Peirce's Law
   HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
logic Logic is the study of correct reasoning. It includes both formal and informal logic. Formal logic is the study of deductively valid inferences or logical truths. It examines how conclusions follow from premises based on the structure o ...
, Peirce's law is named after the
philosopher Philosophy ('love of wisdom' in Ancient Greek) is a systematic study of general and fundamental questions concerning topics like existence, reason, knowledge, Value (ethics and social sciences), value, mind, and language. It is a rational an ...
and
logician Logic is the study of correct reasoning. It includes both formal and informal logic. Formal logic is the study of deductively valid inferences or logical truths. It examines how conclusions follow from premises based on the structure of arg ...
Charles Sanders Peirce Charles Sanders Peirce ( ; September 10, 1839 – April 19, 1914) was an American scientist, mathematician, logician, and philosopher who is sometimes known as "the father of pragmatism". According to philosopher Paul Weiss (philosopher), Paul ...
. It was taken as an
axiom An axiom, postulate, or assumption is a statement that is taken to be true, to serve as a premise or starting point for further reasoning and arguments. The word comes from the Ancient Greek word (), meaning 'that which is thought worthy or ...
in his first axiomatisation of
propositional logic The propositional calculus is a branch of logic. It is also called propositional logic, statement logic, sentential calculus, sentential logic, or sometimes zeroth-order logic. Sometimes, it is called ''first-order'' propositional logic to contra ...
. It can be thought of as the
law of excluded middle In logic, the law of excluded middle or the principle of excluded middle states that for every proposition, either this proposition or its negation is true. It is one of the three laws of thought, along with the law of noncontradiction and t ...
written in a form that involves only one sort of connective, namely implication. In
propositional calculus The propositional calculus is a branch of logic. It is also called propositional logic, statement logic, sentential calculus, sentential logic, or sometimes zeroth-order logic. Sometimes, it is called ''first-order'' propositional logic to contra ...
, Peirce's law says that ((''P''→''Q'')→''P'')→''P''. Written out, this means that ''P'' must be true if there is a proposition ''Q'' such that the truth of ''P'' follows from the truth of "if ''P'' then ''Q''". Peirce's law does not hold in
intuitionistic logic Intuitionistic logic, sometimes more generally called constructive logic, refers to systems of symbolic logic that differ from the systems used for classical logic by more closely mirroring the notion of constructive proof. In particular, systems ...
or
intermediate logic In mathematical logic, a superintuitionistic logic is a propositional logic extending intuitionistic logic. Classical logic is the strongest consistent superintuitionistic logic; thus, consistent superintuitionistic logics are called intermediate ...
s and cannot be deduced from the
deduction theorem In mathematical logic, a deduction theorem is a metatheorem that justifies doing conditional proofs from a hypothesis in systems that do not explicitly axiomatize that hypothesis, i.e. to prove an implication A \to B, it is sufficient to assume A ...
alone. Under the Curry–Howard isomorphism, Peirce's law is the type of
continuation In computer science, a continuation is an abstract representation of the control state of a computer program. A continuation implements ( reifies) the program control state, i.e. the continuation is a data structure that represents the computat ...
operators, e.g. call/cc in Scheme.Timothy G. Griffin, A Formulae-as-Types Notion of Control, 1990
- Griffin defines K on page 3 as an equivalent to Scheme's call/cc and then discusses its type being the equivalent of Peirce's law at the end of section 5 on page 9.


History

Here is Peirce's own statement of the law: : A ''fifth icon'' is required for the principle of
excluded middle In logic, the law of excluded middle or the principle of excluded middle states that for every proposition, either this proposition or its negation is true. It is one of the three laws of thought, along with the law of noncontradiction and th ...
and other propositions connected with it. One of the simplest formulae of this kind is: : This is hardly axiomatical. That it is true appears as follows. It can only be false by the final consequent ''x'' being false while its antecedent (''x'' ⤙ ''y'') ⤙ ''x'' is true. If this is true, either its consequent, ''x'', is true, when the whole formula would be true, or its antecedent ''x'' ⤙ ''y'' is false. But in the last case the antecedent of ''x'' ⤙ ''y'', that is ''x'', must be true. (Peirce, the ''Collected Papers'' 3.384). Peirce goes on to point out an immediate application of the law: : From the formula just given, we at once get: : where the ''a'' is used in such a sense that (''x'' ⤙ ''y'') ⤙ ''a'' means that from (''x'' ⤙ ''y'') every proposition follows. With that understanding, the formula states the principle of excluded middle, that from the falsity of the denial of ''x'' follows the truth of ''x''. (Peirce, the ''Collected Papers'' 3.384). Warning: As explained in the text, "''a''" here does not denote a propositional atom, but something like the quantified propositional formula \forall p\,p. The formula would not be a tautology if ''a'' were interpreted as an atom.


Relations between principles

In intuitionistic logic, if P is proven or rejected, or if Q is proven valid, then Peirce's law for the two propositions holds. But the law's special case when Q is rejected, called consequentia mirabilis, is equivalent to excluded middle already over minimal logic. This also means that Piece's law entails classical logic over intuitionistic logic. This is shown below. Firstly, from P\to Q follows the equivalence P\leftrightarrow(P\land Q), and so (P\to Q)\to P is equivalent to (P\to Q)\to (P\land Q). With this, one can also establish Peirce's law by establishing the equivalent form ((P\to Q)\to(P\land Q))\to P. Considering the case Q=\bot likewise also shows how double-negation elimination \neg \neg P\to P implies consequentia mirabilis, and this direction even only uses minimal logic. Now in intuitionistic logic, explosion can be used for \bot\to(P\land\bot), and so here consequentia mirabilis also implies double-negation elimination. As the double-negated excluded middle is always already valid even in minimal logic, it thus further also implies excluded middle, over intuitionistic logic. In the other direction, one can intuitionistically also show that excluded middle implies the full Peirce's law directly. To this end, note that using the
principle of explosion In classical logic, intuitionistic logic, and similar logical systems, the principle of explosion is the law according to which any statement can be proven from a contradiction. That is, from a contradiction, any proposition (including its n ...
, excluded middle may be expressed as P\lor (P\to Q). In words, this may be expressed as: "Every proposition P either holds or implies any other proposition." Now to prove the law, note that (P\lor R)\to((R\to P)\to P) is derivable from just implication introduction on the one hand and
modus ponens In propositional logic, (; MP), also known as (), implication elimination, or affirming the antecedent, is a deductive argument form and rule of inference. It can be summarized as "''P'' implies ''Q.'' ''P'' is true. Therefore, ''Q'' must ...
on the other. Finally, in place of R consider P\to Q. Another proof of the law in classical logic proceeds by passing through the classically valid reverse
disjunctive syllogism In classical logic, disjunctive syllogism (historically known as ''modus tollendo ponens'' (MTP), Latin for "mode that affirms by denying") is a valid argument form which is a syllogism having a disjunctive statement for one of its premises. ...
twice: First note that \neg\neg P is implied by (\neg\neg P \land \neg Q) \lor P, which is intuitionistically equivalent to \neg(\neg P \lor Q) \lor P. Now explosion entails that \neg A \lor B implies A \to B, and using excluded middle for A here entails that these two are in fact equivalent. Taken together, this means that in classical logic P is equivalent to (P \to Q)\to P. Intuitionistically, not even the constraint \neg Q\to P always implies Pierce's law for two propositions. Postulating the latter to be valid in its propositional form results in Smetanich's intermediate logic.


Using Peirce's law with the deduction theorem

Peirce's law allows one to enhance the technique of using the
deduction theorem In mathematical logic, a deduction theorem is a metatheorem that justifies doing conditional proofs from a hypothesis in systems that do not explicitly axiomatize that hypothesis, i.e. to prove an implication A \to B, it is sufficient to assume A ...
to prove theorems. Suppose one is given a set of premises Γ and one wants to deduce a proposition ''Z'' from them. With Peirce's law, one can add (at no cost) additional premises of the form ''Z''→''P'' to Γ. For example, suppose we are given ''P''→''Z'' and (''P''→''Q'')→''Z'' and we wish to deduce ''Z'' so that we can use the deduction theorem to conclude that (''P''→''Z'')→(((''P''→''Q'')→''Z'')→''Z'') is a theorem. Then we can add another premise ''Z''→''Q''. From that and ''P''→''Z'', we get ''P''→''Q''. Then we apply modus ponens with (''P''→''Q'')→''Z'' as the major premise to get ''Z''. Applying the deduction theorem, we get that (''Z''→''Q'')→''Z'' follows from the original premises. Then we use Peirce's law in the form ((''Z''→''Q'')→''Z'')→''Z'' and modus ponens to derive ''Z'' from the original premises. Then we can finish off proving the theorem as we originally intended.


Completeness of the implicational propositional calculus

One reason that Peirce's law is important is that it can substitute for the law of excluded middle in the logic which only uses implication. The sentences which can be deduced from the axiom schemas: * ''P''→(''Q''→''P'') * (''P''→(''Q''→''R''))→((''P''→''Q'')→(''P''→''R'')) * ((''P''→''Q'')→''P'')→''P'' * from ''P'' and ''P''→''Q'' infer ''Q'' (where ''P'',''Q'',''R'' contain only "→" as a connective) are all the tautologies which use only "→" as a connective.


Failure in non-classical models of intuitionistic logic

Since Peirce's law implies the law of the excluded middle, it must always fail in non-classical intuitionistic logics. A simple explicit counterexample is that of Gödel many valued logics, which are a
fuzzy logic Fuzzy logic is a form of many-valued logic in which the truth value of variables may be any real number between 0 and 1. It is employed to handle the concept of partial truth, where the truth value may range between completely true and completely ...
where truth values are real numbers between 0 and 1, with material implication defined by: : \begin u \mathrel v &= \begin 1, & \textu \leq v \\ v, & \textu > v \end \end and where Peirce's law as a formula can be simplified to: : \begin ((u \mathrel v) \mathrel u) \mathrel u &= \begin 1, & \textu \leq v \\ u, & \textu > v \end \end{align} where it always being true would be equivalent to the statement that u > v implies u = 1, which is true only if 0 and 1 are the only allowed values. At the same time however, the expression cannot ever be equal to the bottom truth value of the logic and its double negation is always true.


See also

*
Charles Sanders Peirce bibliography This Charles Sanders Peirce bibliography consolidates numerous references to the writings of Charles Sanders Peirce, including letters, manuscripts, publications, and . For an extensive chronological list of Peirce's works (titled in English), se ...


Notes


Further reading

* Peirce, C.S., "On the Algebra of Logic: A Contribution to the Philosophy of Notation", ''American Journal of Mathematics'' 7, 180–202 (1885). Reprinted, the ''Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce'' 3.359–403 and the ''Writings of Charles S. Peirce: A Chronological Edition'' 5, 162–190. * Peirce, C.S., ''Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce'', Vols. 1–6, Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss (eds.), Vols. 7–8, Arthur W. Burks (ed.), Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1931–1935, 1958. Mathematical logic Charles Sanders Peirce Theorems in propositional logic Intuitionism