HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
mathematics Mathematics is an area of knowledge that includes the topics of numbers, formulas and related structures, shapes and the spaces in which they are contained, and quantities and their changes. These topics are represented in modern mathematics ...
and logic, plural quantification is the theory that an individual variable x may take on '' plural'', as well as singular, values. As well as substituting individual objects such as Alice, the number 1, the tallest building in London etc. for x, we may substitute both Alice and Bob, or all the numbers between 0 and 10, or all the buildings in London over 20 stories. The point of the theory is to give first-order logic the power of set theory, but without any " existential commitment" to such objects as sets. The classic expositions are Boolos 1984 and Lewis 1991.


History

The view is commonly associated with George Boolos, though it is older (see notably
Simons Simons is a surname of Scandinavian origins and a variant of Sigmundsson, a patronymic surname with roots in proto-Germanic ''*segaz'' and ''*mundō'', giving a rough translation of "protection through victory". Notable people A * Alan Si ...
1982), and is related to the view of classes defended by
John Stuart Mill John Stuart Mill (20 May 1806 – 7 May 1873) was an English philosopher, political economist, Member of Parliament (MP) and civil servant. One of the most influential thinkers in the history of classical liberalism, he contributed widely to ...
and other nominalist philosophers. Mill argued that universals or "classes" are not a peculiar kind of thing, having an objective existence distinct from the individual objects that fall under them, but "is neither more nor less than the individual things in the class". (Mill 1904, II. ii. 2,also I. iv. 3). A similar position was also discussed by Bertrand Russell in chapter VI of Russell (1903), but later dropped in favour of a "no-classes" theory. See also Gottlob Frege 1895 for a critique of an earlier view defended by Ernst Schroeder. The general idea can be traced back to Leibniz. (Levey 2011, pp. 129–133) Interest revived in plurals with work in linguistics in the 1970s by Remko Scha,
Godehard Link Godehard Link (born 7 July 1944 in Lippstadt) is a professor of logic and philosophy of science at the University of Munich The Ludwig Maximilian University of Munich (simply University of Munich or LMU; german: Ludwig-Maximilians-Universitä ...
, Fred Landman,
Friederike Moltmann Friederike Moltmann is a linguist and philosopher. She has done pioneering work at the intersection of philosophy and linguistics, especially on the interface between metaphysics and natural language semantics, but also on the interface betw ...
, Roger Schwarzschild,
Peter Lasersohn Peter Lasersohn is a professor of linguistics at the University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign. Education *Ph.D. in Linguistics: Ohio State University, 1988 *M.A. in Linguistics: Ohio State University, 1985 *B.A. in German, French: Earlham Colle ...
and others, who developed ideas for a semantics of plurals.


Background and motivation


Multigrade (variably polyadic) predicates and relations

Sentences like : Alice and Bob cooperate. : Alice, Bob and Carol cooperate. are said to involve a multigrade (also known as variably polyadic, also anadic) predicate or relation ("cooperate" in this example), meaning that they stand for the same concept even though they don't have a fixed
arity Arity () is the number of arguments or operands taken by a function, operation or relation in logic, mathematics, and computer science. In mathematics, arity may also be named ''rank'', but this word can have many other meanings in mathematics. In ...
(cf. Linnebo & Nicolas 2008). The notion of multigrade relation/predicate has appeared as early as the 1940s and has been notably used by Quine (cf. Morton 1975). Plural quantification deals with formalizing the quantification over the variable-length arguments of such predicates, e.g. "''xx'' cooperate" where ''xx'' is a plural variable. Note that in this example it makes no sense, semantically, to instantiate ''xx'' with the name of a single person.


Nominalism

Broadly speaking, nominalism denies the existence of universals ( abstract entities), like sets, classes, relations, properties, etc. Thus the plural logic(s) were developed as an attempt to formalize reasoning about plurals, such as those involved in multigrade predicates, apparently without resorting to notions that nominalists deny, e.g. sets. Standard first-order logic has difficulties in representing some sentences with plurals. Most well-known is the Geach–Kaplan sentence "some critics admire only one another". Kaplan proved that it is nonfirstorderizable (the proof can be found in that article). Hence its paraphrase into a formal language commits us to quantification over (i.e. the existence of) sets. Boolos argued that 2nd-order monadic quantification may be systematically interpreted in terms of plural quantification, and that, therefore, 2nd-order monadic quantification is "ontologically innocent".. Later, Oliver & Smiley (2001), Rayo (2002), Yi (2005) and McKay (2006) argued that sentences such as :They are shipmates :They are meeting together :They lifted a piano :They are surrounding a building :They admire only one another also cannot be interpreted in monadic second-order logic. This is because predicates such as "are shipmates", "are meeting together", "are surrounding a building" are not ''distributive''. A predicate F is distributive if, whenever some things are F, each one of them is F. But in standard logic, ''every monadic predicate is distributive''. Yet such sentences also seem innocent of any existential assumptions, and do not involve quantification. So one can propose a unified account of plural terms that allows for both distributive and non-distributive satisfaction of predicates, while defending this position against the "singularist" assumption that such predicates are predicates of sets of individuals (or of mereological sums). Several writers have suggested that plural logic opens the prospect of simplifying the foundations of mathematics, avoiding the paradoxes of set theory, and simplifying the complex and unintuitive axiom sets needed in order to avoid them. Recently, Linnebo & Nicolas (2008) have suggested that natural languages often contain superplural variables (and associated quantifiers) such as "these people, those people, and these other people compete against each other" (e.g. as teams in an online game), while Nicolas (2008) has argued that plural logic should be used to account for the semantics of mass nouns, like "wine" and "furniture".


Formal definition

This section presents a simple formulation of plural logic/quantification approximately the same as given by Boolos in ''Nominalist Platonism'' (Boolos 1985).


Syntax

Sub-sentential units are defined as * Predicate symbols F, G, etc. (with appropriate arities, which are left implicit) * Singular variable symbols x, y, etc. * Plural variable symbols \bar, \bar, etc. Full sentences are defined as * If F is an ''n''-ary predicate symbol, and x_0, \ldots, x_n are singular variable symbols, then F(x_0, \ldots, x_n) is a sentence. * If P is a sentence, then so is \neg P * If P and Q are sentences, then so is P \land Q * If P is a sentence and x is a singular variable symbol, then \exists x.P is a sentence * If x is a singular variable symbol and \bar is a plural variable symbol, then x \prec \bar is a sentence (where ≺ is usually interpreted as the relation "is one of") * If P is a sentence and \bar is a plural variable symbol, then \exists \bar.P is a sentence The last two lines are the only essentially new component to the syntax for plural logic. Other logical symbols definable in terms of these can be used freely as notational shorthands. This logic turns out to be equi-interpretable with monadic second-order logic.


Model theory

Plural logic's model theory/semantics is where the logic's lack of sets is cashed out. A model is defined as a tuple (D,V,s,R) where D is the domain, V is a collection of valuations V_F for each predicate name F in the usual sense, and s is a Tarskian sequence (assignment of values to variables) in the usual sense (i.e. a map from singular variable symbols to elements of D). The new component R is a binary relation relating values in the domain to plural variable symbols. Satisfaction is given as * (D,V,s,R) \models F(x_0, \ldots, x_n) iff (s_, \ldots, s_) \in V_F * (D,V,s,R) \models \neg P iff (D,V,s,R) \nvDash P * (D,V,s,R) \models P \land Q iff (D,V,s,R) \models P and (D,V,s,R) \models Q * (D,V,s,R) \models \exists x.P iff there is an s' \approx_x s such that (D,V,s',R) \models P * (D,V,s,R) \models x \prec \bar iff s_xR\bar * (D,V,s,R) \models \exists \bar.P iff there is an R' \approx_\bar R such that (D,V,s,R') \models P Where for singular variable symbols, s \approx_x s' means that for all singular variable symbols y other than x, it holds that s_y = s'_y, and for plural variable symbols, R \approx_\bar R' means that for all plural variable symbols \bar other than \bar, and for all objects of the domain d, it holds that dR\bar = dR'\bar. As in the syntax, only the last two are truly new in plural logic. Boolos observes that by using assignment ''relations'' R, the domain does not have to include sets, and therefore plural logic achieves ontological innocence while still retaining the ability to talk about the extensions of a predicate. Thus, the plural logic comprehension schema \exists \bar. \forall y. y \prec \bar \leftrightarrow F(y) does not yield Russell's paradox because the quantification of plural variables does not quantify over the domain. Another aspect of the logic as Boolos defines it, crucial to this bypassing of Russell's paradox, is the fact that sentences of the form F(\bar) are not well-formed: predicate names can only combine with singular variable symbols, not plural variable symbols. This can be taken as the simplest, and most obvious argument that plural logic as Boolos defined it is ontologically innocent.


See also

* Generalized quantifier * Variadic function


Notes


References

* George Boolos, 1984, "To be is to be the value of a variable (or to be some values of some variables)," ''Journal of Philosophy'' 81: 430–449. In Boolos 1998, 54–72. * --------, 1985, "Nominalist platonism." ''Philosophical Review'' 94: 327–344. In Boolos 1998, 73–87. * --------, 1998. ''Logic, Logic, and Logic''. Harvard University Press. * Burgess, J.P., "From Frege to Friedman: A Dream Come True?" * --------, 2004, “E Pluribus Unum: Plural Logic and Set Theory,” ''Philosophia Mathematica'' 12(3): 193–221. * Cameron, J. R., 1999, "Plural Reference," ''Ratio''. * * De Rouilhan, P., 2002, "On What There Are," ''Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society'': 183–200. * Gottlob Frege, 1895, "A critical elucidation of some points in E. Schroeder's ''Vorlesungen Ueber Die Algebra der Logik''," ''Archiv für systematische Philosophie'': 433–456. * Fred Landman 2000. ''Events and Plurality''. Kluwer. * *
David K. Lewis David Kellogg Lewis (September 28, 1941 – October 14, 2001) was an American philosopher who is widely regarded as one of the most important philosophers of the 20th century. Lewis taught briefly at UCLA and then at Princeton University fr ...
, 1991. ''Parts of Classes''. London: Blackwell. * * *
John Stuart Mill John Stuart Mill (20 May 1806 – 7 May 1873) was an English philosopher, political economist, Member of Parliament (MP) and civil servant. One of the most influential thinkers in the history of classical liberalism, he contributed widely to ...
, 1904, ''A System of Logic'', 8th ed. London: . * Moltmann, Friederike, 1997, ''Parts and Wholes in Semantics''. Oxford University Press, New York. * Moltmann, Friederike, 'Plural Reference and Reference to a Plurality. Linguistic Facts and Semantic Analyses'. In M. Carrara, A. Arapinis and F. Moltmann (eds.): Unity and Plurality. Logic, Philosophy, and Semantics. Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2016, pp. 93-120. * * * * * --------, 2006, “Beyond Plurals,” in Rayo and Uzquiano (2006). * --------, 2007, “Plurals,” forthcoming in ''Philosophy Compass''. * --------, and Gabriel Uzquiano, eds., 2006. ''Absolute Generality'' Oxford University Press. * Bertrand Russell, B., 1903. '' The Principles of Mathematics''. Oxford Univ. Press. * Peter Simons, 1982, “Plural Reference and Set Theory,” in Barry Smith, ed., ''Parts and Moments: Studies in Logic and Formal Ontology''. Munich: Philosophia Verlag. * --------, 1987. ''Parts''. Oxford University Press. * * * --------, 2005, “The Logic and Meaning of Plurals, Part I,” ''Journal of Philosophical Logic'' 34: 459–506. *
Adam Morton Adam Morton (1945 – 2020) was a Canadian philosopher. Morton's work focused on how we understand one another's behaviour in everyday life, with an emphasis on the role mutual intelligibility plays in cooperative activity. He also wrote on ethi ...
. "Complex individuals and multigrade relations." Noûs (1975): 309-318. * Samuel Levey (2011) "Logical theory in Leibniz" in Brandon C. Look (ed.) ''The Continuum Companion to Leibniz'', Continuum International Publishing Group,


External links

* {{cite SEP , url-id=plural-quant , title=Plural quantification , last=Linnebo , first=Øystein * Moltmann, Friederike. (August 2012)
Plural Reference and Reference to a Plurality. A Reassessment of the Linguistic Facts


* https://web.archive.org/web/20150211224457/http://lumiere.ens.fr/~amari/genius/PapersSeminar/Nicolas-Semantics-for-plurals-Handout-0110.pdf Quantifier (logic)