HOME

TheInfoList



OR:

In
metalogic Metalogic is the metatheory of logic. Whereas ''logic'' studies how logical systems can be used to construct valid and sound arguments, metalogic studies the properties of logical systems. Logic concerns the truths that may be derived using a lo ...
and
metamathematics Metamathematics is the study of mathematics itself using mathematical methods. This study produces metatheory, metatheories, which are Mathematical theory, mathematical theories about other mathematical theories. Emphasis on metamathematics (and ...
, Frege's theorem is a
metatheorem In logic, a metatheorem is a statement about a formal system proven in a metalanguage. Unlike theorems proved within a given formal system, a metatheorem is proved within a metatheory, and may reference concepts that are present in the metatheo ...
that states that the Peano axioms of
arithmetic Arithmetic is an elementary branch of mathematics that deals with numerical operations like addition, subtraction, multiplication, and division. In a wider sense, it also includes exponentiation, extraction of roots, and taking logarithms. ...
can be derived in
second-order logic In logic and mathematics, second-order logic is an extension of first-order logic, which itself is an extension of propositional logic. Second-order logic is in turn extended by higher-order logic and type theory. First-order logic quantifies on ...
from
Hume's principle Hume's principle or HP says that, given two collections of objects \mathcal F and \mathcal G with properties F and G respectively, the number of objects with property F is equal to the number of objects with property G if and only if there is a ...
. It was first proven, informally, by
Gottlob Frege Friedrich Ludwig Gottlob Frege (; ; 8 November 1848 – 26 July 1925) was a German philosopher, logician, and mathematician. He was a mathematics professor at the University of Jena, and is understood by many to be the father of analytic philos ...
in his 1884 ''Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik'' ('' The Foundations of Arithmetic'')
Gottlob Frege Friedrich Ludwig Gottlob Frege (; ; 8 November 1848 – 26 July 1925) was a German philosopher, logician, and mathematician. He was a mathematics professor at the University of Jena, and is understood by many to be the father of analytic philos ...
, ''
Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik ''The Foundations of Arithmetic'' () is a book by Gottlob Frege, published in 1884, which investigates the Philosophy, philosophical foundations of arithmetic. Frege refutes other Idealism, idealist and Materialism, materialist theories of number ...
'', Breslau: Verlag von Wilhelm Koebner, 1884, §63.
and proven more formally in his 1893 ''Grundgesetze der Arithmetik'' I (''Basic Laws of Arithmetic'' I).
Gottlob Frege Friedrich Ludwig Gottlob Frege (; ; 8 November 1848 – 26 July 1925) was a German philosopher, logician, and mathematician. He was a mathematics professor at the University of Jena, and is understood by many to be the father of analytic philos ...
, ''Grundgesetze der Arithmetik'' I, Jena: Verlag Hermann Pohle, 1893, §§20 and 47.
The theorem was re-discovered by Crispin Wright in the early 1980s and has since been the focus of significant work. It is at the core of the
philosophy of mathematics Philosophy of mathematics is the branch of philosophy that deals with the nature of mathematics and its relationship to other areas of philosophy, particularly epistemology and metaphysics. Central questions posed include whether or not mathem ...
known as neo-logicism (at least of the Scottish School variety).


Overview

In '' The Foundations of Arithmetic'' (1884), and later, in ''Basic Laws of Arithmetic'' (vol. 1, 1893; vol. 2, 1903), Frege attempted to derive all of the laws of arithmetic from axioms he asserted as logical (see
logicism In the philosophy of mathematics, logicism is a programme comprising one or more of the theses that – for some coherent meaning of 'logic' – mathematics is an extension of logic, some or all of mathematics is reducible to logic, or some or al ...
). Most of these axioms were carried over from his ''
Begriffsschrift ''Begriffsschrift'' (German for, roughly, "concept-writing") is a book on logic by Gottlob Frege, published in 1879, and the formal system set out in that book. ''Begriffsschrift'' is usually translated as ''concept writing'' or ''concept notati ...
''; the one truly new principle was one he called the Basic Law V (now known as the axiom schema of unrestricted comprehension): the "value-range" of the function ''f''(''x'') is the same as the "value-range" of the function ''g''(''x'') if and only if ∀''x'' 'f''(''x'') = ''g''(''x'') However, not only did Basic Law V fail to be a logical proposition, but the resulting system proved to be inconsistent, because it was subject to
Russell's paradox In mathematical logic, Russell's paradox (also known as Russell's antinomy) is a set-theoretic paradox published by the British philosopher and mathematician, Bertrand Russell, in 1901. Russell's paradox shows that every set theory that contains ...
.. The inconsistency in Frege's ''Grundgesetze'' overshadowed Frege's achievement: according to
Edward Zalta Edward Nouri Zalta (; born March 16, 1952) is an American philosopher who is a senior research scholar at the Center for the Study of Language and Information at Stanford University. He received his Bachelor of Arts, BA from Rice University in 1 ...
, the ''Grundgesetze'' "contains all the essential steps of a valid proof (in
second-order logic In logic and mathematics, second-order logic is an extension of first-order logic, which itself is an extension of propositional logic. Second-order logic is in turn extended by higher-order logic and type theory. First-order logic quantifies on ...
) of the fundamental propositions of arithmetic from a single consistent principle." This achievement has become known as Frege's theorem.


Frege's theorem in propositional logic

In
propositional logic The propositional calculus is a branch of logic. It is also called propositional logic, statement logic, sentential calculus, sentential logic, or sometimes zeroth-order logic. Sometimes, it is called ''first-order'' propositional logic to contra ...
, Frege's theorem refers to this tautology: :\big(P\to(Q\to R)\big)\to\big((P\to Q)\to(P\to R)\big) The theorem already holds in one of the weakest logics imaginable, the constructive implicational calculus. The proof under the
Brouwer–Heyting–Kolmogorov interpretation In mathematical logic, the Brouwer–Heyting–Kolmogorov interpretation, or BHK interpretation, is an explanation of the meaning of proof in intuitionistic logic, proposed by L. E. J. Brouwer and Arend Heyting, and independently by Andrey Kolmogor ...
reads f \mapsto g\mapsto p\mapsto (f(p)\circ g)(p). In words: "Let ''f'' denote a reason that ''P'' implies that ''Q'' implies ''R''. And let ''g'' denote a reason that ''P'' implies ''Q''. Then given a ''f'', then given a ''g'', then given a reason ''p'' for ''P'', we know both that ''Q'' holds by ''g'' and that ''Q'' implies ''R'' holds by ''f''. So ''R'' holds." The
truth table A truth table is a mathematical table used in logic—specifically in connection with Boolean algebra, Boolean functions, and propositional calculus—which sets out the functional values of logical expressions on each of their functional arg ...
to the right gives a semantic proof. For all possible assignments of ''false'' () or ''true'' () to ''P'', ''Q'', and ''R'' (columns 1, 3, 5), each subformula is evaluated according to the rules for
material conditional The material conditional (also known as material implication) is a binary operation commonly used in logic. When the conditional symbol \to is interpreted as material implication, a formula P \to Q is true unless P is true and Q is false. M ...
, the result being shown below its main operator. Column 6 shows that the whole formula evaluates to ''true'' in every case, i.e. that it is a tautology. In fact, its antecedent (column 2) and its
consequent A consequent is the second half of a hypothetical proposition. In the standard form of such a proposition, it is the part that follows "then". In an implication, if ''P'' implies ''Q'', then ''P'' is called the antecedent and ''Q'' is called t ...
(column 10) are even equivalent.


Special cases

One commonly takes \neg P to mean P\to\bot, where \bot denotes a false proposition. With \bot for R, the theorem entails the curried form of the negation introduction principle, :\big((P\to \neg Q\big)\land (P\to Q)\big) \to \neg P


Notes


References

* * &ndash
Edition
in modern notation * &ndash
Edition
in modern notation {{DEFAULTSORT:Frege's Theorem Theorems in the foundations of mathematics Theorems in propositional logic Metatheorems