In
mathematics
Mathematics is a field of study that discovers and organizes methods, Mathematical theory, theories and theorems that are developed and Mathematical proof, proved for the needs of empirical sciences and mathematics itself. There are many ar ...
, a measurable cardinal is a certain kind of
large cardinal
In the mathematical field of set theory, a large cardinal property is a certain kind of property of transfinite cardinal numbers. Cardinals with such properties are, as the name suggests, generally very "large" (for example, bigger than the least ...
number. In order to define the concept, one introduces a two-valued
measure on a cardinal ''κ'', or more generally on any set. For a cardinal ''κ'', it can be described as a subdivision of all of its
subset
In mathematics, a Set (mathematics), set ''A'' is a subset of a set ''B'' if all Element (mathematics), elements of ''A'' are also elements of ''B''; ''B'' is then a superset of ''A''. It is possible for ''A'' and ''B'' to be equal; if they a ...
s into large and small sets such that ''κ'' itself is large, ∅ and all
singletons (with ''α'' ∈ ''κ'') are small,
complements of small sets are large and vice versa. The
intersection
In mathematics, the intersection of two or more objects is another object consisting of everything that is contained in all of the objects simultaneously. For example, in Euclidean geometry, when two lines in a plane are not parallel, their ...
of fewer than ''κ'' large sets is again large.
It turns out that
uncountable
In mathematics, an uncountable set, informally, is an infinite set that contains too many elements to be countable. The uncountability of a set is closely related to its cardinal number: a set is uncountable if its cardinal number is larger tha ...
cardinals endowed with a two-valued measure are large cardinals whose existence cannot be proved from
ZFC.
The concept of a measurable cardinal was introduced by
Stanisław Ulam
Stanisław Marcin Ulam ( ; 13 April 1909 – 13 May 1984) was a Polish and American mathematician, nuclear physicist and computer scientist. He participated in the Manhattan Project, originated the History of the Teller–Ulam design, Telle ...
in 1930.
Definition
Formally, a measurable cardinal is an uncountable
cardinal number
In mathematics, a cardinal number, or cardinal for short, is what is commonly called the number of elements of a set. In the case of a finite set, its cardinal number, or cardinality is therefore a natural number. For dealing with the cas ...
''κ'' such that there exists a ''κ''-additive, non-trivial, 0-1-valued
measure ''μ'' on the
power set
In mathematics, the power set (or powerset) of a set is the set of all subsets of , including the empty set and itself. In axiomatic set theory (as developed, for example, in the ZFC axioms), the existence of the power set of any set is po ...
of ''κ.''
Here, κ-additive means: For every ''λ'' < ''κ'' and every ''λ''-sized set
''β''<''λ'' of pairwise disjoint subsets ''A''
''β'' ⊆ ''κ,'' we have
:''μ''(⋃
''β''<''λ'' ''A''
''β'') = Σ
''β''<''λ'' ''μ''(''A''
''β'').
Equivalently, ''κ'' is a measurable cardinal if and only if it is an uncountable cardinal with a ''κ''-complete, non-principal
ultrafilter
In the Mathematics, mathematical field of order theory, an ultrafilter on a given partially ordered set (or "poset") P is a certain subset of P, namely a Maximal element, maximal Filter (mathematics), filter on P; that is, a proper filter on P th ...
. This means that the intersection of any ''strictly less than'' ''κ''-many sets in the ultrafilter, is also in the ultrafilter.
Equivalently, ''κ'' is measurable means that it is the
critical point of a non-trivial
elementary embedding
In model theory, a branch of mathematical logic, two structures ''M'' and ''N'' of the same signature ''σ'' are called elementarily equivalent if they satisfy the same first-order ''σ''-sentences.
If ''N'' is a substructure of ''M'', one oft ...
of the
universe
The universe is all of space and time and their contents. It comprises all of existence, any fundamental interaction, physical process and physical constant, and therefore all forms of matter and energy, and the structures they form, from s ...
''V'' into a
transitive class ''M''. This equivalence is due to
Jerome Keisler and
Dana Scott
Dana Stewart Scott (born October 11, 1932) is an American logician who is the emeritus Hillman University Professor of Computer Science, Philosophy, and Mathematical Logic at Carnegie Mellon University; he is now retired and lives in Berkeley, C ...
, and uses the
ultrapower
The ultraproduct is a mathematical construction that appears mainly in abstract algebra and mathematical logic, in particular in model theory and set theory. An ultraproduct is a quotient of the direct product of a family of structures. All fact ...
construction from
model theory
In mathematical logic, model theory is the study of the relationship between theory (mathematical logic), formal theories (a collection of Sentence (mathematical logic), sentences in a formal language expressing statements about a Structure (mat ...
. Since ''V'' is a
proper class
Proper may refer to:
Mathematics
* Proper map, in topology, a property of continuous function between topological spaces, if inverse images of compact subsets are compact
* Proper morphism, in algebraic geometry, an analogue of a proper map f ...
, a technical problem that is not usually present when considering ultrapowers needs to be addressed, by what is now called
Scott's trick
In set theory, Scott's trick is a method for giving a definition of equivalence classes for equivalence relations on a proper class (Jech 2003:65) by referring to levels of the cumulative hierarchy.
The method relies on the axiom of regularity bu ...
.
Properties
It is trivial to note that if ''κ'' admits a non-trivial ''κ''-additive measure, then ''κ'' must be
regular. (By non-triviality and ''κ''-additivity, any subset of cardinality less than ''κ'' must have measure 0, and then by ''κ''-additivity again, this means that the entire set must not be a union of fewer than ''κ'' sets of cardinality less than ''κ.'') Finally, if ''λ'' < ''κ,'' then it can't be the case that ''κ'' ≤ 2
''λ''. If this were the case, we could identify ''κ'' with some collection of 0-1 sequences of length ''λ.'' For each position in the sequence, either the subset of sequences with 1 in that position or the subset with 0 in that position would have to have measure 1. The intersection of these ''λ''-many measure 1 subsets would thus also have to have measure 1, but it would contain exactly one sequence, which would contradict the non-triviality of the measure. Thus, assuming the Axiom of Choice, we can infer that ''κ'' is a
strong limit cardinal
In mathematics, limit cardinals are certain cardinal numbers. A cardinal number ''λ'' is a weak limit cardinal if ''λ'' is neither a successor cardinal nor zero. This means that one cannot "reach" ''λ'' from another cardinal by repeated success ...
, which completes the proof of its
inaccessibility.
Although it follows from
ZFC that every measurable cardinal is
inaccessible
Inaccessible Island is a volcanic island located in the South Atlantic Ocean, south-west of Tristan da Cunha. Its highest point, Swale's Fell, reaches , and the island is in area. The volcano was last active approximately one million years a ...
(and is
ineffable,
Ramsey, etc.), it is consistent with
ZF that a measurable cardinal can be a
successor cardinal In set theory, one can define a successor operation on cardinal numbers in a similar way to the successor operation on the ordinal numbers. The cardinal successor coincides with the ordinal successor for finite cardinals, but in the infinite case th ...
. It follows from ZF +
AD that ω
1 is measurable,
[T. Jech,]
The Brave New World of Determinacy
(PDF download). Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society, vol. 5, number 3, November 1981 (pp.339--349). and that every subset of ω
1 contains or is disjoint from a
closed and unbounded subset.
Ulam showed that the smallest cardinal ''κ'' that admits a non-trivial countably-additive two-valued measure must in fact admit a ''κ''-additive measure. (If there were some collection of fewer than ''κ'' measure-0 subsets whose union was ''κ,'' then the induced measure on this collection would be a counterexample to the minimality of ''κ.'') From there, one can prove (with the Axiom of Choice) that the least such cardinal must be inaccessible.
If ''κ'' is measurable and ''p'' ∈ ''V''
''κ'' and ''M'' (the ultrapower of ''V'') satisfies ''ψ''(''κ, p''), then the set of ''α'' < ''κ'' such that ''V'' satisfies ''ψ''(''α, p'') is stationary in ''κ'' (actually a set of measure 1). In particular if ''ψ'' is a Π
1 formula and ''V'' satisfies ''ψ''(''κ, p''), then ''M'' satisfies it and thus ''V'' satisfies ''ψ''(''α, p'') for a stationary set of ''α'' < ''κ.'' This property can be used to show that ''κ'' is a limit of most types of large cardinals that are weaker than measurable. Notice that the ultrafilter or measure witnessing that ''κ'' is measurable cannot be in ''M'' since the smallest such measurable cardinal would have to have another such below it, which is impossible.
If one starts with an elementary embedding ''j''
1 of ''V'' into ''M''
1 with
critical point ''κ,'' then one can define an ultrafilter ''U'' on ''κ'' as . Then taking an ultrapower of ''V'' over ''U'' we can get another elementary embedding ''j''
2 of ''V'' into ''M''
2. However, it is important to remember that ''j''
2 ≠ ''j''
1. Thus other types of large cardinals such as
strong cardinals may also be measurable, but not using the same embedding. It can be shown that a strong cardinal ''κ'' is measurable and also has ''κ''-many measurable cardinals below it.
Every measurable cardinal ''κ'' is a 0-
huge cardinal In mathematics, a cardinal number \kappa is called huge if there exists an elementary embedding j : V \to M from V into a transitive inner model M with critical point \kappa and
:^M \subset M.
Here, ^\alpha M is the class of all sequences of leng ...
because
''κ''''M'' ⊆ ''M'', that is, every function from ''κ'' to ''M'' is in ''M''. Consequently, ''V''
''κ''+1 ⊆ ''M''.
Implications of existence
If a measurable cardinal exists, every Σ (with respect to the
analytical hierarchy
Analytic or analytical may refer to:
Chemistry
* Analytical chemistry, the analysis of material samples to learn their chemical composition and structure
* Analytical technique, a method that is used to determine the concentration of a chemica ...
) set of reals has a
Lebesgue measure
In measure theory, a branch of mathematics, the Lebesgue measure, named after French mathematician Henri Lebesgue, is the standard way of assigning a measure to subsets of higher dimensional Euclidean '-spaces. For lower dimensions or , it c ...
.
In particular, any
non-measurable set
In mathematics, a non-measurable set is a set which cannot be assigned a meaningful "volume". The existence of such sets is construed to provide information about the notions of length, area and volume in formal set theory. In Zermelo–Fraenke ...
of reals must not be Σ.
Real-valued measurable
A cardinal ''κ'' is called real-valued measurable if there is a ''κ''-additive
probability measure
In mathematics, a probability measure is a real-valued function defined on a set of events in a σ-algebra that satisfies Measure (mathematics), measure properties such as ''countable additivity''. The difference between a probability measure an ...
on the power set of ''κ'' that vanishes on singletons. Real-valued measurable cardinals were introduced by . showed that the
continuum hypothesis
In mathematics, specifically set theory, the continuum hypothesis (abbreviated CH) is a hypothesis about the possible sizes of infinite sets. It states:
Or equivalently:
In Zermelo–Fraenkel set theory with the axiom of choice (ZFC), this ...
implies that 𝔠 is not real-valued measurable. showed (see below for parts of Ulam's proof) that real valued measurable cardinals are weakly inaccessible (they are in fact
weakly Mahlo). All measurable cardinals are real-valued measurable, and a real-valued measurable cardinal ''κ'' is measurable if and only if ''κ'' is greater than 𝔠. Thus a cardinal is measurable if and only if it is real-valued measurable and strongly inaccessible. A real valued measurable cardinal less than or equal to 𝔠 exists if and only if there is a
countably additive extension of the
Lebesgue measure
In measure theory, a branch of mathematics, the Lebesgue measure, named after French mathematician Henri Lebesgue, is the standard way of assigning a measure to subsets of higher dimensional Euclidean '-spaces. For lower dimensions or , it c ...
to all sets of real numbers if and only if there is an
atomless probability measure on the power set of some non-empty set.
showed that existence of measurable cardinals in ZFC, real-valued measurable cardinals in ZFC, and measurable cardinals in ZF, are
equiconsistent
In mathematical logic, two theories are equiconsistent if the consistency of one theory implies the consistency of the other theory, and vice versa. In this case, they are, roughly speaking, "as consistent as each other".
In general, it is not p ...
.
Weak inaccessibility of real-valued measurable cardinals
Say that a cardinal number ''α'' is an ''Ulam number'' if
[The notion in the article ]Ulam number
In mathematics, the Ulam numbers comprise an integer sequence devised by and named after Stanislaw Ulam, who introduced it in 1964. The standard Ulam sequence (the (1, 2)-Ulam sequence) starts with ''U''1 = 1 and ''U''2 =&nbs ...
is different.
whenever
then
::if , ''X'', ≤ ''α'' then ''μ''(''X'') = 0.
Equivalently, a cardinal number ''α'' is an Ulam number if
whenever
# ''ν'' is an outer measure on a set ''Y,'' and ''F'' a set of pairwise disjoint subsets of ''Y,''
# ''ν''(⋃''F'') < ∞,
# ''ν''(''A'') = 0 for ''A'' ∈ ''F,''
# ⋃''G'' is ''ν''-measurable for every ''G'' ⊂ ''F,''
then
::if , ''F'', ≤ ''α'' then ''ν''(⋃''F'') = 0.
The smallest infinite cardinal
ℵ0 is an Ulam number. The class of Ulam numbers is closed under the
cardinal successor operation. If an infinite cardinal ''β'' has an immediate predecessor ''α'' that is an Ulam number, assume ''μ'' satisfies properties ()–() with ''X'' = ''β.'' In the
von Neumann model
The von Neumann architecture—also known as the von Neumann model or Princeton architecture—is a computer architecture based on the ''First Draft of a Report on the EDVAC'', written by John von Neumann in 1945, describing designs discuss ...
of ordinals and cardinals, for each ''x'' ∈ ''β'', choose an
injective function
In mathematics, an injective function (also known as injection, or one-to-one function ) is a function that maps distinct elements of its domain to distinct elements of its codomain; that is, implies (equivalently by contraposition, impl ...
:''f''
''x'': ''x'' → ''α''
and define the sets
:''U''(''b, a'') =
Since the ''f''
''x'' are one-to-one, the sets
: with ''a'' ∈ ''α'' fixed
: with ''b'' ∈ ''β'' fixed
are pairwise disjoint. By property () of ''μ,'' the set
:
is
countable
In mathematics, a Set (mathematics), set is countable if either it is finite set, finite or it can be made in one to one correspondence with the set of natural numbers. Equivalently, a set is ''countable'' if there exists an injective function fro ...
, and hence
:, , ≤ ℵ
0⋅''α.''
Thus there is a ''b''
0 such that
:''μ''(''U''(''b''
0, ''a'')) = 0 for every ''a'' ∈ ''α''
implying, since ''α'' is an Ulam number and using the second definition (with ''ν'' = ''μ'' and conditions ()–() fulfilled),
:''μ''(⋃
''a''∈''α'' ''U''(''b''
0, ''a'')) = 0.
If ''b''
0 < ''x'' < ''β'' and ''f''
x(''b''
0) = ''a''
''x'' then ''x'' ∈ ''U''(''b''
0, ''a''
''x''). Thus
:''β'' = b
0 ∪ ∪ ⋃
''a''∈''α'' ''U''(''b''
0, ''a'')
By property (), ''μ''() = 0, and since , ''b''
0, ≤ ''α'', by (), () and (), ''μ''(''b''
0) = 0. It follows that ''μ''(''β'') = 0. The conclusion is that ''β'' is an Ulam number.
There is a similar proof
that the supremum of a set ''S'' of Ulam numbers with , ''S'', an Ulam number is again a Ulam number. Together with the previous result, this implies that a cardinal that is not an Ulam number is
weakly inaccessible.
See also
*
Normal measure
*
Mitchell order
*
List of large cardinal properties
Notes
Citations
References
*.
*.
*.
*.
*.
*.
*. A copy of parts I and II of this article with corrections is available at th
author's web page
*.
*{{Citation , last1=Ulam , first1=Stanislaw , authorlink = Stanislaw Ulam, title=Zur Masstheorie in der allgemeinen Mengenlehre , url=https://eudml.org/doc/212487 , year=1930 , journal=
Fundamenta Mathematicae
''Fundamenta Mathematicae'' is a peer-reviewed scientific journal of mathematics with a special focus on the foundations of mathematics, concentrating on set theory, mathematical logic, topology and its interactions with algebra, and dynamical sys ...
, issn=0016-2736 , volume=16 , pages=140–150, doi=10.4064/fm-16-1-140-150 , doi-access=free .
Large cardinals
Determinacy