. This assignment can be generalized to general well-orderings with a cardinality beyond countability, to yield the ordinal numbers. An ordinal number may also be used to describe the notion of "size" for a well-ordered set, in a sense different from cardinality: if there is an order isomorphism (more than a bijection) between two well-ordered sets, they have the same ordinal number. The first ordinal number that is not a natural number is expressed as ; this is also the ordinal number of the set of natural numbers itself.
The least ordinal of cardinality (that is, the initial ordinal of ) is but many well-ordered sets with cardinal number have an ordinal number greater than .
For finite well-ordered sets, there is a one-to-one correspondence between ordinal and cardinal numbers; therefore they can both be expressed by the same natural number, the number of elements of the set. This number can also be used to describe the position of an element in a larger finite, or an infinite, sequence.
A countable non-standard model of arithmetic satisfying the Peano Arithmetic (that is, the first-order Peano axioms) was developed by Skolem in 1933. The hypernatural numbers are an uncountable model that can be constructed from the ordinary natural numbers via the ultrapower construction. Other generalizations are discussed in .
Georges Reeb used to claim provocatively that "The naïve integers don't fill up ".
Formal definitions
There are two standard methods for formally defining natural numbers. The first one, named for Giuseppe Peano
Giuseppe Peano (; ; 27 August 1858 – 20 April 1932) was an Italian mathematician and glottologist. The author of over 200 books and papers, he was a founder of mathematical logic and set theory, to which he contributed much Mathematical notati ...
, consists of an autonomous axiomatic theory called Peano arithmetic, based on few axioms called Peano axioms.
The second definition is based on set theory
Set theory is the branch of mathematical logic that studies Set (mathematics), sets, which can be informally described as collections of objects. Although objects of any kind can be collected into a set, set theory – as a branch of mathema ...
. It defines the natural numbers as specific sets. More precisely, each natural number is defined as an explicitly defined set, whose elements allow counting the elements of other sets, in the sense that the sentence "a set has elements" means that there exists a one to one correspondence between the two sets and .
The sets used to define natural numbers satisfy Peano axioms. It follows that every theorem that can be stated and proved in Peano arithmetic can also be proved in set theory. However, the two definitions are not equivalent, as there are theorems that can be stated in terms of Peano arithmetic and proved in set theory, which are not ''provable'' inside Peano arithmetic. A probable example is Fermat's Last Theorem
In number theory, Fermat's Last Theorem (sometimes called Fermat's conjecture, especially in older texts) states that no three positive number, positive integers , , and satisfy the equation for any integer value of greater than . The cases ...
.
The definition of the integers as sets satisfying Peano axioms provide a model of Peano arithmetic inside set theory. An important consequence is that, if set theory is consistent (as it is usually guessed), then Peano arithmetic is consistent. In other words, if a contradiction could be proved in Peano arithmetic, then set theory would be contradictory, and every theorem of set theory would be both true and wrong.
Peano axioms
The five Peano axioms are the following:
# 0 is a natural number.
# Every natural number has a successor which is also a natural number.
# 0 is not the successor of any natural number.
# If the successor of equals the successor of , then equals .
# The axiom of induction: If a statement is true of 0, and if the truth of that statement for a number implies its truth for the successor of that number, then the statement is true for every natural number.
These are not the original axioms published by Peano, but are named in his honor. Some forms of the Peano axioms have 1 in place of 0. In ordinary arithmetic, the successor of is .
Set-theoretic definition
Intuitively, the natural number is the common property of all sets that have elements. So, it seems natural to define as an equivalence class under the relation "can be made in one to one correspondence". This does not work in all set theories, as such an equivalence class would not be a set (because of Russell's paradox). The standard solution is to define a particular set with elements that will be called the natural number .
The following definition was first published by John von Neumann, although Levy attributes the idea to unpublished work of Zermelo in 1916. As this definition extends to infinite set as a definition of ordinal number
In set theory, an ordinal number, or ordinal, is a generalization of ordinal numerals (first, second, th, etc.) aimed to extend enumeration to infinite sets.
A finite set can be enumerated by successively labeling each element with the leas ...
, the sets considered below are sometimes called von Neumann ordinals.
The definition proceeds as follows:
* Call , the empty set
In mathematics, the empty set or void set is the unique Set (mathematics), set having no Element (mathematics), elements; its size or cardinality (count of elements in a set) is 0, zero. Some axiomatic set theories ensure that the empty set exi ...
.
* Define the ''successor'' of any set by .
* By the axiom of infinity, there exist sets which contain 0 and are closed under the successor function. Such sets are said to be ''inductive''. The intersection of all inductive sets is still an inductive set.
* This intersection is the set of the ''natural numbers''.
It follows that the natural numbers are defined iteratively as follows:
:*,
:*,
:*,
:* ,
:* ,
:* etc.
It can be checked that the natural numbers satisfy the Peano axioms.
With this definition, given a natural number , the sentence "a set has elements" can be formally defined as "there exists a bijection from to ." This formalizes the operation of ''counting'' the elements of . Also, if and only if is a subset of . In other words, the set inclusion defines the usual total order on the natural numbers. This order is a well-order.
It follows from the definition that each natural number is equal to the set of all natural numbers less than it. This definition, can be extended to the von Neumann definition of ordinals for defining all ordinal number
In set theory, an ordinal number, or ordinal, is a generalization of ordinal numerals (first, second, th, etc.) aimed to extend enumeration to infinite sets.
A finite set can be enumerated by successively labeling each element with the leas ...
s, including the infinite ones: "each ordinal is the well-ordered set of all smaller ordinals."
If one does not accept the axiom of infinity, the natural numbers may not form a set. Nevertheless, the natural numbers can still be individually defined as above, and they still satisfy the Peano axioms.
There are other set theoretical constructions. In particular, Ernst Zermelo provided a construction that is nowadays only of historical interest, and is sometimes referred to as . It consists in defining as the empty set, and .
With this definition each nonzero natural number is a singleton set. So, the property of the natural numbers to represent cardinalities is not directly accessible; only the ordinal property (being the th element of a sequence) is immediate. Unlike von Neumann's construction, the Zermelo ordinals do not extend to infinite ordinals.
See also
*
*
* Sequence – Function of the natural numbers in another set
*
*
*
Notes
References
Bibliography
*
*
*
*
**
**
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
* – English translation of .
External links
*
*
{{Authority control
Cardinal numbers
Elementary mathematics
Integers
Number theory
Sets of real numbers