In
philosophy of logic, defeasible reasoning is a kind of provisional
reasoning that is rationally compelling, though not
deductively valid.
It usually occurs when a rule is given, but there may be specific exceptions to the rule, or subclasses that are subject to a different rule. Defeasibility is found in literatures that are concerned with
argument
An argument is a series of sentences, statements, or propositions some of which are called premises and one is the conclusion. The purpose of an argument is to give reasons for one's conclusion via justification, explanation, and/or persu ...
and the process of argument, or
heuristic reasoning.
Defeasible reasoning is a particular kind of non-demonstrative reasoning, where the reasoning does not produce a full, complete, or final demonstration of a claim, i.e., where fallibility and corrigibility of a conclusion are acknowledged. In other words, defeasible reasoning produces a
contingent statement or claim. Defeasible reasoning is also a kind of
ampliative Ampliative (from Latin ''ampliare'', "to enlarge"), a term used mainly in logic, meaning "extending" or "adding to that which is already known".
This terminology was often used by medieval logicians in the analyses of the temporal content of the ...
reasoning because its conclusions reach beyond the pure meanings of the premises.
Defeasible reasoning finds its fullest expression in
jurisprudence,
ethics
Ethics is the philosophy, philosophical study of Morality, moral phenomena. Also called moral philosophy, it investigates Normativity, normative questions about what people ought to do or which behavior is morally right. Its main branches inclu ...
and
moral philosophy,
epistemology
Epistemology is the branch of philosophy that examines the nature, origin, and limits of knowledge. Also called "the theory of knowledge", it explores different types of knowledge, such as propositional knowledge about facts, practical knowle ...
,
pragmatics
In linguistics and the philosophy of language, pragmatics is the study of how Context (linguistics), context contributes to meaning. The field of study evaluates how human language is utilized in social interactions, as well as the relationship ...
and conversational
conventions in
linguistics
Linguistics is the scientific study of language. The areas of linguistic analysis are syntax (rules governing the structure of sentences), semantics (meaning), Morphology (linguistics), morphology (structure of words), phonetics (speech sounds ...
,
constructivist decision theories, and in
knowledge representation
Knowledge representation (KR) aims to model information in a structured manner to formally represent it as knowledge in knowledge-based systems whereas knowledge representation and reasoning (KRR, KR&R, or KR²) also aims to understand, reason, and ...
and
planning in
artificial intelligence
Artificial intelligence (AI) is the capability of computer, computational systems to perform tasks typically associated with human intelligence, such as learning, reasoning, problem-solving, perception, and decision-making. It is a field of re ...
. It is also closely identified with
prima facie (presumptive) reasoning (i.e., reasoning on the "face" of evidence), and
ceteris paribus (default) reasoning (i.e., reasoning, all things "being equal").
According to at least some schools of philosophy, ''all'' reasoning is at most defeasible, and there is no such thing as absolutely certain deductive reasoning, since it is impossible to be absolutely certain of all the facts, or to know with certainty that nothing is unknown. Thus all deductive reasoning is in reality contingent and defeasible.
Other kinds of non-demonstrative reasoning
Other kinds of non-demonstrative reasoning are
probabilistic reasoning,
inductive reasoning
Inductive reasoning refers to a variety of method of reasoning, methods of reasoning in which the conclusion of an argument is supported not with deductive certainty, but with some degree of probability. Unlike Deductive reasoning, ''deductive'' ...
,
statistical reasoning,
abductive reasoning
Abductive reasoning (also called abduction,For example: abductive inference, or retroduction) is a form of logical inference that seeks the simplest and most likely conclusion from a set of observations. It was formulated and advanced by Ameri ...
, and
paraconsistent reasoning.
The differences between these kinds of reasoning correspond to differences about the conditional that each kind of reasoning uses, and on what premise (or on what authority) the conditional is adopted:
* ''
Deductive'' (from meaning postulate or axiom): if ''p'' then ''q'' (equivalent to ''q'' or ''not-p'' in classical logic, not necessarily in other logics)
* ''Defeasible'' (from authority): if ''p'' then (defeasibly) ''q''
* ''
Probabilistic'' (from combinatorics and indifference): if ''p'' then (probably) ''q''
* ''
Statistical'' (from data and presumption): the frequency of ''q''s among ''p''s is high (or inference from a model fit to data); hence, (in the right context) if ''p'' then (probably) ''q''
* ''
Inductive'' (theory formation; from data, coherence, simplicity, and confirmation): (inducibly) "if ''p'' then ''q''"; hence, if ''p'' then (deducibly-but-revisably) ''q''
* ''
Abductive'' (from data and theory): ''p'' and ''q'' are correlated, and ''q'' is sufficient for ''p''; hence, if ''p'' then (abductively) ''q'' as cause
History
Though
Aristotle
Aristotle (; 384–322 BC) was an Ancient Greek philosophy, Ancient Greek philosopher and polymath. His writings cover a broad range of subjects spanning the natural sciences, philosophy, linguistics, economics, politics, psychology, a ...
differentiated the forms of reasoning that are valid for
logic
Logic is the study of correct reasoning. It includes both formal and informal logic. Formal logic is the study of deductively valid inferences or logical truths. It examines how conclusions follow from premises based on the structure o ...
and
philosophy
Philosophy ('love of wisdom' in Ancient Greek) is a systematic study of general and fundamental questions concerning topics like existence, reason, knowledge, Value (ethics and social sciences), value, mind, and language. It is a rational an ...
from the more general ones that are used in everyday life (see
dialectics and
rhetoric), 20th century philosophers mainly concentrated on deductive reasoning. At the end of the 19th century, logic texts would typically survey both demonstrative and non-demonstrative reasoning, often giving more space to the latter. However, after the blossoming of
mathematical logic
Mathematical logic is the study of Logic#Formal logic, formal logic within mathematics. Major subareas include model theory, proof theory, set theory, and recursion theory (also known as computability theory). Research in mathematical logic com ...
at the hands of
Bertrand Russell
Bertrand Arthur William Russell, 3rd Earl Russell, (18 May 1872 – 2 February 1970) was a British philosopher, logician, mathematician, and public intellectual. He had influence on mathematics, logic, set theory, and various areas of analytic ...
,
Alfred North Whitehead and
Willard Van Orman Quine, latter-20th century logic texts paid little attention to the non-deductive modes of inference.
There are several notable exceptions.
John Maynard Keynes wrote his dissertation on non-demonstrative reasoning, and influenced the thinking of
Ludwig Wittgenstein on this subject. Wittgenstein, in turn, had many admirers, including the
positivist legal scholar
H. L. A. Hart and the
speech act linguist
John L. Austin,
Stephen Toulmin and
Chaïm Perelman in rhetoric, the moral theorists
W. D. Ross and
C. L. Stevenson, and the
vagueness epistemologist/ontologist
Friedrich Waismann.
The etymology of ''defeasible'' usually refers to Middle English law of contracts, where a condition of defeasance is a clause that can invalidate or annul a contract or deed. Though ''defeat'', ''dominate'', ''defer'', ''defy'', ''deprecate'' and ''derogate'' are often used in the same contexts as ''defease,'' the verbs ''annul'' and ''invalidate'' (and ''nullify,'' ''overturn,'' ''rescind,'' ''vacate,'' ''repeal,'' ''void'', ''cancel'', ''countermand'', ''preempt'', etc.) are more properly correlated with the concept of defeasibility than those words beginning with the letter ''d''. Many dictionaries do contain the verb, ''to defease'' with past participle, ''defeased.''
Philosophers in moral theory and rhetoric had taken defeasibility largely for granted when American epistemologists rediscovered Wittgenstein's thinking on the subject: John Ladd,
Roderick Chisholm,
Roderick Firth,
Ernest Sosa
Ernest Sosa (; ; born June 17, 1940) is an American philosopher primarily interested in epistemology. Since 2007 he has been Board of Governors Professor of Philosophy at Rutgers University, but he spent most of his career at Brown University.
...
,
Robert Nozick, and
John L. Pollock all began writing with new conviction about how ''appearance as red'' was only a defeasible reason for believing something to be red. More importantly Wittgenstein's orientation toward
language-games (and away from
semantics
Semantics is the study of linguistic Meaning (philosophy), meaning. It examines what meaning is, how words get their meaning, and how the meaning of a complex expression depends on its parts. Part of this process involves the distinction betwee ...
) emboldened these epistemologists to manage rather than to expurgate ''prima facie'' logical inconsistency.
At the same time (in the mid-1960s), two more students of Hart and Austin at Oxford,
Brian Barry and
David Gauthier, were applying defeasible reasoning to political argument and practical reasoning (of action), respectively.
Joel Feinberg and
Joseph Raz were beginning to produce equally mature works in ethics and jurisprudence informed by defeasibility.
By far the most significant works on defeasibility by the mid-1970s were in epistemology, where
John Pollock's 1974 ''Knowledge and Justification'' popularized his terminology of ''undercutting'' and ''rebutting'' (which mirrored the analysis of Toulmin). Pollock's work was significant precisely because it brought defeasibility so close to philosophical logicians. The failure of logicians to dismiss defeasibility in epistemology (as Cambridge's logicians had done to Hart decades earlier) landed defeasible reasoning in the philosophical mainstream.
Defeasibility had always been closely related to argument, rhetoric, and law, except in epistemology, where the chains of reasons, and the origin of reasons, were not often discussed.
Nicholas Rescher's ''Dialectics'' is an example of how difficult it was for philosophers to contemplate more complex systems of defeasible reasoning. This was in part because proponents of
informal logic became the keepers of argument and rhetoric while insisting that formalism was anathema to argument.
About this time, researchers in
artificial intelligence
Artificial intelligence (AI) is the capability of computer, computational systems to perform tasks typically associated with human intelligence, such as learning, reasoning, problem-solving, perception, and decision-making. It is a field of re ...
became interested in
non-monotonic reasoning and its
semantics
Semantics is the study of linguistic Meaning (philosophy), meaning. It examines what meaning is, how words get their meaning, and how the meaning of a complex expression depends on its parts. Part of this process involves the distinction betwee ...
. With philosophers such as Pollock and Donald Nute (e.g.,
defeasible logic), dozens of computer scientists and logicians produced complex systems of defeasible reasoning between 1980 and 2000. No single system of defeasible reasoning would emerge in the same way that Quine's system of logic became a de facto standard. Nevertheless, the 100-year headstart on non-demonstrative logical calculi, due to
George Boole
George Boole ( ; 2 November 1815 – 8 December 1864) was a largely self-taught English mathematician, philosopher and logician, most of whose short career was spent as the first professor of mathematics at Queen's College, Cork in Ireland. H ...
,
Charles Sanders Peirce
Charles Sanders Peirce ( ; September 10, 1839 – April 19, 1914) was an American scientist, mathematician, logician, and philosopher who is sometimes known as "the father of pragmatism". According to philosopher Paul Weiss (philosopher), Paul ...
, and
Gottlob Frege
Friedrich Ludwig Gottlob Frege (; ; 8 November 1848 – 26 July 1925) was a German philosopher, logician, and mathematician. He was a mathematics professor at the University of Jena, and is understood by many to be the father of analytic philos ...
was being closed: both demonstrative and non-demonstrative reasoning now have formal calculi.
There are related (and slightly competing) systems of reasoning that are newer than systems of defeasible reasoning, e.g.,
belief revision and
dynamic logic. The dialogue logics of
Charles Hamblin and Jim Mackenzie, and their colleagues, can also be tied closely to defeasible reasoning. Belief revision is a non-constructive specification of the desiderata with which, or constraints according to which, epistemic change takes place. Dynamic logic is related mainly because, like paraconsistent logic, the reordering of premises can change the set of justified conclusions. Dialogue logics introduce an adversary, but are like belief revision theories in their adherence to deductively consistent states of belief.
Political and judicial use
Many political philosophers have been fond of the word ''indefeasible'' when referring to rights that were ''inalienable,'' ''divine,'' or ''indubitable''.
For instance, the 1776
Virginia Declaration of Rights notes "community hath an indubitable, inalienable, and indefeasible right to reform, alter or abolish government..." (also attributed to
James Madison); and
John Adams
John Adams (October 30, 1735 – July 4, 1826) was a Founding Fathers of the United States, Founding Father and the second president of the United States from 1797 to 1801. Before Presidency of John Adams, his presidency, he was a leader of ...
, "The people have a right, an indisputable, unalienable, indefeasible, divine right to that most dreaded and envied kind of knowledge – I mean of the character and conduct of their rulers." Also,
Lord Aberdeen: "indefeasible right inherent in the British Crown" and
Gouverneur Morris: "the Basis of our own Constitution is the indefeasible Right of the People." Scholarship about
Abraham Lincoln
Abraham Lincoln (February 12, 1809 – April 15, 1865) was the 16th president of the United States, serving from 1861 until Assassination of Abraham Lincoln, his assassination in 1865. He led the United States through the American Civil War ...
often cites these passages in the justification of secession.
Philosophers who use the word ''defeasible'' have historically had different world views from those who use the word ''indefeasible'' (and this distinction has often been mirrored by Oxford and Cambridge zeitgeist); hence it is rare to find authors who use both words.
In judicial opinions, the use of ''defeasible'' is commonplace. There is however disagreement among legal logicians whether ''defeasible reasoning'' is central, e.g., in the consideration of ''open texture'',
precedent,
exceptions, and ''rationales'', or whether it applies only to explicit defeasance clauses.
H.L.A. Hart in ''
The Concept of Law'' gives two famous examples of defeasibility: "No vehicles in the park" (except during parades); and "Offer, acceptance, and memorandum produce a contract" (except when the contract is illegal, the parties are minors, inebriated, or incapacitated, etc.).
Specificity
One of the main disputes among those who produce systems of defeasible reasoning is the status of a ''rule of specificity.'' In its simplest form, it is the same rule as subclass
inheritance
Inheritance is the practice of receiving private property, titles, debts, entitlements, privileges, rights, and obligations upon the death of an individual. The rules of inheritance differ among societies and have changed over time. Offi ...
preempting class inheritance:
(R1) if ''r'' then (defeasibly) ''q'' e.g., if bird, then can fly
(R2) if ''p'' then (defeasibly) ''not-q'' e.g., if penguin, then cannot fly
(O1) if ''p'' then (deductively) ''r'' e.g., if penguin, then bird
(M1) arguably, p e.g., arguably, penguin
(M2) R2 is a more specific reason than R1 e.g., R2 is better than R1
(M3) therefore, arguably, not-q e.g., therefore, arguably, cannot fly
Approximately half of the systems of defeasible reasoning discussed today adopt a rule of specificity, while half expect that such ''preference'' rules be written explicitly by whoever provides the defeasible reasons. For example, Rescher's dialectical system uses specificity, as do early systems of multiple inheritance (e.g.,
David Touretzky) and the early argument systems of Donald Nute and of
Guillermo Simari and
Ronald Loui. Defeasible reasoning accounts of precedent (
stare decisis and
case-based reasoning) also make use of specificity (e.g.,
Joseph Raz and the work of Kevin D. Ashley and
Edwina Rissland). Meanwhile, the argument systems of Henry Prakken and Giovanni Sartor, of Bart Verheij and Jaap Hage, and the system of Phan Minh Dung do not adopt such a rule.
Nature of defeasibility
There is a distinct difference between those who theorize about defeasible reasoning as if it were a system of confirmational revision (with affinities to
belief revision), and those who theorize about defeasibility as if it were the result of further (non-empirical) investigation. There are at least three kinds of further non-empirical investigation: progress in a lexical/syntactic process, progress in a computational process, and progress in an adversary or legal proceeding.
; Defeasibility as corrigibility : Here, a person learns something new that annuls a prior inference. In this case, defeasible reasoning provides a constructive mechanism for belief revision, like a
truth maintenance system as envisioned by Jon Doyle.
; Defeasibility as shorthand for preconditions : Here, the author of a set of rules or legislative code is writing rules with exceptions. Sometimes a set of defeasible rules can be rewritten, with more cogency, with explicit (local) pre-conditions instead of (non-local) competing rules. Many non-monotonic systems with
fixed-point or
preferential semantics fit this view. However, sometimes the rules govern a process of argument (the last view on this list), so that they cannot be re-compiled into a set of deductive rules lest they lose their force in situations with incomplete knowledge or incomplete derivation of preconditions.
; Defeasibility as an
anytime algorithm : Here, it is assumed that calculating arguments takes time, and at any given time, based on a subset of the potentially constructible arguments, a conclusion is defeasibly justified.
Isaac Levi has protested against this kind of defeasibility, but it is well-suited to the heuristic projects of, for example,
Herbert A. Simon. On this view, the ''best move so far'' in a chess-playing program's analysis at a particular depth is a defeasibly justified conclusion. This interpretation works with either the prior or the next semantical view.
; Defeasibility as a means of controlling an investigative or social process : Here, justification is the result of the right kind of procedure (e.g., a fair and efficient hearing), and defeasible reasoning provides impetus for pro and con responses to each other. Defeasibility has to do with the alternation of verdict as locutions are made and cases presented, not the changing of a mind with respect to new (empirical) discovery. Under this view, defeasible reasoning and defeasible argumentation refer to the same phenomenon.
See also
*
*
*
*
*
*
*
Defeater
References
Further reading
Defeasible logic Donald Nute, Lecture Notes in Computer Science, Springer, 2003.
Logical models of argument Carlos Chesnevar, et al., ACM Computing Surveys 32:4, 2000.
Logics for defeasible argumentation Henry Prakken and Gerard Vreeswijk, in Handbook of Philosophical Logic,
Dov M. Gabbay,
Franz Guenthner, eds., Kluwer, 2002.
Dialectics Nicholas Rescher, SUNY Press, 1977.
Defeasible reasoning John Pollock, Cognitive Science, 1987.
Knowledge and Justification John Pollock, Princeton University Press, 1974.
Hart's critics on defeasible concepts and ascriptivism Ronald Loui, Proc. 5th Intl. Conf. on AI and Law, 1995.
Political argument Brian Barry, Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1970.
The uses of argument Stephen Toulmin, Cambridge University Press, 1958.
Discourse relations and defeasible knowledge Alex Lascarides and Nicholas Asher, Proc. of the 29th Meeting of the Assn. for Comp. Ling., 1991.
Defeasible logic programming: an argumentative approach Alejandro Garcia and
Guillermo Simari, Theory and Practice of Logic Programming 4:95–138, 2004.
Philosophical foundations of deontic logic and the logic of defeasible conditionals Carlos Alchourron, in Deontic logic in computer science: normative system specification, J. Meyer, R. Wieringa, eds., Wiley, 1994.
A Mathematical Treatment of Defeasible Reasoning and its Implementation. Guillermo Simari,
Ronald Loui, Artificial Intelligence, 53(2–3): 125–157 (1992).
*
* {{cite journal , last=Hage , first=Jaap , year=2003 , title=Law and defeasibility , url=http://www.umiacs.umd.edu/~horty/courses/readings/hage-2003-defeasibility.pdf , journal=Artificial Intelligence and Law , volume=11 , issue=2/3 , pages=221–243 , doi=10.1023/B:ARTI.0000046011.13621.08 , s2cid=12271954 , access-date=6 June 2016
External links
Article on Defeasible Reasoningin the
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
The ''Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy'' (''SEP'') is a freely available online philosophy resource published and maintained by Stanford University, encompassing both an online encyclopedia of philosophy and peer-reviewed original publication ...
An example of defeasible reasoning in action
Belief revision
Concepts in logic
Logic programming
Reasoning
Philosophy of logic